Metz, Thaddeus. Meaning in Life: an Analytic Study

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Metz, Thaddeus. Meaning in Life: an Analytic Study [Expositions 9.1 (2015) 142–148] Expositions (online) ISSN: 1747–5376 Metz, Thaddeus. Meaning in Life: An Analytic Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. 288pp. $45.00 (cloth). ISBN: 978–0–199–59931–8 Questions about the meaning of life are among the deepest and most important questions humans can ask. Such questions include: Does the universe have any meaning or purpose? (The question of cosmic meaning.) Does my life have any meaning or purpose? (The question of individual meaning.) If my life does have some meaning or purpose, is that entirely up to me? Partially up to me? Or not up to me at all? Could it be—as existential nihilists claim—that life has no meaning whatsoever? If so, how should we respond to that complete lack of meaning? If life can have meaning, what forms do such meanings take, which modes of meaningfulness are most important, and how can I make my own life as meaningful as possible? These are deep questions because they force us to think about ultimate issues about the nature of reality and what our highest priorities in life should be. They are also important questions because the quest for meaning is one of the most fundamental and persistent drives in human nature. How we answer such questions may determine whether we live lives of happiness and purpose, or instead struggle with feelings of apathy, anomie, and despair. Over the past three decades, an extensive body of high-quality literature has developed in Anglo-American philosophy on the cluster of related issues collectively known as “the meaning of life.” One of the most significant participants in that discussion has been the South African philosopher, Thaddeus Metz. Metz’s Meaning in Life is an important contribution to the growing academic literature on the meaning of life. Over the past fifteen years, Metz has published prolifically in the field and is the author of a superb Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on the topic. Meaning in Life is mostly cobbled together from previously published articles, and shows it in places with certain oddities of emphasis and focus. Whatever one thinks about the particular conclusions Metz defends, the book unquestionably provides a helpful framework and vocabulary for thinking about the relevant issues. 143 Bassham Like most contemporary philosophers who write on the meaning of life, Metz focuses almost entirely on questions of individual meaning. Issues of “cosmic” or “holistic” meaning are addressed only to the extent that they directly impinge on questions of individual meaning. Metz’s book has three main parts. The first part seeks to clarify what we mean when we ask about the “meaning” of an individual human life. In Part II, he considers a number of supernaturalist theories of meaning, and in Part III he discusses two prominent naturalistic accounts of meaning: what he calls subjective naturalism and objective naturalism. He concludes with a critique of existential nihilism. Metz begins by unpacking the general concept of meaning and setting forth what he believes a theory of meaning must include. In his view, meaning is something that comes in degrees, varies from person to person, can be manifested in both the parts and in the whole of an individual’s life, is intrinsically desirable as an end in itself, is roughly synonymous with terms such as “significance” or “importance,” and is exemplified most saliently by certain kinds of intellectual excellence (think: Albert Einstein), moral achievement (think: Mother Teresa), and artistic creation (think: Pablo Picasso). Meaning should not be confused, he argues, with absurdity, which consists in a kind of conspicuous or ludicrous incongruity. Nor should meaning be confused with futility, which is roughly the idea of persistent failure to achieve one’s ends (6). More debatably, Metz argues that a meaningful life should not be identified with a happy life. Metz rightly notes that that there is nothing contradictory in speaking of a “happy but meaningless life,” or, conversely, of a “meaningful but unhappy life.” As examples of meaningless but happy lives, he cites (a) Nozick’s example of an intensely pleasure-filled life lived inside an experience machine1 and (b) Richard Taylor’s example of a drug-fueled Sisyphus joyously (but futilely) rolling a rock up a hill for all eternity.2 Plausibly, he takes such examples to show that meaning does not consist simply in pleasure or happiness. But Metz also argues for a stronger conclusion—that pleasure or happiness as such cannot even contribute to a meaningful life (27). As he sees it, a life of Sisyphean rock-rolling, however pleasurable or joyous, is a paradigm of absolute meaninglessness. It follows, therefore, that pleasure or happiness per se can contribute nothing to a meaningful life. This claim is implausible. As Richard Taylor famously argues (but later retracted (Metz 174– 75)), a joyous Sisyphean life of endlessly pointless rock-rolling would not, in fact, be a paradigm of complete meaninglessness. Rather, it would possess a kind of “subjective meaning” in virtue of the fact that Sisyphus finds it to be deeply meaningful, enjoyable, and fulfilling. Moreover, such a life may also possess a kind of objective meaning inasmuch as it involves at least two objective and intrinsic goods (happiness and pleasure). If, as many theorists claim, whatever has intrinsic value has at least some degree of meaningfulness, then (pace Metz) Sisyphus’s life does have at least some meaning, however minimal. Review of Meaning in Life 144 As Metz acknowledges, his view of the connection between meaning and happiness seems to commit him to the highly implausible claim that Taylor’s classic discussion of the meaning of life isn’t about “meaning” at all. Those theorists who speak of empty, objectively insignificant pleasures as contributing to meaningfulness are “conceptually confused,” Metz argues (30). In his view, nothing that belongs merely to our “animal self” can confer any meaning whatsoever (29– 30). What has gone wrong here? The fatal mistake, I suggest, is Metz’s virtual identification of “meaning” with the notions of “significance” or “importance” (see, e.g., 79). As Tom Morris argues, meaning has to do not only with significance or importance, but also, crucially, with the notions of purpose and value.3 Metz focuses unduly on one element of this triad, forcing him to draw counterintuitive conclusions at many points in his analysis. Having clarified what he takes to be the generic concept of individual (human) life-meaning, Metz turns next to consider the leading theories of meaningfulness in the academic literature. His principal focus is on the conditions that contribute to what we might term a highly or richly meaningful life. He says relatively little—directly at least—about such important issues as: a) Are there any human beings that lead (or could lead) completely meaningless lives? If so, why? What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for a life to have any meaning at all? b) Given that some activities (e.g., twiddling your thumbs) can be meaning-neutral, and other activities (cf. 64) can be meaning-subtractors (e.g., blowing up the Sphinx just for the fun of it), what are the necessary and sufficient conditions for a human life to “meaningful” on balance? Metz focuses on three main (families of) theories of what gives meaning to individual human lives: supernaturalism (roughly, the view that God, or something spiritual, gives meaning to life), subjective naturalism (roughly, the idea that individuals give their own lives meaning through their own freely-chosen values and commitments), and objective naturalism (the view that lives have meaning to the extent that they connect with important objective values, such as truth , goodness, beauty, etc.). (Confusingly, Metz classifies any naturalistic theory that allows for both subjective and objective modes of meaningfulness as an “objective” theory. It would be preferable to call these “mixed” theories.) Metz ultimately defends a version of objective naturalism. Briefly, Metz argues that subjective naturalism is untenable because it implies that utterly pointless and insignificant activities like joyous Sisyphean rock-rolling or Nozickian experience- machine pleasure-surfing would be meaningful, when in fact they are completely devoid of meaning. We have seen how this analysis might be challenged. Metz turns next to supernaturalist theories of meaning. His rich and complex eighty-page discussion of various supernaturalist theories of meaning cannot be summarized adequately here. One form of supernaturalism he scrutinizes in detail is what he calls “purpose theory.” According to purpose theory, God is absolutely necessary for any form of meaning, and the closer a person 145 Bassham comes to fulfilling the (collective or individualized) purpose God has assigned to her, the more meaningful her life is. Metz offers a mixed bag of objections against supernaturalist accounts of meaning. One plausible objection he gives is that, intuitively, some things can be meaningful even if nothing supernatural exists (144). For example, feeding a hungry child seems to have significance—and therefore meaning—even if we decide that there is no God or spiritual realm. Metz’s primary argument against supernaturalism is more questionable. Essentially, he argues that supernatural accounts of meaning depend on a conception of God that is ultimately incoherent. He argues that meaning can be wholly dependent on God only if God is an absolutely perfect being, and God can be an absolutely perfect being only if he is outside of time and completely unchangeable. But if God is wholly atemporal and immutable he presumably cannot do things like “choose” to create a universe or to “assign” individual life-purposes. Such activities, Metz argues, are possible only if God exists in time and can change (106–14). Here four things should be noted: 1.
Recommended publications
  • Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman
    17 Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman The Alpha Course, a well‐known evangelical Christian programme, advertises itself with posters displaying the words THE MEANING OF LIFE IS_________, followed by the invitation ‘Fill in the blanks at alpha.org’. Followers of the course will discover that ‘Men and women were created to live in a relationship with God’, and that ‘without that relationship there will always be a hunger, an emptiness, a feeling that something is missing’.1 We all have that need because we are all sinners, we are told, and the truth which will fill the need is that Jesus Christ died to save us from our sins. Not all Christian or other religious views about the meaning of life are as simplistic as this, but they typically share the assumptions that the meaning of life is to be found in some belief whose truth we need to recognize, and that this is a belief about the purpose for which we exist. A further implication is that this purpose is the purpose intended by the God who created us, and that if we fail to identify and live in accordance with that purpose, our lives will lack meaning. The assumption is echoed in the question many humanists will have encountered: if you don’t believe in a God, what’s the point of it all? And many people who don’t share the answer still accept the legitimacy of the question – ‘What is the meaning of life?’ – and assume that what we need is a correct belief, religious or non‐religious, which will fill the blank in the sentence ‘The meaning of life is …’.
    [Show full text]
  • Defending the Subjective Component of Susan Wolf's
    Defending the Subjective Component of Susan Wolf’s “Fitting Fulfillment View” About Meaning in Life. Andreas Hjälmarö Andreas Hjälmarö Kandidatuppsats Filosofi, 15 hp. Ht 2016 Handledare Frans Svensson Umeå Universitet, Umeå Table of content Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 3 1. Introduction ..................................................................................................................................... 4 2. Background ...................................................................................................................................... 5 2.1 The question .................................................................................................................................. 5 2.2 Common answers .......................................................................................................................... 8 The nihilistic view ............................................................................................................................ 8 The super-naturalistic view ............................................................................................................. 8 The naturalistic view ....................................................................................................................... 9 2.3 Wolf’s view – a combination ......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Search for Meaning of Life: Existentialism, Communication, and Islam
    The Search for 0eaning of Life: Existentialism, Communication, and ,slam 2. HasEiansyah ABSTRACT 0aNna merupaNan hal sangat penting dalam Nehidupan manusia. Tanpa maNna, Nehidupan aNan tanpa arah dan penuh Negelisahan. 0aNna hidup dapat dicari melalui nilai-nilai Nreatif, nilai-nilai pengalaman, nilai-nilai cara EersiNap, NomuniNasi dan partisipasi, pemahaman diri, dan pemahaman aNan aMaran agama. ,slam menawarNan aspeN nomatif Eagi pencapaian hidup EermaNn lewat pemEersihan diri, Nontemplasi, serta Nomitmen pada Neilmuan dan NemasyaraNatan. ,ntroduction was ever upset deeply, while he had a good posi- tion and future. He needed something else, that :e face our life every day. :e sleep, wake was a high meaningful life, which could make him up, eat, work, take part in communication, have a aEsolutely satisfied. He gave up all his position. rest, and so on. Events come to us and we pay Then, he was lost himself in a realm of mysticism attention to them, even involve ourselves in them, (tashawwuf). In this world, he felt a highest satis- or ignore them. In other cases, we need some- faction and a real significant life. thing, we seek it, we get it or not, then we feel At first glance it seems difficult to understand happy or sad. It takes place automatically and why, for instance, someone is very interested in routinely. :e are as though in a circle of situation. climEing up mountain, while another is pleased to However in reality, life is not as simple as that. contriEute most of his possession to others and Each of us is not always involved passively in a he chooses to lead an extremely soEer life.
    [Show full text]
  • The Three Meanings of Meaning in Life: Distinguishing Coherence, Purpose, and Significance
    The Journal of Positive Psychology Dedicated to furthering research and promoting good practice ISSN: 1743-9760 (Print) 1743-9779 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rpos20 The three meanings of meaning in life: Distinguishing coherence, purpose, and significance Frank Martela & Michael F. Steger To cite this article: Frank Martela & Michael F. Steger (2016) The three meanings of meaning in life: Distinguishing coherence, purpose, and significance, The Journal of Positive Psychology, 11:5, 531-545, DOI: 10.1080/17439760.2015.1137623 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2015.1137623 Published online: 27 Jan 2016. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 425 View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rpos20 Download by: [Colorado State University] Date: 06 July 2016, At: 11:55 The Journal of Positive Psychology, 2016 Vol. 11, No. 5, 531–545, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2015.1137623 The three meanings of meaning in life: Distinguishing coherence, purpose, and significance Frank Martelaa* and Michael F. Stegerb,c aFaculty of Theology, University of Helsinki, P.O. Box 4, Helsinki 00014, Finland; bDepartment of Psychology, Colorado State University, 1876 Campus Delivery, Fort Collins, CO 80523-1876, USA; cSchool of Behavioural Sciences, North-West University, Vanderbijlpark, South Africa (Received 25 June 2015; accepted 3 December 2015) Despite growing interest in meaning in life, many have voiced their concern over the conceptual refinement of the con- struct itself. Researchers seem to have two main ways to understand what meaning in life means: coherence and pur- pose, with a third way, significance, gaining increasing attention.
    [Show full text]
  • The No-Self View and the Meaning of Life Baptiste Le Bihan
    The No-Self View and the Meaning of Life Baptiste Le Bihan Philosophy East and West, Early Release Articles, (Article) Published by University of Hawai'i Press This is a preprint article. When the final version of this article launches, this URL will be automatically redirected. For additional information about this preprint article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/697321/summary Access provided by Universite de Geneve (7 Jun 2018 09:39 GMT) The No-Self View and the Meaning of Life Baptiste Le Bihan Department of philosophy, University of Geneva [email protected] I. Introduction Several philosophers, both in Buddhist philosophy (see e.g. Zahavi, Thompson, and Siderits 2011) and Western philosophy (Unger 1979a, 1979b, 1979c, Stone 2005) have claimed that the self does not exist. Such a claim may immediately be rejected because of the incredulous stares and the existential threatening it triggers. One might think that it is obvious that the self exists since one feels as though one does have a very direct access to one’s self. Or, alternatively, one may claim that if the self were to fail to exist then life would be meaningless–thereby perceiving the eliminativist claim as an existential threat. A lot has already been written about incredulous stares and the roles of experience-based intuitions in metaphysics (see for instance Korman 2009 and Benovsky 2015) so, within the scope of the paper, I shall only concern myself–so to speak–with the latter resistance, which has received far less attention. The no-self view (also called “eliminativism about the self”) might, intuitively, threaten not only our existence as a subject but also the very meaning of our lives.
    [Show full text]
  • What Does It Mean to Live a Fully Embodied Spiritual Life? Jorge N
    What Does It Mean to Live a Fully Embodied Spiritual Life? Jorge N. Ferrer1 California Institute of Integral Studies San Francisco, CA, USA This essay discusses the meaning of embodied spirituality—based on the integration of all human attributes, including the body and sexuality—and contrasts it with the disembodied spirituality—based on dissociation and/or sublimation—prevailing in human religious history. It then describes what it means to approach the body as a living partner with which to co-create one’s spiritual life, and outlines ten features of a fully embodied spirituality. The article concludes with some reflections about the past, present, and potential future of embodied spirituality. For in him the whole fullness of divinity dwells bodily. (Colossians 2:9) mbodied spirituality has become a buzzword in What Is Embodied Spirituality? contemporary spiritual circles, yet the concept n a way, the expression “embodied spirituality” can be has not been dealt with in a thorough manner. Irightfully seen as redundant and perhaps even hollow. EWhat do we really mean when we say that spirituality After all, is not all human spirituality “embodied” insofar is “embodied”? Is there a distinct understanding of the as it necessarily transpires in and through embodied body underlying this expression? What distinguishes men and women? Proponents of embodied spiritual “embodied” from “disembodied” spirituality in practice? practice, however, tell us that important trends of past What are the implications for spiritual practice and and present spiritualities are “disembodied.” But what spiritual goals—and for our very approach to spiritual does “disembodied” mean in this context? liberation—of taking embodiment seriously? In light of our spiritual history, I suggest that Before attempting to answer these questions, two “disembodied” does not denote that the body and caveats are in order.
    [Show full text]
  • God, the Meaning of Life, and a New Argument for Atheism
    Penultimate Draft. Please cite the version forthcoming in the International Journal for Philosophy of Religion. GOD, THE MEANING OF LIFE, AND A NEW ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Jason Megill and Daniel Linford ABSTRACT We raise various puzzles about the relationship between God (if God exists) and the meaning of life (if life has meaning). These difficulties suggest that, even if we assume that God exists, and even if (as we argue) God’s existence would entail that our lives have meaning, God is not and could not be the source of the meaning of life. We conclude by discussing implications of our ​ arguments: (i) these claims can be used in a novel argument for atheism; (ii) these claims undermine an extant argument for God’s existence; and (iii) they suggest that atheism is consistent with our lives having meaning. INTRODUCTION In the literature on the meaning of life over the last few decades, the “meaning of life” is generally taken to be some positive feature of an individual’s life that is distinct from (though perhaps related to) other positive features (wellbeing, happiness, etc.) that a life might or might not have. It is also typically thought that lives can have meaning to varying degrees, so e.g., one life might be more meaningful than another, or the same life might be more or less meaningful at different times. We follow these conventions.1 Some philosophers have endorsed the view that God is somehow the source of the meaning of life and moreover, God’s existence is necessary for life to have meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • Rudolf Eucken's Philsophy of Life
    RUDOLF EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHY OF LIFE BY W. R. BOYCE GIBSON LECTURER IN PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON LONDON ADAM AND CHARLES BLACK 1906 PREFACE T he chapters in this book were originally delivered as inter-collegiate lectures at Westfield College, Uni­ versity of London, during the Michaelmas term, 1905. They arose out of the deep respect I feel for the work and personality of Professor Eucken, and from a profound sense of the importance of his teaching for philosophy, for religion, and for everyday life. In the publication of these lectures I have been most generously assisted by the Hibbert Trustees. My sincerest thanks are due to them, not only for the grant defraying the expenses of publication, but for their sympathetic recognition of the value of Professor Eucken’s work, and of the need for making it better known to English readers. I gratefully acknowledge the help given me by my wife in the typing of the manuscript and the reading of the proofs. I am also most indebted in this connec­ tion to Professor Eucken himself, who very kindly read through all the proof-sheets, and assisted me in many ways with the most unfailing cordiality and goodwill. CONTENTS CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY— EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHICAL PUBLICA­ TIONS— OUTLINE SKETCH OF THE NEW IDEALISM, WITH PRELIMINARY APPRECIATION AND CRITICISM— EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHY A RALLYING-POINT FOR IDEALISTIC EFFORT— THE SOLIDARITY OF IDEALISM 1 -2 1 CHAPTER II e u c k e n ’s v i e w s o n t h e r e l a t i o n o f p h il o s o p h y t o HISTORY, PARTICULARLY TO THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY,
    [Show full text]
  • The Notion of Absurdity and Meaning of Life in Albert Camus Existentialism
    Open Journal of Philosophy, 2020, 10, 528-538 https://www.scirp.org/journal/ojpp ISSN Online: 2163-9442 ISSN Print: 2163-9434 The Notion of Absurdity and Meaning of Life in Albert Camus Existentialism Ambrose Tochukwu Arinze1, Ignatius Nnaemeka Onwuatuegwu2 1Pope John Paul II Major Seminary Okpuno, Anambra, Nigeria 2Philosophy Department, Faculty of Arts, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka, Nigeria How to cite this paper: Arinze, A. T., & Abstract Onwuatuegwu, I. N. (2020). The Notion of Absurdity and Meaning of Life in Albert Camus unreservedly condemned and strictly criticized and rejected suicide Camus Existentialism. Open Journal of Phi- and existential leap because suicide is a total surrender to absurdity and a to- losophy, 10, 528-538. tal confession that life is too much on the individual. His interest in existen- https://doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2020.104037 tialism is to explain the meaninglessness of life through his explication of the Received: September 4, 2020 absurd which is found in human existence; and which continues to torment Accepted: November 24, 2020 man until the finality of his existence which is death. The knowledge that life Published: November 27, 2020 is absurd is already a step towards conquering the meaninglessness of life. For Camus therefore, since absurd has no meaning, man must hold himself apart Copyright © 2020 by author(s) and from it and revolt against it. This is why he suggested philosophical suicide as Scientific Research Publishing Inc. This work is licensed under the Creative a solution to reverse the absurdity of life. The question then is, since man’s Commons Attribution International belief in the absurdity of existence, then how and where should he direct his License (CC BY 4.0).
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kanfs Influence on the Psychology of Alfred Adler
    Immanuel Kanfs Influence on the Psychology of Alfred Adler Mark H. Stone Abstract The influence of immanuel Kant's philosophy on the psychology of Alfred Adler is important to understand because Kant much earlier addressed many ideas and concepts assumed original with Adler. Kant addressed the concepts of private sense and common sense, the primacy of reason, the existential questions of life, fictions, the power ofthe mind over sense perceptions, the unconscious and conscious mind, unity of the person, fostering community feeling, and determining a moral course of action, all concepts Adler later applied to his psychology. Familiarity with Kant's works can help clinicians gain a better understanding of what Adler wrote and im- plied when explicating Individual Psychology. Kant's writings can be complicated and difficult to understand, but several very readable essays are recommended and readily available. The purpose of this article is to show the influence of Immanuel Kant's (1 724-1804) philosofjhy upon the psychology of Alfred Adler (1870-1937). A number of Adier's important ideas can be traced back to the writings of Kant. This is not to diminish Adier's contributions to psychology because it is Adier's elucidation of these concepts for understanding behavior that is striking. This connection between Kant and Adler relates a segment of the continuing stream of thought in intellectual history that connects the ideas from one thinker to those of another. Ellenberger (1970) wrote, "Adler has many affinities with Kant" (p. 628). However, Ellenberger stopped short of elucidating any of these connections save a very short discussion of com- mon sense and private sense.
    [Show full text]
  • DICTIONARY of PHILOSOPHY This Page Intentionally Left Blank
    A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY This page intentionally left blank. A Dictionary of Philosophy Third edition A.R.Lacey Department of Philosophy, King’s College, University of London First published in 1976 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Second edition 1986 Third edition 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © A.R.Lacey 1976, 1986, 1996 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lacey, A.R. A dictionary of philosophy.—3rd edn. 1. Philosophy—Dictionaries I. Title 190′.3′21 B41 ISBN 0-203-19819-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-19822-0 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-13332-7 (Print Edition) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available on request Preface to the first edition This book aims to give the layman or intending student a pocket encyclopaedia of philosophy, one with a bias towards explaining terminology. The latter task is not an easy one since philosophy is regularly concerned with concepts which are unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton
    The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton Chapter 4: Is Life What You Make It? Submitted by Paul Lussier ‘Recommended Readings’ for the Aspen/Yale Conference 2007 The following is an excerpt from: Terry Eagleton, The Meaning of Life. Oxford University Press (2007), pp.135-175 The Meaning of Life By: Terry Eagleton Chapter 4: Is Life What You Make It? So far, we have looked more at meaning than at life. Yet the word 'life' is every bit as problematic as the word 'meaning', and it is not hard to see why. For surely the reason why we cannot talk about the meaning of life is that there is no such thing as life? Are we not, as Wittgenstein might say, bewitched here by our grammar, which can generate the word 'life' in the singular just as it can the word 'tomato'? Perhaps we have the word 'life' only because our language is intrinsically reifying, 'Essence is expressed by grammar', as Wittgenstein remarks.24 How on earth could everything that falls under the heading of human life, from childbirth to clog dancing, be thought to stack up to a single meaning? Isn't this exactly the delusion of the paranoiac, for whom everything is supposed to be ominously resonant of everything else, bound together in an oppressively translucent whole? Or, if you prefer, the delusion of philosophy, which as Freud mischievously commented is the nearest thing to paranoia? Not even an individual life adds up to a unified whole. It is true that some people see their lives as forming an elegant narrative all the way from Introduction to Epilogue, but not everyone views themselves like this.
    [Show full text]