Worldly Patterns Emergence, Functionalism and Pragmatic Reality in Wallacian Quantum Mechanics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Worldly Patterns Emergence, Functionalism and Pragmatic Reality in Wallacian Quantum Mechanics History and Philosophy of Science; Foundations of Physics Utrecht University: Master thesis Worldly Patterns Emergence, Functionalism and Pragmatic Reality in Wallacian quantum mechanics \While the wave-function realist will deny that three-dimensional objects and spatial structures find a place in the fundamental ontology, this is not to say that the three-dimensional objects surrounding us, with which we constantly interact, and which we perceive, think and talk about, do not exist; that there are no truths about them; it is just to maintain that they are emergent objects, rather than fundamental ones. But an emergent object is no less real for being emergent." | David Wallace & Christopher Timpson Advisors: Author: Dr. Guido Bacciagaluppi Ruward Arthur Mulder Dr. Ronnie Hermens 15th August, 2018 But I love extravagance And wanting it has handed down The glitter and glamour of the sun As my inheritance |Sappho of Lesbos (630-570 BCE) Scientific summary David Wallace's The Emergent Multiverse is the most recent complete presentation of a version of Everett's theory of quantum mechanics that has attracted much scientific activity in the past decade. I present a brief sketch of Wallace's solution to the measure- ment problem, arguing that the many-worlds interpretation is not as far-fetched as it is often conceived to be. Taking the wavefunction as the fundamental ontology, it claims to solve the measurement problem by recognizing certain (quasi-classical) patterns of the wavefunction in 3N-dimensional configuration space that functionally behave like the (classical) configuration-space pattern of a N-particle system described by classical mechanics. In this sense, structures within the universal wavefunction are identified with classical `worlds' at the coarse-grained level. I highlight two elements of this work: the role of emergence and the functionalist framework that Wallace imports through what he calls `Dennett's criterion'. This criterion appeals to the virtue of usefulness (in the form of predictability and explanatory power) as a criterion for the reality of `patterns'. It is shown that, due to decoherence, quasi-classical worlds emerge weakly, similar to that of the emergence of thermodynamic temperature from statistical physics, in the sense that they are autonomous and unexpected with respect to the lower-level domain (as opposed to strong emergence of some insuper et supra high-level ontology). However, the use of Dennett's criterion obscures this result, laying bare some philosophical issues, which we address over three axes of distinctions: (i) the objective/subjective-axis, (ii) the quantitative/qualitative-axis within the framework of intertheoretic reduction and (iii) the ontological/epistemological-axis. First, Daniel Dennett's `real patterns' are compared to Wallace approach to pat- terns. Then, I point out (i) an analogy with Bas van Fraassen's idea of causal patterns that become salient due to pragmatic explanation, namely that in the context of a prag- matic goal the quasi-classical pattern is made salient over other objectively existing, non-classical, patterns. I conclude that in the absence of human goals there is no reason to regard the quasi-classical pattern as `more real' than other patterns. In analogy to Dennett's `intentional stance', Wallace is committed to a `classical stance', equivalent to breaking Hilbert space democracy of bases. Although Wallace's version is a weaker one, his (ii) relations between theories bare resemblance to the reductionist program, and I argue that, next to quantitative deduction, additional conceptual `bridge principles' `ala Ernest Nagel are needed. The appeal to usefulness as a criterion for reality (iii), I claim, is not necessary to solve the measurement problem itself, but has the further (unwarranted) goal of establishing `real' worlds. I spell out a solution to the measurement problem, the many-minds theory, which solves the problem along the same lines as The Emergent Multiverse, with the exception that the { although the quantum world itself is real { the classical worlds with definite properties are beliefs in the superposed brains of observers. Persoonlijk voor- en dankwoord Voor u ligt een scriptie waarmee ik na acht jaar mijn academische opleiding afrond. Na vele jaren te hebben gezworven tussen verschillende velden { natuur- en sterrenkunde, geschiedenis, filosofie, kunst- matige intelligentie en biologie { en het afronden van een opleiding theoretische fysica een jaar geleden, ben ik uiteindelijk trots om de spreekwoordelijke punt te zetten achter de master History and Philos- ophy of Science (HPS). Deze omzwervingen zijn het resultaat geweest van een gevoel van onbehagen, dat groeide naarmate mijn beeld van de wetenschap afbrokkelde. Steeds meer leek de praktijk niet te bevestigen wat wetenschap mij in eerste instantie toescheen: een manier om onomstotelijke en objec- tieve feiten te verwerven; om uit te leggen hoe de natuur daadwerkelijk werkt; om menselijke factoren, en vooral politiek en maatschappij, weg te filteren; om universele kennis cumulatief te verwerven vanaf de Griekse Oudheid tot de dag van vandaag. Dat onbehagen is eigenlijk al een one-way-ticket naar HPS. Vanuit daar kon ik laten zien wat de wetenschap allemaal n´ı´etis; en dat heb ik dan ook met veel overtuiging proberen te doen. Maar het bleek dat ook daar na¨ıviteitloerde en dat ik met enkel kritiek ook niet uit de voeten kon. Ik voelde een behoefte aan een retour-ticket, om dat onwaarschijnlijke idee `wetenschap' weer te gaan verdedigen. Na deze jaren denk ik dat het einde van die tocht voor mij persoonlijk in zicht is; al die dingen die wetenschap niet is { universeel, objectief, cumulatief { maken het voor mij nu juist geloofwaardig en overtuigend. We kunnen feiten w´elaannemen van `autoritaire' wetenschappers, niet omdat zij de waarheid voor eens en altijd in pacht hebben maar omdat zij een leven lang werken om feiten robuust te krijgen. Wetenschap is een culturele onderneming welke wat mij betreft het `gezonde verstand' idoliseert. Waar het dat voorheen niet deed, lijkt mijn beeld nu veel meer aan te sluiten bij de realiteit. Kortom, ik heb de mogelijkheid gekregen om mijn persoonlijk wereldbeeld te vernietigen en het weer op te bouwen en dat is precies wat we van de universiteiten moeten verwachten|en wat ze nooit als taak mogen vergeten. Uiteindelijk resulteert bovenstaand proces in twee overtuigingen. Ten eerste dat ik al die tijd (tegen alle initi¨elepogingen in) t´och aan een maatschappelijk project heb zitten werken; dat is tevens een realisatie die ik met beide handen heb aangegrepen door ook buiten de Ivoren Toren zo veel mo- gelijk verantwoordelijkheid op me te nemen. En ten tweede is het juist dankzij die herwaardering voor wetenschap dat ik de natuurkunde niet heb losgelaten en alsnog een these heb geschreven over een thema in de grondslagen van de natuurkunde, want naar mijn mening zijn conceptuele analyses van gangbare wetenschappelijk theorie¨ennoodzakelijk. Filosofische kritiek zal altijd nodig zijn, ook voor de komende generaties, zowel binnen de wetenschap als daarbuiten. Het levert handvatten voor beter begrip, leidt soms zelfs tot nieuwe theorie¨enen houdt bovenal de { altijd verleidelijke { dogmatische interpretaties op afstand. Deze these, om maar eens op de inhoud over te gaan, is zo'n natuurkundige/filosofische hybride. Voor al die vrienden en familieleden die mij meerdere malen hebben gevraagd wat ik nu eigenlijk al die tijd aan het doen ben, zal ik hier een poging wagen die vragen te beantwoorden. Als uitgangspunt neemt dit werk enkele kernproblemen in onze meest succesvolle theorie van de natuur, de kwantummechanica. Deze problematiek wordt vaak afgekort als `het meetprobleem' en ligt ten grondslag aan de (letterlijk!) eeuwige anarchie van verschillende theorie¨en(vaak onterecht verschillende `interpretaties' genoemd), waarvan hun aanhangers beweren dat ze de problemen oplossen zonder in te leveren op de empirische adequaatheid (de aansluiting met de waarneming). Dit werk is aanvankelijk dan ook een verkenning van ´e´envan de mogelijke oplossingen van die problematiek: de relatieve-toestandstheorie van Hugh Everett III, in de volksmond (het volk bestaat uit een aantal verdwaalde natuurkundestudenten) ook wel de `veelwerelden-interpretatie' genoemd. Everett schreef aan de universiteit van Princeton aan het einde van de jaren vijftig zijn visie op in zijn proefschrift onder John Archibald Wheeler. Zijn werk was gedetailleerd, radicaal vernieuwend op vele vlakken (zoals men dan zegt was hij `zijn tijd vooruit') en formuleerde buitengewoon scherp de tekortkomingen van de gangbare theorie: Kopen- hagen. Everett zelf vervolgde zijn academische carri`ereniet, misschien mede door de overmatige (en achteraf onterechte) kritiek van leidende natuurkundigen als Niels Bohr en L´eonRosenfeld. Everetts idee¨en,echter, aangevuld en aangejuicht door bekende namen (denk onder andere aan Bryce DeWitt, Murray Gell-Mann, John Wheeler zelf), zijn sindsdien eigenlijk voortdurend onderhevig geweest aan een populariteitsconjunctuur; en juist die lijkt in de afgelopen jaren weer te pieken. Het idee van de veelwerelden-theorie is dat de eigenaardige superposities van de kwantum- fysica { superposities zijn een wiskundige beschrijving waarbij het lijkt alsof objecten tegenstrijdige eigenschappen tegelijkertijd kunnen bezitten (zoals een op hetzelfde moment linksdraaiend ´enrechts- draaiend voorwerp) { verschillende `parallelle werelden' beschrijven, waardoor de inwoners van ´e´enzo'n
Recommended publications
  • Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us About the Role of Providence in Nature 247 Bruce L
    Journal of Biblical and Theological Studies JBTSVOLUME 2 | ISSUE 2 Christianity and the Philosophy of Science Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us about the Role of Providence in Nature 247 Bruce L. Gordon [JBTS 2.2 (2017): 247-298] Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us about the Role of Providence in Nature1 BRUCE L. GORDON Bruce L. Gordon is Associate Professor of the History and Philosophy of Science at Houston Baptist University and a Senior Fellow of Discovery Institute’s Center for Science and Culture Abstract: Modern science has revealed a world far more exotic and wonder- provoking than our wildest imaginings could have anticipated. It is the purpose of this essay to introduce the reader to the empirical discoveries and scientific concepts that limn our understanding of how reality is structured and interconnected—from the incomprehensibly large to the inconceivably small—and to draw out the metaphysical implications of this picture. What is unveiled is a universe in which Mind plays an indispensable role: from the uncanny life-giving precision inscribed in its initial conditions, mathematical regularities, and natural constants in the distant past, to its material insubstantiality and absolute dependence on transcendent causation for causal closure and phenomenological coherence in the present, the reality we inhabit is one in which divine action is before all things, in all things, and constitutes the very basis on which all things hold together (Colossians 1:17). §1. Introduction: The Intelligible Cosmos For science to be possible there has to be order present in nature and it has to be discoverable by the human mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Reformulating Bell's Theorem: the Search for a Truly Local Quantum
    Reformulating Bell's Theorem: The Search for a Truly Local Quantum Theory∗ Mordecai Waegelly and Kelvin J. McQueenz March 2, 2020 Abstract The apparent nonlocality of quantum theory has been a persistent concern. Einstein et. al. (1935) and Bell (1964) emphasized the apparent nonlocality arising from entanglement correlations. While some interpretations embrace this nonlocality, modern variations of the Everett-inspired many worlds interpretation try to circumvent it. In this paper, we review Bell's \no-go" theorem and explain how it rests on three axioms, local causality, no superdeterminism, and one world. Although Bell is often taken to have shown that local causality is ruled out by the experimentally confirmed entanglement correlations, we make clear that it is the conjunction of the three axioms that is ruled out by these correlations. We then show that by assuming local causality and no superdeterminism, we can give a direct proof of many worlds. The remainder of the paper searches for a consistent, local, formulation of many worlds. We show that prominent formulations whose ontology is given by the wave function violate local causality, and we critically evaluate claims in the literature to the contrary. We ultimately identify a local many worlds interpretation that replaces the wave function with a separable Lorentz-invariant wave-field. We conclude with discussions of the Born rule, and other interpretations of quantum mechanics. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Local causality 3 3 Reformulating Bell's theorem 5 4 Proving Bell's theorem with many worlds 6 5 Global worlds 8 5.1 Global branching . .8 5.2 Global divergence .
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum/Classical Correspondence in the Light of Bell's Inequalities Contents
    Quantum/Classical Correspondence in the Light of Bell’s Inequalities Leonid A. Khalfin1 and Boris S. Tsirelson2 Received November 26, 1990; revised October 31, 1991 Instead of the usual asymptotic passage from quantum mechanics to classical mechanics when a parameter tended to infinity, a sharp boundary is obtained for the domain of existence of classical reality. The last is treated as separable em- pirical reality following d’Espagnat, described by a mathematical superstructure over quantum dynamics for the universal wave function. Being empirical, this reality is constructed in terms of both fundamental notions and characteristics of observers. It is presupposed that considered observers perceive the world as a system of collective degrees of freedom that are inherently dissipative because of interaction with thermal degrees of freedom. Relevant problems of foundation of statistical physics are considered. A feasible example is given of a macroscopic system not admitting such classical reality. The article contains a concise survey of some relevant domains: quantum and classical Bell-type inequalities; universal wave function; approaches to quan- tum description of macroscopic world, with emphasis on dissipation; spontaneous reduction models; experimental tests of the universal validity of the quantum the- ory. Contents Introduction 880 1 KinematicsandDynamicsofCorrelations 883 2 Universal Wave Function 894 3 Reconstruction of the Classical World: Approaches to the Problem 900 4 Dissipative Dynamics of Correlations 911 5 In Search of Alternative Theories 923 6 Relationship to the Problem of the Foundations of Statistical Physics926 1Permanent address: Steklov Mathematical Institute, Russian Academy of Sciences, Leningrad Division, Fontanka 27, 191011 Leningrad, Russia. 2Permanent address: School of Mathematics, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israrel.
    [Show full text]
  • Decoherence and Its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics
    Decoherence and its Role in Interpretations of Quantum Physics Simon Matthew Thomas Newey Submitted in Accordance with the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Leeds School of Philosophy, Religion and History of Science February 2019 2 The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his/her/their own and that appropriate credit has been given where reference has been made to the work of others. This copy has been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper acknowledgement. The right of Simon Mathew Thomas Newey to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted by Simon Mathew Thomas Newey in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 3 Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisors Juha Saatsi and Stephen French for their patience, support and guidance over the last four years. I am grateful to the Arts and Humanities Research Council for funding this project. I am also grateful for helpful and interesting conversations I have had over the last four years with Callum Duguid, Guido Bacciagaluppi, Karim Thébault, Richard Dawid, and Simon Saunders. 4 Abstract The purpose of this thesis is to examine different conceptions of decoherence and their significance within interpretations of quantum mechanics. I set out three different conceptions of decoherence found in the literature and examine the relations between them. I argue that only the weakest of these conceptions is empirically well supported, and that the other two rely on claims about the structure of the histories (robust patterns within the wavefunction) which we occupy which require justification.
    [Show full text]
  • Many Worlds? an Introduction
    Many Worlds? An Introduction Simon Saunders This problem of getting the interpretationprovedtoberathermoredifficult than just working out the equation. P.A.M. Dirac Ask not if quantum mechanics is true, ask rather what the theory implies. What does realism about the quantum state imply? What follows then, when quantum theory is applied without restriction, if need be to the whole universe? This is the question that this book addresses. The answers vary widely. According to one view, ‘what follows’ is a detailed and realistic picture of reality that provides a unified description of micro- and macroworlds. But according to another, the result is nonsense—there is no physically meaningful theory at all, or not in the sense of a realist theory, a theory supposed to give an intelligible picture of a reality existing independently of our thoughts and beliefs. According to the latter view, the formalism of quantum mechanics, if applied unrestrictedly, is at best a fragment of such a theory, in need of substantive additional assumptions and equations. So sharp a division about what appears to be a reasonably well-defined question is all the more striking given how much agreement there is otherwise, for all parties to the debate in this book are agreed on realism, and on the need, or the aspiration, for a theory that unites micro- and macroworlds, at least in principle. They all see it as legitimate—obligatory even—to ask whether the fundamental equations of quantum mechanics, principally the Schrodinger¨ equation, already constitute such a system. They all agree that such equations, if they are to be truly fundamental, must ultimately apply to the entire universe.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Measurement Problem
    International Journal of Theoretical and Mathematical Physics 2014, 4(5): 202-219 DOI: 10.5923/j.ijtmp.20140405.04 On the Measurement Problem Raed M. Shaiia Department of Physics, Damascus University, Damascus, Syria Abstract In this paper, we will see that we can reformulate the purely classical probability theory, using similar language to the one used in quantum mechanics. This leads us to reformulate quantum mechanics itself using this different way of understanding probability theory, which in turn will yield a new interpretation of quantum mechanics. In this reformulation, we still prove the existence of none classical phenomena of quantum mechanics, such as quantum superposition, quantum entanglement, the uncertainty principle and the collapse of the wave packet. But, here, we provide a different interpretation of these phenomena of how it is used to be understood in quantum physics. The advantages of this formulation and interpretation are that it induces the same experimental results, solves the measurement problem, and reduces the number of axioms in quantum mechanics. Besides, it suggests that we can use new types of Q-bits which are more easily to manipulate. Keywords Measurement problem, Interpretation of quantum mechanics, Quantum computing, Quantum mechanics, Probability theory Measurement reduced the wave packet to a single wave and 1. Introduction a single momentum [3, 4]. The ensemble interpretation: This interpretation states Throughout this paper, Dirac's notation will be used. that the wave function does not apply to an individual In quantum mechanics, for example [1] in the experiment system – or for example, a single particle – but is an of measuring the component of the spin of an electron on abstract mathematical, statistical quantity that only applies the Z-axis, and using as a basis the eigenvectors of σˆ3 , the to an ensemble of similarly prepared systems or particles [5] state vector of the electron before the measurement is: [6].
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical, Theoretical and Experimental Propositions on Wavefunction Collapse
    Imperial College of Science, Technology and Medicine Department of Physics Philosophical, Theoretical and Experimental Propositions On Wavefunction Collapse Daniel Goldwater Submitted in part fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Physics of the University of London and the Diploma of Imperial College, September 2018 Declaration I, Daniel Goldwater, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where infor- mation has been drawn from other sources, it has been appropriately labelled and referenced in the text. The work described in chapter 4 will appear in a forthcoming paper [1]; the results of chapter 5 were reported in [2]; whilst those of chapter 6 appear in [3], and were achieved in collaboration with Dr. Sandro Donadi. Chapter 7 recounts a collaboration with Dr. James Millen, and is reported in [4]. Though I wrote the code for the simulations presented in chapter 7, it was James who produced the plots from these simulations. Copyright declaration: The copyright of this thesis rests with the author. Unless otherwise indicated, its contents are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial 4.0 International Licence (CC BY-NC). Under this licence, you may copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format. You may also create and distribute modified versions of the work. This is on the condition that: you credit the author and do not use it, or any derivative works, for a commercial purpose. When reusing or sharing this work, ensure you make the licence terms clear to others by naming the licence and linking to the licence text.
    [Show full text]
  • TIME and the FOUNDATIONS of QUANTUM MECHANICS By
    TIME AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS by Thomas Pashby M. Sci., University of Bristol, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2014 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Thomas Pashby It was defended on March 28th, 2014 and approved by John Earman, Ph.D., History and Philosophy of Science John D. Norton, Ph.D., History and Philosophy of Science Robert Batterman, Ph.D., Philosophy Gordon Belot, Ph.D., Philosophy (University of Michigan) Giovanni Valente, Ph.D., Philosophy Dissertation Directors: John Earman and John D. Norton ii Copyright c by Thomas Pashby 2014 iii TIME AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS Thomas Pashby, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2014 Quantum mechanics has provided philosophers of science with many counterin- tuitive insights and interpretive puzzles, but little has been written about the role that time plays in the theory. One reason for this is the celebrated argument of Wolfgang Pauli against the inclusion of time as an observable of the theory, which has been seen as a demonstration that time may only enter the theory as a classical parameter. Against this orthodoxy I argue that there are good rea- sons to expect certain kinds of `time observables' to find a representation within quantum theory, including clock operators (which provide the means to measure the passage of time) and event time operators, which provide predictions for the time at which a particular event occurs, such as the appearance of a dot on a luminescent screen.
    [Show full text]
  • Seminar – Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics
    Seminar | Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Interpretations of probability A great deal of confusion about quantum mechanics originates from confusion about proba- bility itself. Unbeknownst to most physicists, a great deal has been written by the philosophers about interpretations of probability [1]. Are probabilities just relative frequencies? Then one must explain how to connect that with the usual probability calculus. Or are probabilities better understood as subjective degrees of belief [2]? Then one must explain why probabilistic events like Chernobyl seem pretty much objective. Or maybe objective chances exist after all [3]? Maybe they do, but one must do better than simply postulating that this is the case. [1] A. Hájek. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Interpretations of Probability. 2011. url: https: //plato.stanford.edu/entries/probability-interpret/. [2] C. Caves. Notes on the Dutch Book Argument. 2000. url: http://info.phys.unm.edu/ ~caves/reports/dutchbook.pdf. [3] D. Lewis. “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance”. Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability. Ed. by R. Carnap and R. Jeffrey. v. 2. University of California Press, 1980, p. 293. url: http://www.andrewmbailey.com/dkl/Subjectivist_Guide.pdf. The measurement problem The central problem in the interpretation of quantum mechanics is the measurement problem [1,2]: how does one describe physically what happens during a measurement? Does the quantum state evolve according to the projection postulate, in a non-linear, irreversible, non- deterministic way
    [Show full text]
  • The Self–Simulation Hypothesis Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
    Article The Self–Simulation Hypothesis Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Klee Irwin 1,* , Marcelo Amaral 1 and David Chester 1 1 Quantum Gravity Research, Los Angeles, CA 90290, USA * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: We modify the simulation hypothesis to a self–simulation hypothesis, where the physical universe, as a strange loop, is a mental self–simulation that might exist as one of a broad class of possible code theoretic quantum gravity models of reality obeying the principle of efficient language axiom. This leads to ontological interpretations about quantum mechanics. We also discuss some implications of the self–simulation hypothesis such as an informational arrow of time. Keywords: simulation hypothesis, philosophy of mind, quantum mechanics Contents 1 Introduction and Background2 1.1 Definitions.............................................6 2 The Self–Simulation Hypothesis7 2.1 Axioms and Principle of Efficient Language..........................7 2.2 Information............................................8 2.3 Nonlocality of the Self–Simulation............................... 14 3 Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics 18 3.1 Completeness........................................... 18 3.2 Local Realism........................................... 19 3.3 Determinism............................................ 19 3.4 Randomness............................................ 19 3.5 Ontologically Real Wavefunction................................ 20 3.6 Unique Particle History..................................... 20
    [Show full text]
  • QUANTUM GRAVITY and the ROLE of CONSCIOUSNESS in PHYSICS Resolving the Contradictions Between Quantum Mechanics and Relativity
    1 QUANTUM CONSCIOUSNESS RESEARCH LIMITED QUANTUM GRAVITY and the ROLE of CONSCIOUSNESS in PHYSICS Resolving the contradictions between quantum mechanics and relativity Sky Darmos 2020/8/14 Explains/resolves accelerated expansion, quantum entanglement, information paradox, flatness problem, consciousness, non-Copernican structures, quasicrystals, dark matter, the nature of quantum spin, weakness of gravity, arrow of time, vacuum paradox, and much more. 2 Working titles: Physics of the Mind (2003 - 2006); The Conscious Universe (2013 - 2014). Presented theories (created and developed by Sky Darmos): Similar-worlds interpretation (2003); Space particle dualism theory* (2005); Conscious set theory (2004) (Created by the author independently but fundamentally dependent upon each other). *Inspired by Roger Penrose’s twistor theory (1967). Old names of these theories: Equivalence theory (2003); Discontinuity theory (2005); Relationism (2004). Contact information: Facebook: Sky Darmos WeChat: Sky_Darmos Email: [email protected] Cover design: Sky Darmos (2005) Its meaning: The German word “Elementarräume”, meaning elementary spaces, is written in graffiti style. The blue background looks like a 2-dimensional surface, but when we look at it through the two magnifying glasses at the bottom we see that it consists of 1-dimensional elementary “spaces” (circles). That is expressing the idea that our well known 3-dimensional space could in the same way be made of 2- dimensional sphere surfaces. The play with dimensionality is further extended by letting all the letters approach from a distant background where they appear as a single point (or point particle) moving through the pattern formed by these overlapping elementary spaces. The many circles originating from all angles in the letters represent the idea that every point (particle) gives rise to another elementary space (circle).
    [Show full text]
  • Probability in the Everett Interpretation Hilary Greaves* Rutgers University
    Probability in the Everett interpretation Hilary Greaves* Rutgers University Abstract The Everett (many-worlds) interpretation of quantum mechanics faces a prima facie problem concerning quantum probabilities. Research in this area has been fast-paced over the last few years, following a controversial suggestion by David Deutsch that decision theory can solve the problem. This article provides a non-technical introduction to the decision-theoretic program, and a sketch of the current state of the debate. Full text: 1 The problem of probability 1.1 Introduction Quantum mechanics, as usually understood, is an indeterministic theory; it makes probabilistic predictions. For example: if one feeds into a Stern-Gerlach device an electron in a nontrivial superposition of spin-up and spin-down, ψ = a ↑ + b ↓ , the 'textbook' predictions are that the outcome will be either spin-up or spin-down, with probabilities given by |a|2,|b|2 respectively. The Everett, or many-worlds, interpretation gives a different account of quantum measurement. Indeterminism enters the 'textbook' story at the point of wavefunction collapse: when the measurement is performed, the wavefunction is supposed to collapse (indeterministically) into one or the other eigenstate of the observable being measured. But the many-worlds interpretation denies that collapse occurs. Instead, according to the many-worlds interpretation, when the measurement is performed, the apparatus, and the observer, and the laboratory, and indeed the entire world, will split into two copies, or 'branches'. There will be one branch on which the spin-up outcome occurs (and a future copy of the observer records spin-up), and there will be another branch on which spin- down occurs (and a future copy of the observer records spin-down).
    [Show full text]