Morality As Interpretation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Morality As Interpretation Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1991 Morality as Interpretation Joseph Raz Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Science and Technology Law Commons Recommended Citation Joseph Raz, Morality as Interpretation, 101 ETHICS 392 (1991). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/2232 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Moralityas Interpretation* JosephRazt With the growinginterest in interpretationas an activityessential in the study of the artsand of societyit was inevitablethat the question of the relationbetween moralityand interpretationwould attractconsiderable interest. Given thatmoral viewsand argumentsare expressed in language, are essentiallylanguage bound, there is no doubt thatthe understandingof moral viewsand argumentinvolves, at least at times,interpretation (of argumentsand propositions,etc.). The same can be said of physics.The question is whethermorality is interpretativein a way in which physicsis not. Some writershave claimed that it is. I will examine the claims and arguments to that effectadvanced by Michael Walzer, though much of my argument will be general and not limited to the arguments he explicitlyadvances.' THE MAIN THESES At the beginning of his book Walzer declares his intentionto defend the view that "the path of interpretation"in moral philosophy is the one that "accords best withour everydayexperience of morality"(p. 3).2 Later on, he explains: What we do when we argue is to give an account of the actuallyexisting morality.That moralityis authoritativefor us because it is only by virtue of its existence that we exist as the moral beings we are. Our categories, relationships,commitments, and aspirationsare all shaped by, expressed in termsof, the existingmorality. [P. 21] One might say that the moral world is authoritativefor us because it provides us with everythingwe need to live a moral life, including the capacity for reflectionand criticism.... The capacity for criticismalways * A review of Michael Walzer, Interpretationand Social Criticism(Cambridge, Mass.: HarvardUniversity Press, 1987). References to thisbook will appear parenthetically in the text. t This articlegrew out of a discussionat theHartman Institute in Jerusalem (in June 1989) in whichI criticizedWalzer's views along the lines elaborated upon here.In writing thearticle I benefitedfrom contributions to thatdiscussion by Amos Funkenstein, Sydney Morgenbesser,Hilary Putnam, and MichaelWalzer. 1. Walzerhimself does notdraw the contrast with physics. 2. Strictlyspeaking, he only claims there that it is betterthan what he calls the paths of discoveryand invention.His descriptionof thosesuggests that his targetsare some formsof moral realism (discovery) and constructivism,or contractarianism (invention). His mainargument is, however,a positiveone, supportingthe path of interpretation,rather thanmerely an argumentfor the comparative superiority of thepath of interpretation. Ethics101 (January 1991): 392-405 C 1991Thisby contentThe University downloadedof fromChicago. 128.059.178.073All rights reserved. on September0014-1704/91/0102-0002$01.00 25, 2018 10:24:00 AM All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c). 392 Raz Reviewof Walzer 393 extends beyond the "needs" of the social structureitself and its dominant groups. I do not want to defend a functionalposition. The moral world and the social worldare more or less coherent.Morality is alwayspotentially subversiveof class and power. [Pp. 21-22] The general question about the rightthing to do is quickly turned into some more specificquestion-about the career open to talents,let's say, and then about equal opportunity,affirmative action, and quotas. These ... require us to argue about what a career is, what sorts of talents we ought to recognise,whether equal opportunityis a "right.". These ques- tions are pursued withina traditionof moral discourse-indeed theyonly arise withinthat tradition-and theyare pursued byinterpreting the terms of that discourse. The argument is about ourselves; the meaning of our way of life is what is at issue. The general question we finallyanswer is not quite the one we asked at first.It has a crucial addition: what is the rightthing forus to do? [P. 23] Walzer's argument is based on the assumption that some moral claims are better,or better founded, than others. This does not commithim to the view that all moral statementsare eithertrue or false,but it commitshim to holding that some moral claims are true and some false. Where a moral claim is better foundedthan another, the statementthat it is, is true,and itsdenial false.Moreover, in such cases various statementsentailed by the precept that people should act in accordance withthe betterclaim are, presumably,true too.3 Given thisassumption, Walzer advances one major and one subsidiarythesis: Ti: Argumentsin moral philosophy are interpretationsof the morality that exists. T2: Even so, there is plentyof room for social criticism. Three main intuitionsinspire the theses. First,and most important,is the view that moralityis sociallydependent, thatis, thatwhat is rightand wrong for a person to do, what is good or bad, laudable or deplorable, virtuousor revealing of moral defectsin character,etc., depends on social practices.Second, morality does not forma systemof principlesand preceptsarranged in some logical way (in the way in which, e.g., Rawls's theoryof justice is a system),nor is there a specialmethod (like decision behind a veilof ignorance,or thetest of thecategorical imperative)for discovering or testingmoral claims. Third, our societyis not the only morallydecent societythat ever existed. Nor is it the morallybest society thatever existed,with other societiesmere stages of imperfectioncompared with us. Nor are othermorally decent societiesin the past or in the presentnecessarily more like ours than those societiesthat are less morallyappealing, that is, there are ways of being moral and having a morallydecent environmentwhich are veryunlike our ways of being morallydecent, and in environmentsvery unlike ours. These statementsof the intuitionsare veryvague. The degree to which the intuitionsare controversialdepends on their more precise formulations.Few people deny that what is rude, arndtherefore on occasion immoral,depends on 3. As the statementof Walzer's assumption above makes clear, his view is consistent withthe existenceof a widespread moral incommensurability,leading to considerabletruth value gaps. The general driftof his argument suggests that he regards intrasocialmoral issues as largely morally determinate,while contemplatingextensive moral incommen- surabilitywhere intersocialcomparisons are in question. This content downloaded from 128.059.178.073 on September 25, 2018 10:24:00 AM All use subject to University of Chicago Press Terms and Conditions (http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/t-and-c). 394 Ethics January1991 social practices.Many deny thatthe contentof moralityis exclusivelydetermined bythe social practicesof, let us say,the societyto whichthe person whose conduct or characterare under considerationbelongs. Few people believe that morality is a deductivesystem in whichall trueconclusions follow from one simpleprinciple withthe addition of purely factualpremises. Many believe that all cogent moral precepts are to some degree interdependent. Walzer's theses, especially the firstand main one, are an attemptto give a more precise articulationto the intuitions.The argumentsfor the thesesare also argumentsfor the intuitions. I willnot challenge or discussthe underlying intuitions. The only matterunder examination is the thesis that moral argumentsare in- terpretative.In challengingthis thesis I willbe challengingthat way of understanding and explaining the intuitions.But none of the followingarguments is directed against the intuitionsthemselves. It is possible to argue that the best verdicton Walzer'stheses is "not proven."There is too much whichis leftobscure in Walzer's discussion to enable one to reach any substantiveconclusion. In particular,it is unclear what he refersto when he speaks of moral argument being "an inter- pretationof the moralitythat exists." Three clustersof questionsremain unresolved. First,which of the existingmoralities does he have in mind? We generally assume that differentmoralities are practicedor at least avowed (and therefore can be said to exist) in differentsocieties, and, in pluralisticsocieties, different moralitiesare practicedor avowed by differentsections of the population within a single society.This briefstatement is itselfmerely an abbreviateddescription of a much more complex phenomenon of divisionsand crosscurrents.Which of the differentmoralities which exist is interpretedin valid moral arguments? Second, what kindof interpretationis involvedin moralargument? Consider some of the activitiesgenerally referredto as interpretative,such as that of professionalinterpreters in multilingualinternational conventions, the interpre- tation of musical compositionsby conductors,soloists, or orchestras,the inter- pretation
Recommended publications
  • Phil of Law 2014 Syllabus
    Princeton University Politics 563/Philosophy 526 Spring 2014 Philosophy of Law Robert P. George and Michael Smith This seminar will consider a range of issues in philosophy of law with particular emphasis on various dimensions of the relationship between law and morality. Requirements: Students are required to read each week's assignments carefully and participate regularly in seminar discussions. Each student must make a presentation to the seminar. Two written work options are available: (1) a long (7000 word) paper on any topic addressed in the seminar or (2) two shorter (3500), critical essays on issues we have explored. These may, but need not, be related to the topic of one’s presentation. Those readings marked with an asterisk (*) are on e-reserve. The following books (all available in paperback editions) are worth purchasing: Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, 2nd edition Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 2nd edition Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms Week 1: Organizational Meeting *O. W. Holmes, “The Path of the Law,” in The Essential Holmes, ed. Richard Posner, pp. 160-77 *John Austin, “The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, “ in The Philosophy of Law, eds. F. Schauer, W. Sinnot-Armstrong, pp. 32-39 *Carl Llewellyn, “The Bramble Bush, a Realistic Jurisprudence, and the common Law Tradition,” in The Philosophy of Law, eds. F. Schauer, W. Sinnot-Armstrong, pp. 53-62 Week 2: Hart's Concept of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, chs. I-VI *Jonathan Cohen, "Critical Notice of Hart's The Concept of Law," in Mind, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Philosophy of Right As a Theory of Justice
    Copyrighted Material I egel’s Philosophy of Right as a H heory of ustice T J Although many contemporary philosophers have embraced Hegelian philosophy to a surprising degree—which may even help to bridge the gulf between the Analytic and Continental traditions—Hegel’s Elements of the Philosophy of Right has so far failed to exert the slightest influence on the current debates in political philosophy. Rather, in recent years—after the abrupt end of the Marxist phase and its reduction of modern right to a mere superstructure—philosophers returned on a broad front to the rationalist paradigm of the Kantian tradition, which es- sentially dominates the debate from Rawls to Habermas; and however hard these two authors in particular try to embed their Kantian concepts of justice in a realistic, almost social-scientific approach, the theoretical model of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right plays no decisive part in their thought. Nor has the situation changed much in response to the countermovement in political philosophy that came into being through the somewhat arti- ficial grouping of theoreticians as diverse as Charles Taylor, Michael Walzer, or Alasdair MacIntyre under the heading of “communitarianism.” Despite a strong tendency to award a privileged position to ethics as opposed to a formalistic prin- ciple of morality, or to communal values as opposed to arbi- trary individual freedom, no real attempt has been made in these circles to render Hegel’s Philosophy of Right fruitful for the discourse of political philosophy. Indeed, the fact that authors Copyrighted Material chapter 1 such as Michael Walzer, Alasdair MacIntyre, or Joseph Raz are trying to keep the greatest possible distance from the political philosophy of Hegel has acquired an almost symptomatic sig- nificance by now.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Law Revisited
    Michigan Law Review Volume 94 Issue 6 1996 The Concept of Law Revisited Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School, York University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Leslie Green, The Concept of Law Revisited, 94 MICH. L. REV. 1687 (1996). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol94/iss6/15 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IBE CONCEPT OF LAW REVISITED Leslie Green* THE CONCEPT OF LAW. Second Edition. By H.L.A. Hart. With a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1994. Pp. xii, 315. $26. Law is a social construction. It is a historically contingent fea­ ture of certain societies, one whose emergence is signaled by the rise of a systematic form of social control and elite domination. In one way it supersedes custom, in another it rests on it, for law is a system of primary social rules that direct and appraise behavior, together with secondary social rules that identify, change, and en­ force the primary rules. Law may be beneficial, but only in some contexts and always at a price, at the risk of grave injustice; our appropriate attitude to it is therefore one of caution rather than celebration.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletters
    APA Newsletters Volume 06, Number 2 Spring 2007 NEWSLETTER ON PHILOSOPHY AND LAW FROM THE EDITOR, STEVEN SCALET ARTICLES BRIAN H. BIX “Joseph Raz and Conceptual Analysis” JULES L. COLEMAN “Law and Political Morality” TIMOTHY ENDICOTT “Interpretation, Jurisdiction, and the Authority of Law” KENNETH EINAR HIMMA “Revisiting Raz: Inclusive Positivism and the Concept of Authority” LIAM MURPHY “Razian Concepts” STEPHEN PERRY “Two Problems of Political Authority” © 2007 by The American Philosophical Association ISSN: 1067-9464 APA NEWSLETTER ON Philosophy and Law Steven Scalet, Editor Spring 2007 Volume 06, Number 2 relating to such theories. In particular, I will look at the role of conceptual analysis in legal theory, focusing on some recent FROM THE EDITOR work by Joseph Raz.1 I. Overview Edition in Tribute to Joseph Raz It was a commonplace in the history of jurisprudence to focus on the inquiry, what is law? It is worth taking a few moments Joseph Raz is professor at Columbia University Law School to consider the question more closely. and research faculty at Oxford University. His writings influence generations of scholars and his many students are now among First and foremost, there is a potential confusion (heightened 2 the leading scholars in philosophy of law. in English more than in other major languages ), as “law,” even if focused on matters jurisprudential (and not speaking of physical For this edition of the Newsletter we invited leading political laws, the laws of games, social conventions, etc.), can refer to and legal philosophers to analyze some aspect of Professor a number of different, if related, matters: most prominently, Raz’s ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • A Moral Right to Dissent? the Case of Civil Disobedience
    A MORAL RIGHT TO DISSENT? THE CASE OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE A thesis submitted to the faculty of San Francisco State University In partial fulfillment of The Requirements for The Degree ?W\L -02T5 Master of Arts in Philosophy By Juan Sebastian Ospina San Francisco, California May 2016 CERTIFICATION OF APPROVAL I certify that I have read A Moral Right to Dissent? The case of civil disobedience by Juan Sebastian Ospina, and that in my opinion this work meets the criteria for approving a thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy at San Francisco State University. Kevin Toh, Ph.D. Associate Professor, Philosophy Department Shelley Wilcox, Ph.D. Professor, Assistant Chair, Philosophy Department A MORAL RIGHT TO DISSENT? THE CASE OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Juan Sebastian Ospina San Francisco, California May 2016 Joseph Raz has argued that in liberal states there is no moral right to disobedience. Raz claims that all states ought to be what he calls “liberal states,” which do not require a moral right to civil disobedience. Broadly, my focus in this paper is on describing how civil disobedience can be understood as a moral right to be included in the framework of political rights recognized in liberal states. I try to demonstrate that Raz’s argument proceeds from a limited understanding of political rights and political actions, and suggest that his conclusion is invalid or extremely exaggerated. I advance a tentative argument about the importance of this moral right to the political process of deliberative democracies, and of its inclusion in limited form among political participation rights.
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism and the Inseparability of Law and Morals
    \\server05\productn\N\NYU\83-4\NYU403.txt unknown Seq: 1 25-SEP-08 12:20 POSITIVISM AND THE INSEPARABILITY OF LAW AND MORALS LESLIE GREEN* H.L.A. Hart made a famous claim that legal positivism somehow involves a “sepa- ration of law and morals.” This Article seeks to clarify and assess this claim, con- tending that Hart’s separability thesis should not be confused with the social thesis, the sources thesis, or a methodological thesis about jurisprudence. In contrast, Hart’s separability thesis denies the existence of any necessary conceptual connec- tions between law and morality. That thesis, however, is false: There are many necessary connections between law and morality, some of them conceptually signif- icant. Among them is an important negative connection: Law is, of its nature, morally fallible and morally risky. Lon Fuller emphasized what he called the “internal morality of law,” the “morality that makes law possible.” This Article argues that Hart’s most important message is that there is also an immorality that law makes possible. Law’s nature is seen not only in its internal virtues, in legality, but also in its internal vices, in legalism. INTRODUCTION H.L.A. Hart’s Holmes Lecture gave new expression to the old idea that legal systems comprise positive law only, a thesis usually labeled “legal positivism.” Hart did this in two ways. First, he disen- tangled the idea from the independent and distracting projects of the imperative theory of law, the analytic study of legal language, and non-cognitivist moral philosophies. Hart’s second move was to offer a fresh characterization of the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Themes from Raz
    Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Osgoode Digital Commons Articles & Book Chapters Faculty Scholarship 2005 Three Themes from Raz Leslie Green Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Source Publication: Oxford Journal of Legal Studies. Volume 25, Issue 3 (2005), p. 503-524. Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/scholarly_works This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Green, Leslie. "Three Themes from Raz." Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25.3 (2005): 503-524. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles & Book Chapters by an authorized administrator of Osgoode Digital Commons. Three Themes from Raz† Leslie Green* The robust interest in analytic jurisprudence among legal philosophers is testament to the broad and deep influence of Joseph Raz. To find another legal theorist who has not only produced an indispensable body of work, but who taught and encouraged so many jurisprudents of the next generation, one has to go back to his forebear, H.L.A. Hart. But Raz’s influence is not just a matter of passing on the torch. Raz controverted so many of Hart’s central ideas that legal positivism, and in some respects even legal philosophy, will never be the same again. That rules are social practices, that every legal system has one rule of recognition, that the validity of law may depend on moral principles, that rights protect important choices, that there is a duty in fairness to obey the law—the hard times on which each of these Hartian ideas has fallen are due in no small part to the power of Raz’s criticisms, and Raz’s competing views are themselves now the subject of many discussions among lawyers, philosophers and political theorists.
    [Show full text]
  • Princeton Philosophy
    Princeton University Politics 563/Philosophy 526 Spring 2017 Prof. Robert P. George This seminar will consider a range of issues in philosophy of law with particular emphasis on various dimensions of the relationship between law and morality. Course Requirements: Students are required to read each week's assignments carefully and participate regularly in class discussions. Each student must make a presentation to the seminar. Two writing options are available: (1) a research paper or (2) two shorter, critical essays. Readings are drawn mainly from contemporary legal philosophers working within the tradition of analytic jurisprudence. Those readings marked with an asterisk (*) are on E-Reserves. The following books (all available in paperback editions) are worth purchasing: Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (2nd edition) --------------, Philosophy of Law (in Collected Essays, Vol. IV) Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd edition) Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms Week 1: Organizational Meeting John Finnis, Philosophy of Law, ch. 5 (“A Grand Tour of Legal Theory”) Week 2: Hart's Concept of Law H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, chs. I-VI *Jonathan Cohen, "Critical Notice of Hart's The Concept of Law," in Mind, Vol. 71 (1962) Week 3: Hart’s Legal and Political Philosophy H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, chs. VII-IX John Finnis, Philosophy of Law, chs. 10 and 11 Week 4: Dworkin vs. Hart *Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, chs. 2-4 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Postscript *H.L.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Reason, Liberal Neutrality and (Same-Sex) Marriage
    Public Reason, Liberal Neutrality and (Same-Sex) Marriage Andrew Lister Department of Political Studies, Queen's University Paper prepared for the CREUM conference on Neutrality, May 1-3, Montreal *two same-sex vs. opposite-sex typos corrected 15/5/08* 1 Principles of state neutrality are often invoked to undercut conservative arguments against same-sex marriage. When people claim that marriage is an institution defined by God, which the state may not redefine as it pleases1, liberals will sometimes adopt what Michael San- del calls the "naive" strategy of simply denying these claims.2 Often, however, they will employ the "sophisticated" strategy of asserting that, whether true or false, religious views are not legit- imate grounds for public policy in a pluralistic society. During the 2003 hearings that the Cana- dian House of Commons' Standing Committee on Justice and Human Rights held on same-sex marriage, for example, Bloc Québécois M.P. Richard Marceau repeatedly invoked an ideal of public reason in response to claims that homosexuality was sinful or that same-sex marriage was unnatural or that marriage was essentially heterosexual. I am not a theologian so it is difficult for me to define the notion of essence. However I am a jurist and a legislator. That is why the kinds of social organization that I am familiar with and that I study are necessarily legal ones. So, with the greatest of respect for people who because of their religious beliefs do not accept homosexual marriages—and they are fully entitled to their opinion—the Justice Committee must not rely on theology to determine the essence of marriage.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Rights in the Emerging World Order
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 2009 Human Rights in the Emerging World Order Joseph Raz Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Human Rights Law Commons Recommended Citation Joseph Raz, Human Rights in the Emerging World Order, TRANSNATIONAL LEGAL THEORY, VOL. 1, P. 31, 2010; OXFORD LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER NO. 47/2009; COLUMBIA PUBLIC LAW RESEARCH PAPER NO. 09-219 (2009). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1607 This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. (2010) 1 Transnational Legal Theory 31–47 Human Rights in the Emerging World Order Joseph Raz* Abstract Pursuing the so-called political account of human rights, this talk first explains some aspects of the relations between legal and moral rights, and between rights and interests, and then applies the analysis to provide an explanation of human rights. Using the rights to health and to education as examples, it rejects the traditional theory that takes human rights to be rights that people have in virtue of their humanity alone. But human rights are synchronically universal. They are rights which all people living today have, a feature that is a precondition of, and a result of, the fact that they set limits to state sovereignty and justify accountability across borders.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Rights
    1 Against Rights Philosophical Issues, vol. 11 (December, 2001) Richard J. Arneson University of California, San Diego Claims to rights and negotiation about their shape are pervasive in our public and private culture. Rights consciousness is surely desirable and is part and parcel of the transition toward a more democratic world. In this essay I consider the proper placement of moral rights in moral theory. In a famous essay, “Taking Rights Seriously,” Ronald Dworkin argues that if it is accepted that individuals have moral rights against their government, that implies serious constraints on the conduct of government and the freedom of a political majority to enforce its wishes through law.1 I endorse the thesis that individuals have such moral rights and support taking rights seriously in Dworkin’s sense. My focus is elsewhere. In this essay I shall argue that moral rights do not and should not figure in our fundamental moral principles; rights enter at the level of subordinate principles. In a very broad way, to take this stand is to side with utilitarians and consequentialists, who see rights as instruments for achieving other values, not moral goals in their own right.2 Is this more than a verbal issue? We can say that act utilitarianism assigns each person the moral right not to be harmed by anyone unless doing so maximizes utility and to be benefited by everyone whenever doing so maximizes utility. Someone who believes that morality just is Pareto efficiency can say that each person has a moral right, if the status quo can be altered by making her better off without making anyone else worse off, either that the status quo be altered to her benefit or that some entirely new 2 situation be brought about, establishing a new status quo to which no one can make a similar complaint.
    [Show full text]
  • Conclusion: Beyond Legal Positivism and Natural Law?
    Conclusion: Beyond Legal Positivism and Natural Law? Peter Langford and Ian Bryan Opposition to the natural law tradition, and to its potential re-emergence, forms an integral element of Kelsenian legal positivism. While the conceptual dichotomy between natural law and legal positivism has a discernible historical dimension,1 its substance, subsistence and validity remain of pressing concern in contemporary legal theory. The Kelsenian theoretical framework, together with its emphatic rejection of natural law theories has, over the course of the late twentieth- and early twenty-first century, been increasingly supplanted by a theory of legal positivism originating in the work of Hart.2 In contrast to the radical separation in Kelsenian legal positivism,3 Hartian and Hartian- influenced legal positivism focuses upon the degree to which law and moral- ity occupy discrete, or, in the alternative, intersecting domains; with, broadly, exclusive legal positivists inclined to complete separation,4 and inclusive (or soft) legal positivists comprehending varying degrees of interconnectedness between law and morality.5 The advent of Hartian and Hartian-influenced 1 See, for example, John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980; 2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011); John Finnis, ‘The Truth in Le- gal Positivism’, in Robert P. George, (ed.), The Autonomy of Law: Essays in Legal Positivism, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 195–214; and Robert P. George, In Defense of Natural Law, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999). 2 See Herbert. L A. Hart, The Concept of Law, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961; 2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994). See, also, Herbert L.A.
    [Show full text]