Stochastic Mechanics Without Ad Hoc Quantization: Theory and Applications to Semiclassical Gravity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Stochastic Mechanics Without Ad Hoc Quantization: Theory and Applications to Semiclassical Gravity Stochastic Mechanics Without Ad Hoc Quantization: Theory And Applications To Semiclassical Gravity arXiv:1804.01394v1 [quant-ph] 31 Mar 2018 Stochastic Mechanics Without Ad Hoc Quantization: Theory And Applications To Semiclassical Gravity Stochastische mechanica zonder ad hoc quantisatie: theorie en toepassingen op semi-klassieke zwaartekracht (met een samenvatting in het Nederlands) Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit Utrecht op gezag van de rector magnificus, prof. dr. G. J. van der Zwaan, ingevolge het besluit van het college voor promoties in het openbaar te verdedigen op donderdag 19 oktober 2017 des middags te 12.45 uur door Maaneli Derakhshani geboren op 3 oktober 1985 te Rancho Palos Verdes, Verenigde Staten van Amerika Promotoren: Prof. dr. R. B. Mann Prof. dr. L. T. G. Theunissen Copromotor: Dr. G. Bacciagaluppi Papers and Publications Chapter 2 • A Suggested Answer To Wallstrom’s Criticism: Zitterbewegung Stochastic Mechanics I Maaneli Derakhshani https://arxiv.org/abs/1510.06391 Chapter 3 • A Suggested Answer To Wallstrom’s Criticism: Zitterbewegung Stochastic Mechanics II Maaneli Derakhshani https://arxiv.org/abs/1607.08838 Chapter 4 • Semiclassical Newtonian Field Theories Based On Stochastic Mechanics I Maaneli Derakhshani https://arxiv.org/abs/1701.06893 Chapter 5 • Semiclassical Newtonian Field Theories Based On Stochastic Mechanics II Maaneli Derakhshani https://arxiv.org/abs/1702.02472 Work which is not directly part of this dissertation (but is referenced throughout): Probing Gravitational Cat States In Canonical Quantum Theory vs. Objective Collapse • Theories Maaneli Derakhshani https://arxiv.org/abs/1609.01711 Probing a Gravitational Cat State: Experimental Possibilities • Maaneli Derakhshani Journal of Physics: Conference Series, Volume 1, conference 1 (2016) https://arxiv.org/abs/1603.04430 i Newtonian Semiclassical Gravity in the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber Theory with Matter Den- • sity Ontology Maaneli Derakhshani Physics Letters A, Volume 378, Issue 14-15 (2014) https://arxiv.org/abs/1304.0471 The Newtonian Limit Of Stochastic Gravity Doesn’t Entail The Many-Body Stochastic • Schr¨odinger -Newton Equations Or Gravitationally-Induced Wavefunction Collapse Maaneli Derakhshani (In preparation) On Multi-Time Correlations And Effective Collapse In Stochastic Mechanics • Maaneli Derakhshani and Guido Bacciagaluppi (In preparation) ii Contents 1 Introduction 11 2 A Suggested Answer To Wallstrom’s Criticism: ZSM I 19 2.1 Introduction.................................... 19 2.2 Nelson-Yasue Stochastic Mechanics . ........ 23 2.3 Wallstrom’sCriticism . 31 2.4 Classical Model of Constrained Zitterbewegung Motion . ............. 34 2.4.1 Onefreeparticle ............................... 35 2.4.2 Classical Hamilton-Jacobi statistical mechanics for one free particle . 37 2.4.3 One particle interacting with external fields . ......... 39 2.4.4 Classical Hamilton-Jacobi statistical mechanics for one particle interact- ingwithexternalfields. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 43 2.5 Zitterbewegung Stochastic Mechanics . ......... 45 2.5.1 Onefreeparticle ............................... 45 2.5.2 One particle interacting with external fields . ......... 56 2.5.3 The central potential revisited . ..... 65 2.6 Conclusion ...................................... 66 2.7 Acknowledgments................................. 66 3 A Suggested Answer To Wallstrom’s Criticism: ZSM II 67 3.1 Introduction.................................... 67 3.2 Nelson-Yasue Stochastic Mechanics for Many Particles . ............. 68 3.3 Interpretation of the Nelson-Yasue wavefunction . ............ 78 3.4 Classical Model of Constrained Zitterbewegung Motion for Many Particles . 83 3.4.1 Free zbw particles .............................. 83 3.4.2 Classical Hamilton-Jacobi statistical mechanics for free zbw particles . 84 3.4.3 External fields interacting with zbw particles ............... 86 3.4.4 Classical Hamilton-Jacobi statistical mechanics for zbw particles inter- actingwithexternalfields . 89 3.4.5 Classically interacting zbw particles .................... 91 iii Contents 3.4.6 Classical Hamilton-Jacobi statistical mechanics for two interacting zbw particles ................................... 96 3.4.7 Remarks on close-range interactions . 101 3.5 Zitterbewegung Stochastic Mechanics . ......... 102 3.5.1 Free zbw particles .............................. 102 3.5.2 Classical fields interacting with zbw particles . 119 3.5.3 Remark on on close-range interactions . 132 3.6 Plausibility of the Zitterbewegung Hypothesis . ............ 132 3.7 ComparisontoOtherAnswers. 137 3.8 Conclusion ...................................... 141 3.9 Acknowledgments................................. 141 4 Semiclassical Newtonian Field Theories Based On Stochastic Mechanics I 143 4.1 Introduction.................................... 143 4.2 Overview of ZSM for many free particles . ....... 147 4.3 ZSM-Newton/Coulomb: Basic equations . ....... 159 4.4 Schr¨odinger-Newton/Coulomb equations as mean-field theories . 176 4.5 Comparison to other semiclassical Newtonian field theories ........... 190 4.5.1 Comparison to non-hidden-variable approaches . ......... 190 4.5.2 Comparison to alternative hidden-variable approaches .......... 194 4.6 Conclusion ...................................... 207 4.7 Acknowledgments................................. 208 5 Semiclassical Newtonian Field Theories Based On Stochastic Mechanics II 209 5.1 Introduction.................................... 209 5.2 Large N center-of-mass approximation in ZSM-Newton/Coulomb . 211 5.2.1 Generalapproach............................... 211 5.3 Classical nonlinear Schr¨odinger equation for large N center-of-mass motion . 224 5.3.1 Oriols et al.’s derivation . 224 5.3.2 Conditional Madelung equations . 225 5.3.3 Comments on the classical nonlinear Schr¨odinger equation . 230 5.4 Recovering classical Newtonian gravity for many macro particles . 230 5.5 Recovering classical Vlasov-Poisson mean-field theory .............. 233 5.6 Incorporating environmental decoherence . .......... 235 5.7 Conclusion ...................................... 236 iv Contents 6 Appendix to Chapter 2 239 6.1 Proof of the 1-particle Stochastic Variational Principle.............. 239 6.2 Classical Zitterbewegung in the Central Potential ................. 240 7 Appendix to Chapter 3 243 7.1 Proof of the N -particle Stochastic Variational Principle . 243 8 Summary and Outlook 245 9 Samenvatting 247 10 About the author 249 Bibliography 251 v Preface This thesis is the culmination of a nearly decade-long journey. The journey started when I was a sophomore undergraduate at Stony Brook University (SBU), excitedly learning about Nelson’s stochastic mechanics and the “Wallstrom criticism” thereof from the papers of Dr. Guido Bacciagaluppi, and from discussions with Prof. Sheldon (Shelly) Goldstein at Rutgers University. Having found stochastic mechanics a compelling way to make sense of quantum mechanics, I was determined to find an answer to the criticism. I explored various possibilities to no avail until, one day, out of sheer luck, I stumbled upon a dusty, yellow-paged book entitled “Observation and Interpretation: A Symposium of Philosophers and Physicists”, in the bookcase of Dr. John No´e, the Director of the Laser Teaching Center at SBU. (Thank you for the book, John.) This book, published in 1957, had among its contributions a little-known paper by David Bohm entitled “A proposed explanation of quantum theory in terms of hidden variables at a sub-quantum-mechanical level”. In this paper, Bohm sketches a model - which he credits to Louis de Broglie (in fact, Bohm’s model was just a slight reformulation of an idea suggested by de Broglie in the latter’s Ph.D thesis, an idea which also happens to be the precursor to the de Broglie-Bohm pilot-wave theory) - of an elementary particle as a localized periodic process of fixed frequency in a hypothetical sub-quantum medium. Invoking the Lorentz transformation of special relativity, Bohm shows how the model recovers a quantization condition of Bohr- Sommerfeld type for the phase of the periodic process, and how this quantization condition is related to the single-valuedness condition on wavefunctions in quantum mechanics. In fact, the quantization condition obtained in the model of de Broglie and Bohm is precisely what’s needed for stochastic mechanical theories to recover the Schr¨odinger equation of non-relativistic quantum mechanics (as I will explain in the thesis). And it was precisely the lack of justifi- cation for this quantization condition in stochastic mechanics that Wallstrom emphasized and criticized in the late 80’s and early 90’s. So it became clear to me how to answer the criticism - reformulate Nelson’s stochastic mechanics so as to consistently incorporate the model of de Broglie and Bohm. Throughout my circuitous path through graduate school, I persistently worked on this prob- lem, hoping to base my Ph.D thesis on it. Eventually I would find the opportunity to do so under the supervision of Guido (mentioned above), Prof. Robb Mann (at the University of Waterloo), Prof. Bert Theunissen (at Utrecht University), and the flagship of Utrecht Uni- vii Contents versity. Along the way, I extended the reformulated stochastic mechanics to the domain of semiclassical Newtonian gravity, finding that it has advantages over other approaches to semi- classical Newtonian gravity (e.g., the Schr¨odinger-Newton equation). The result is the thesis before you. Maaneli (Max) Derakhshani Utrecht,
Recommended publications
  • Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us About the Role of Providence in Nature 247 Bruce L
    Journal of Biblical and Theological Studies JBTSVOLUME 2 | ISSUE 2 Christianity and the Philosophy of Science Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us about the Role of Providence in Nature 247 Bruce L. Gordon [JBTS 2.2 (2017): 247-298] Divine Action and the World of Science: What Cosmology and Quantum Physics Teach Us about the Role of Providence in Nature1 BRUCE L. GORDON Bruce L. Gordon is Associate Professor of the History and Philosophy of Science at Houston Baptist University and a Senior Fellow of Discovery Institute’s Center for Science and Culture Abstract: Modern science has revealed a world far more exotic and wonder- provoking than our wildest imaginings could have anticipated. It is the purpose of this essay to introduce the reader to the empirical discoveries and scientific concepts that limn our understanding of how reality is structured and interconnected—from the incomprehensibly large to the inconceivably small—and to draw out the metaphysical implications of this picture. What is unveiled is a universe in which Mind plays an indispensable role: from the uncanny life-giving precision inscribed in its initial conditions, mathematical regularities, and natural constants in the distant past, to its material insubstantiality and absolute dependence on transcendent causation for causal closure and phenomenological coherence in the present, the reality we inhabit is one in which divine action is before all things, in all things, and constitutes the very basis on which all things hold together (Colossians 1:17). §1. Introduction: The Intelligible Cosmos For science to be possible there has to be order present in nature and it has to be discoverable by the human mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Macroscopic Oil Droplets Mimicking Quantum Behavior: How Far Can We Push an Analogy?
    Macroscopic oil droplets mimicking quantum behavior: How far can we push an analogy? Louis Vervoort1, Yves Gingras2 1Institut National de Recherche Scientifique (INRS), and 1Minkowski Institute, Montreal, Canada 2Université du Québec à Montréal, Montreal, Canada 29.04.2015, revised 20.10.2015 Abstract. We describe here a series of experimental analogies between fluid mechanics and quantum mechanics recently discovered by a team of physicists. These analogies arise in droplet systems guided by a surface (or pilot) wave. We argue that these experimental facts put ancient theoretical work by Madelung on the analogy between fluid and quantum mechanics into new light. After re-deriving Madelung’s result starting from two basic fluid-mechanical equations (the Navier-Stokes equation and the continuity equation), we discuss the relation with the de Broglie-Bohm theory. This allows to make a direct link with the droplet experiments. It is argued that the fluid-mechanical interpretation of quantum mechanics, if it can be extended to the general N-particle case, would have an advantage over the Bohm interpretation: it could rid Bohm’s theory of its strongly non-local character. 1. Introduction Historically analogies have played an important role in understanding or deriving new scientific results. They are generally employed to make a new phenomenon easier to understand by comparing it to a better known one. Since the beginning of modern science different kinds of analogies have been used in physics as well as in natural history and biology (for a recent historical study, see Gingras and Guay 2011). With the growing mathematization of physics, mathematical (or formal) analogies have become more frequent as a tool for understanding new phenomena; but also for proposing new interpretations and theories for such new discoveries.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (ACM30210) Set 3
    Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (ACM30210) Set 3 Dr Lennon O´ N´araigh 20th February 2020 Instructions: This is a graded assignment. • Put your name and student number on your homework. • The assignment is to be handed in on Monday March 9th before 13:00. • Hand in your assignment by putting it into the homework box marked ‘ACM 30210’ • outside the school office (G03, Science North). Model answers will be made available online in due course. • For environmental reasons, please do not place your homework in a ‘polly pocket’ • – use a staple instead. Preliminaries In these exercises, let ψ(x, t) be the wavefunction of for a single-particle system satisfying Schr¨odinger’s equation, ∂ψ ~2 i~ = 2 + U(x) ψ, (1) ∂t −2m∇ where all the symbols have their usual meaning. 1 Quantum Mechanics Madelung Transformations 1. Write ψ in ‘polar-coordinate form’, ψ(x, t) = R(x, t)eiθ(x,t), where R and θ are both functions of space and time. Show that: ∂R ~ + R2 θ =0. (2) ∂t 2mR∇· ∇ Hint: Use the ‘conservation law of probability’ in Chapter 9 of the lecture notes. 2. Define 2 R = ρm/m mR = ρm, (3a) ⇐⇒ and: p 1 θ = S/~ S = θ~, u = S. (3b) ⇐⇒ m∇ Show that Equation (4) can be re-written as: ∂ρm + (uρm)=0. (4) ∂t ∇· 3. Again using the representation ψ = Reiθ, show that S = θ~ satisfies the Quantum Hamilton–Jacobi equation: ∂S 1 ~2 2R + S 2 + U = ∇ . (5) ∂t 2m|∇ | 2m R 4. Starting with Equation (5), deduce: ∂u 1 + u u = UQ, (6) ∂t ·∇ −m∇ where UQ is the Quantum Potential, 2 2 ~ √ρm UQ = U ∇ .
    [Show full text]
  • Galaxy Formation with Ultralight Bosonic Dark Matter
    GALAXY FORMATION WITH ULTRALIGHT BOSONIC DARK MATTER Dissertation zur Erlangung des mathematisch-naturwissenschaftlichen Doktorgrades "Doctor rerum naturalium" der Georg-August-Universit¨atG¨ottingen im Promotionsstudiengang Physik der Georg-August University School of Science (GAUSS) vorgelegt von Jan Veltmaat aus Bietigheim-Bissingen G¨ottingen,2019 Betreuungsausschuss Prof. Dr. Jens Niemeyer, Institut f¨urAstrophysik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Prof. Dr. Steffen Schumann, Institut f¨urTheoretische Physik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Mitglieder der Pr¨ufungskommission Referent: Prof. Dr. Jens Niemeyer, Institut f¨urAstrophysik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Korreferent: Prof. Dr. David Marsh, Institut f¨urAstrophysik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Weitere Mitglieder der Pr¨ufungskommission: Prof. Dr. Fabian Heidrich-Meisner, Institut f¨urTheoretische Physik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Prof. Dr. Wolfram Kollatschny, Institut f¨urAstrophysik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Prof. Dr. Steffen Schumann, Institut f¨urTheoretische Physik, Universit¨atG¨ottingen Dr. Michael Wilczek, Max-Planck-Institut f¨urDynamik und Selbstorganisation, G¨ottingen Tag der m¨undlichen Pr¨ufung:12.12.2019 Abstract Ultralight bosonic particles forming a coherent state are dark matter candidates with distinctive wave-like behaviour on the scale of dwarf galaxies and below. In this thesis, a new simulation technique for ul- tralight bosonic dark matter, also called fuzzy dark matter, is devel- oped and applied in zoom-in simulations of dwarf galaxy halos. When gas and star formation are not included in the simulations, it is found that halos contain solitonic cores in their centers reproducing previous results in the literature. The cores exhibit strong quasi-normal oscil- lations, which are possibly testable by observations. The results are inconclusive regarding the long-term evolution of the core mass.
    [Show full text]
  • The Consistency of Arithmetic
    The Consistency of Arithmetic Timothy Y. Chow July 11, 2018 In 2010, Vladimir Voevodsky, a Fields Medalist and a professor at the Insti- tute for Advanced Study, gave a lecture entitled, “What If Current Foundations of Mathematics Are Inconsistent?” Voevodsky invited the audience to consider seriously the possibility that first-order Peano arithmetic (or PA for short) was inconsistent. He briefly discussed two of the standard proofs of the consistency of PA (about which we will say more later), and explained why he did not find either of them convincing. He then said that he was seriously suspicious that an inconsistency in PA might someday be found. About one year later, Voevodsky might have felt vindicated when Edward Nelson, a professor of mathematics at Princeton University, announced that he had a proof not only that PA was inconsistent, but that a small fragment of primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA)—a system that is widely regarded as implementing a very modest and “safe” subset of mathematical reasoning—was inconsistent [11]. However, a fatal error in his proof was soon detected by Daniel Tausk and (independently) Terence Tao. Nelson withdrew his claim, remarking that the consistency of PA remained “an open problem.” For mathematicians without much training in formal logic, these claims by Voevodsky and Nelson may seem bewildering. While the consistency of some axioms of infinite set theory might be debatable, is the consistency of PA really “an open problem,” as Nelson claimed? Are the existing proofs of the con- sistency of PA suspect, as Voevodsky claimed? If so, does this mean that we cannot be sure that even basic mathematical reasoning is consistent? This article is an expanded version of an answer that I posted on the Math- Overflow website in response to the question, “Is PA consistent? do we know arXiv:1807.05641v1 [math.LO] 16 Jul 2018 it?” Since the question of the consistency of PA seems to come up repeat- edly, and continues to generate confusion, a more extended discussion seems worthwhile.
    [Show full text]
  • Reformulating Bell's Theorem: the Search for a Truly Local Quantum
    Reformulating Bell's Theorem: The Search for a Truly Local Quantum Theory∗ Mordecai Waegelly and Kelvin J. McQueenz March 2, 2020 Abstract The apparent nonlocality of quantum theory has been a persistent concern. Einstein et. al. (1935) and Bell (1964) emphasized the apparent nonlocality arising from entanglement correlations. While some interpretations embrace this nonlocality, modern variations of the Everett-inspired many worlds interpretation try to circumvent it. In this paper, we review Bell's \no-go" theorem and explain how it rests on three axioms, local causality, no superdeterminism, and one world. Although Bell is often taken to have shown that local causality is ruled out by the experimentally confirmed entanglement correlations, we make clear that it is the conjunction of the three axioms that is ruled out by these correlations. We then show that by assuming local causality and no superdeterminism, we can give a direct proof of many worlds. The remainder of the paper searches for a consistent, local, formulation of many worlds. We show that prominent formulations whose ontology is given by the wave function violate local causality, and we critically evaluate claims in the literature to the contrary. We ultimately identify a local many worlds interpretation that replaces the wave function with a separable Lorentz-invariant wave-field. We conclude with discussions of the Born rule, and other interpretations of quantum mechanics. Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Local causality 3 3 Reformulating Bell's theorem 5 4 Proving Bell's theorem with many worlds 6 5 Global worlds 8 5.1 Global branching . .8 5.2 Global divergence .
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum-Like Face of Classical Mechanics
    The Quantum-like Face of Classical Mechanics Partha Ghose∗ The National Academy of Sciences, India, 5 Lajpatrai Road, Allahabad 211002, India Abstract It is first shown that when the Schr¨odinger equation for a wave function is written in the polar form, complete information about the system’s quantum-ness is separated out in a sin- gle term Q, the so called ‘quantum potential’. An operator method for classical mechanics described by a ‘classical Schr¨odinger equation’ is then presented, and its similarities and dif- ferences with quantum mechanics are pointed out. It is shown how this operator method goes beyond standard classical mechanics in predicting coherent superpositions of classical states but no interference patterns, challenging deeply held notions of classical-ness, quantum-ness and macro realism. It is also shown that measurement of a quantum system with a classical mea- suring apparatus described by the operator method does not have the measurement problem that is unavoidable when the measuring apparatus is quantum mechanical. The type of de- coherence that occurs in such a measurement is contrasted with the conventional decoherence mechanism. The method also provides a more convenient basis to delve deeper into the area of quantum-classical correspondence and information processing than exists at present. 1 Introduction The hallmark of quantum mechanics is the characterization of physical states by vectors in a Hilbert space with observables represented by Hermitean operators that do not all commute. The description is non-realist and non-causal. On the other hand, physical states in standard classical mechanics are points in phase space, all observables commute, and the description is realist and causal.
    [Show full text]
  • Irving Ezra Segal (1918–1998)
    mem-segal.qxp 5/12/99 12:57 PM Page 659 Irving Ezra Segal (1918–1998) John C. Baez, Edwin F. Beschler, Leonard Gross, Bertram Kostant, Edward Nelson, Michèle Vergne, and Arthur S. Wightman Irving Segal died suddenly on August 30, 1998, After the war while taking an evening walk. He was seventy-nine Segal spent two and was vigorously engaged in research. years at the Insti- Born on September 13, 1918, in the Bronx, he tute for Advanced grew up in Trenton and received his A.B. from Study, where he Princeton in 1937. What must it have been like to held the first of the be a member of the Jewish quota at Princeton in three Guggenheim the 1930s? He told me once that a fellow under- Fellowships that he graduate offered him money to take an exam in his was to win. Other stead and was surprised when Irving turned him honors included down. election to the Na- He received his Ph.D. from Yale in 1940. His the- tional Academy of sis was written under the nominal direction of Sciences in 1973 Einar Hille, who suggested that Segal continue his and the Humboldt Award in 1981. At and Tamarkin’s investigation of the ideal theory the University of of the algebra of Laplace-Stieltjes transforms ab- Chicago from 1948 solutely convergent in a fixed half-plane. But, Segal to 1960, he had fif- wrote, “For conceptual clarification and for other teen doctoral stu- reasons, an investigation of the group algebra of dents, and at MIT, a general [locally compact] abelian group was of where he was pro- Irving Segal interest.” And the thesis was not restricted to fessor from 1960 abelian groups.
    [Show full text]
  • Michail Zaka
    1 From quantum mechanics to intelligent particle. Michail Zak a Jet Propulsion Laboratory California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91109, USA The challenge of this work is to connect quantum mechanics with the concept of intelligence. By intelligence we understand a capability to move from disorder to order without external resources, i.e. in violation of the second law of thermodynamics. The objective is to find such a mathematical object described by ODE that possesses such a capability. The proposed approach is based upon modification of the Madelung version of the Schrodinger equation by replacing the force following from quantum potential with non-conservative forces that link to the concept of information. A mathematical formalism suggests that a hypothetical intelligent particle, besides the capability to move against the second law of thermodynamics, acquires such properties like self-image, self-awareness, self- supervision, etc. that are typical for Livings. However since this particle being a quantum-classical hybrid acquires non-Newtonian and non-quantum properties, it does not belong to the physics matter as we know it: the modern physics should be complemented with the concept of an information force that represents a bridge to intelligent particle. It has been suggested that quantum mechanics should be complemented by the intelligent particle as an independent entity, and that will be the necessary step to physics of Life. At this stage, the intelligent particle is introduced as an abstract mathematical concept that is satisfied only mathematical rules and assumptions, and its physical representation is still an open problem. 1. Introduction. The recent statement about completeness of the physical picture of our Universe made in Geneva raised many questions, and one of them is the ability to create Life and Mind out of physical matter without any additional entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Non-Equilibrium in Stochastic Mechanics Guido Bacciagaluppi
    Non-equilibrium in Stochastic Mechanics Guido Bacciagaluppi To cite this version: Guido Bacciagaluppi. Non-equilibrium in Stochastic Mechanics. Journal of Physics: Conference Series, IOP Publishing, 2012, 361, pp.1-12. 10.1088/1742-6596/361/1/012017. halshs-00999721 HAL Id: halshs-00999721 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00999721 Submitted on 4 Jun 2014 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Non-equilibrium in Stochastic Mechanics Guido Bacciagaluppi∗ Department of Philosophy, University of Aberdeen Institut d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques (CNRS, Paris 1, ENS) Abstract The notion of non-equilibrium, in the sense of a particle distribution other than ρ = |ψ|2, is imported into Nelson’s stochastic mechanics, and described in terms of effective wavefunctions obeying non-linear equations. These techniques are applied to the discussion of non-locality in non-linear Schr¨odinger equations. 1 Introduction The ideal of quantum mechanics as an emergent theory is well represented by Nelson’s stochastic mechanics, which aims at recovering quantum mechanics from an underlying stochastic process in configuration space. More precisely, as we sketch in Section 2, Nelson starts from a time-reversible description of a diffu- sion process in configuration space, and then introduces some (time-symmetric) dynamical conditions on the process, leading to the Madelung equations for two real functions R and S, which are implied by the Schr¨odinger equation for ψ = ReiS/~.
    [Show full text]
  • 1995 Steele Prizes
    steele.qxp 4/27/98 3:29 PM Page 1288 1995 Steele Prizes Three Leroy P. Steele Prizes were presented at The text that follows contains, for each award, the awards banquet during the Summer Math- the committee’s citation, the recipient’s response fest in Burlington, Vermont, in early August. upon receiving the award, and a brief bio- These prizes were established in 1970 in honor graphical sketch of the recipient. of George David Birkhoff, William Fogg Osgood, and William Caspar Graustein Edward Nelson: 1995 Steele Prize for and are endowed under the Seminal Contribution to Research terms of a bequest from The 1995 Leroy P. Steele award for research of Leroy P. Steele. seminal importance goes to Professor Edward The Steele Prizes are Nelson of Princeton University for the following ...for a research awarded in three categories: two papers in mathematical physics character- for a research paper of fun- ized by leaders of the field as extremely innov- paper of damental and lasting impor- ative: tance, for expository writing, 1. “A quartic interaction in two dimensions” in fundamental and for cumulative influence Mathematical Theory of Elementary Particles, and lasting extending over a career, in- MIT Press, 1966, pages 69–73; cluding the education of doc- 2. “Construction of quantum fields from Markoff importance, toral students. The current fields” in Journal of Functional Analysis 12 award is $4,000 in each cate- (1973), 97–112. for expository gory. In these papers he showed for the first time The recipients of the 1995 how to use the powerful tools of probability writing, and for Steele Prizes are Edward Nel- theory to attack the hard analytic questions of son for seminal contribution constructive quantum field theory, controlling cumulative to research, Jean-Pierre Serre renormalizations with Lp estimates in the first influence for mathematical exposition, paper and, in the second, turning Euclidean and John T.
    [Show full text]
  • Edward Nelson (1932-2014) 3
    EDWARD NELSON (1932-2014) MIKHAIL G. KATZ AND SEMEN S. KUTATELADZE On September 10, 2014 we lost Edward Nelson, one of the most original and controversial mathematical thinkers of our time. Nelson was born on May 4, 1932 in Decatur, Georgia. His father spoke fluent Russian, having spent some time in St. Petersburg in con- nection with issues related to prisoners of war (Nelson 1995 [11]). Nel- son was educated at the University of Chicago. In 1953 he was awarded a master’s degree, and in 1955 he earned a doctorate under the super- vision of Irving Segal, an expert in mathematical methods of quantum mechanics and functional analysis and one of the founders of the theory of C*-algebras. Not surprisingly, Nelson’s early papers were devoted to quantum mechanics. In 1995, Nelson received the Steele prize awarded by the American Mathematical Society, for his 1963 and 1977 papers on applications of probability theory to quantum fluctuations. After graduating, Nelson spent three years at Princeton’s Institute for Advanced Study, and from 1959 until his retirement in 2013, he worked at Princeton University where he became a Professor in 1964. In his memory the university flag was raised at half-mast for three days. In 1975 Nelson was elected to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, and in 1997, to the National Academy of Sciences of the USA. Princeton University Press published the following six monographs by Nelson: arXiv:1506.01570v1 [math.HO] 4 Jun 2015 (1) Dynamical theories of Brownian motion. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J.
    [Show full text]