Jewish Dimensions of Idealism and Idealist Dimensions of Judaism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Jewish Dimensions of Idealism and Idealist Dimensions of Judaism Rabbinic Idealism and Kabbalistic Realism: Jewish Dimensions of Idealism and Idealist Dimensions of Judaism (forthcoming in The Impact of Idealism, general editor Nicholas Boyle, editor of volume on theology Nicholas Adams) Paul Franks For over two centuries, Jewish philosophy and post-Kantian Idealism, have been intertwined. Habermas has rightly noted “the German Idealism of the Jewish philosophers”, asking how, given the Christian or post-Christian character of Idealism, this intimacy is possible.1 In what follows, I offer an answer. First, however, I will deepen the puzzle. For what is internal to Idealism is not only Christianity or post-Christianity, but specifically the claim that Christianity or post-Christianity has superseded Judaism. Accordingly, Idealism constitutes a challenge to Judaism, which must justify its continued existence in the modern world. This makes it more puzzling that Idealism has attracted so many Jewish philosophers. To solve this puzzle, it is necessary to show that both Kantian and post-Kantian Idealism have what I will call Jewish dimensions – namely, rabbinic Idealism and kabbalistic Realism.2 By articulating these dimensions, Jewish philosophy has contributed to the inner development of Idealism. Moreover, by reappropriating these dimensions as Jewish, Jewish philosophers have found within Idealism the resources to respond to the Idealist challenge, by demonstrating that Judaism has not been superseded. The seeds of all these developments lie in works by Salomon Maimon, published between 1790 and 1793.3 In a sadly illuminating illustration of Idealism’s complex relationship to Judaism and Jewishness, Kant said of Maimon, “none of my critics understood me or the main questions so well.”4 He also complained about Maimon’s proposed “improvement” of the critical response to 1 these questions that, “Jews always like . to gain an air of importance for themselves at someone else’s expense.”5 The anti-Judaic trope is all too familiar. Anxiety concerning Christianity’s derivativeness from Judaism and Judaism’s capacity for vitality under adverse conditions gives rise to the prejudice that Jews cannot be original, and that, since Jewish promotion is always undeserved, it must always involve some non-Jew’s unfair demotion. Maimon was interested only in contributing to philosophy. His successors were also interested in showing that Judaism deserved to survive in the modern world. I: The Idealist Challenge to Judaism Karl Leonhard Reinhold, the first German Idealist, made Kant’s philosophy famous by presenting it as “the gospel of pure reason” that would resolve, once and for all, the conflict between reason and faith.6 Whether the various forms of Kantian and post-Kantian Idealism are Christian or post-Christian need not be decided here. Driven by their distinctive interest in the rationality of history and the history of reason, these philosophies inherit Christianity’s need to negotiate its relationship with its precursor: with Judaism, or whatever serves as its structural analogue. At one extreme lies Marcionism: the view that Christianity is the antagonist of Judaism, to which it owes exactly nothing. At the opposite extreme lie views that ascribe continuing roles to both Christianity and Judaism. Various views lie in between, including the supersessionist view that Judaism should not only acknowledge Christianity as its fulfillment, but should cease to exist once Christianity has arrived.7 The presupposition of Idealist discussions of Judaism is that Torah is, above all, law. Two millennia earlier, the Septuagint had translated “Torah” as “nomos”. However, what was once the law of nature, or the law that imitated nature, had become, in Spinoza’s hands, a political arrangement, vestige of a vanished state.8 2 Kant saw one aspect of the law – the prohibition of the representation of God – as sublime.9 But in the rest of the Mosaic law he saw no sublimity. Given by a deity external to reason, the Torah was surely heteronomous. Indeed, since religion consisted of the faith and hope required for morality, and since morality was autonomous, Judaism was not religion but politics. Yet, precisely because of Judaism’s sublime idea of an unrepresentable God, it was especially dangerous. Unlike the demands of desire, Judaism could be mistaken for morality. The purification of religion would require “the euthanasia of Judaism” – from Christianity as well as from Judaism itself.10 Kant was so insistent that Jesus “appeared as though descended from heaven”, taking nothing from Judaism, that Fichte’s neo-Marcionism becomes intelligible.11 He regarded Judaism as misanthropic, and retained only the Gospel of John. Hegel and Schelling, however, were supersessionists. Indeed, the Christianity’s supersession of Judaism was a principal model for their versions of sublation. On the one hand, supersession is an abstraction, an idealization of ancient history. On the other, Idealist sublation finds in concrete, actual Judaism one of its principal applications. Hegel and Schelling inherited Kant’s idea that Judaism was especially dangerous because it represented the stage immediately prior to salvation, where consciousness could easily become paralyzed, as if mesmerized by slavery in the guise of freedom.12 But they did not share Kant’s formal conception of freedom as autonomy. What Judaism lacked, in Hegel’s view, was a collective identification with the Lord that would give human action as such an essential role in God’s recognition of Godself in the other, which alone could reconcile infinity with finitude. This lack explained why Judaism had remained frozen for millennia: parochially particular and excluded from history’s march towards the universality of the absolute religion, which was at last in view. A major debate of the time was whether, a thousand years after their civil rights were removed by the Christianized Roman Empire, Jews should become citizens of the modern 3 European states that were superseding Christendom. That Jews should, as humans and as residents, become citizens, was agreed by Kant, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel. Disagreement focused on whether Jews should shed their Judaism as a pre-condition of emancipation or as its consequence.13 That Judaism should be dispensed with was beyond question. Within Idealism’s modern world, Jews as humans would be welcome. But Jews as Jews would find no place. This was the new, Idealist version of the Christian challenge that Jewish philosophy would have to face after Kant. II: Kant, Plato and Rabbinic Idealism Kant’s critical philosophy has an explicitly Platonic dimension. After the Aristotelian emphasis of the Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason on cognition’s need for both intelligible form and sensible matter, it is striking that, in the Dialectic, Kant insists on the necessity for ideas too: rational forms that wholly transcend the senses and that are incapable of instantiation by sensible matter. These ideas play an essential role in setting the ends of cognition and also in the transition from theoretical to practical philosophy, where they provide the structure of rational faith. It is in this context that Kant claims to understand Plato better than Plato understood himself.14 Aristobulus, the first known Jewish philosopher, is said to have claimed that Plato knew the laws of Moses.15 To be sure, the high point of medieval Jewish philosophy is often said to occur with Maimonides, who did not admire his more Platonic predecessors, and who affirmed as true every Aristotelian statement about the sublunar realm.16 But, like other Arabic-speaking “Aristotelians”, there was more Platonism and Neo-Platonism in Maimonides’ view than he could have known, thanks to texts such as the Theology of Aristotle, actually an epitome of Plotinus’ Enneads. Moreover, precisely because of Maimonides’ self-professed Aristotelianism, Plato was favoured by those who opposed Maimonides’ radical rationalism in the name of “kabbalah” or tradition received from an authoritative source. 4 The association with Platonism was reinforced during the Renaissance by Pico della Mirandola, who had an entire library of kabbalistic texts translated from Hebrew and Aramaic, just as Marcilio Ficino had translated previously unknown Platonic texts. Both kabbalah and Platonism were presented as prisca theologia, anticipating Christianity. Simultaneously, open practitioners of Judaism were expelled from the Iberian peninsula, revitalizing kabbalistic thought in Renaissance Italy, and the idea of an accord between kabbalah and Platonism became more important to kabbalistically inclined Jewish writers. Thus, Isaac Abarbanel, a distinguished Iberian Jew taking refuge in Italy, wrote that Jeremiah was Plato’s teacher,17 and it became commonplace to compare Platonic ideas to the kabbalistic sefirot: the ten numbers or divine attributes mediating between the infinite and the created, finite world.18 Even when new and less Platonic waves of kabbalistic thinking spread from the Galilee throughout the Jewish world in the seventeenth century, they appeared initially in a Neo-Platonic guise, both in the Jewish community beyond the Land of Israel, and among the Christians who gained access to kabbalistic works only in the late seventeenth century, with the massive translation project of the Kabbala Denudata.19 In the words of Abraham Herrera, author of one of the translated works, “we follow our ḥakhamim or wise men sages and the Platonic philosophers who, being more divine [than the Peripatetics], are
Recommended publications
  • Lotze and the Early Cambridge Analytic Philosophy
    LOTZE AND THE EARLY CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY ―This summer I‘ve read about a half of Lotze‘s Metaphysik. He is the most delectable, certainly, of all German writers—a pure genius.‖ William James, September 8, 1879.1 Summary Many historians of analytic philosophy consider the early philosophy of Moore, Russell and Wittgenstein as much more neo-Hegelian as once believed. At the same time, the authors who closely investigate Green, Bradley and Bosanquet find out that these have little in common with Hegel. The thesis advanced in this chapter is that what the British (ill-named) neo-Hegelians brought to the early analytic philosophers were, above all, some ideas of Lotze, not of Hegel. This is true regarding: (i) Lotze’s logical approach to practically all philosoph- ical problems; (ii) his treating of the concepts relation, structure (constructions) and order; (iii) the discussion of the concepts of states of affairs, multiple theory of judgment, general logical form; (iv) some common themes like panpsychism and contemplating the world sub specie aeternitatis. 1. LOTZE, NOT HEGEL, LIES AT THE BOTTOM OF CAMBRIDGE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY Conventional wisdom has it that the early philosophy of Moore and Russell was under the strong sway of the British ―neo-Hegelians‖. In the same time, however, those historians who investigate the British ―neo-Hegelians‖ of 1880–1920 in detail, turn attention to the fact that the latter are not necessarily connected with Hegel: William Sweet made this point in regard to 1 Perry (1935), ii, p. 16. Bosanquet,2 Geoffrey Thomas in regard to Green,3 and Peter Nicholson in regard to Bradley.4 Finally, Nicholas Griffin has shown that Russell from 1895–8, then an alleged neo-Hegelian, ―was very strongly influenced by Kant and hardly at all by Hegel‖.5 These facts are hardly surprising, if we keep in mind that the representatives of the school of T.
    [Show full text]
  • ACTA UNIVERSITATIS UPSALIENSIS Uppsala Studies in History of Ideas 48
    ACTA UNIVERSITATIS UPSALIENSIS Uppsala Studies in History of Ideas 48 ANDREAS RYDBERG Inner Experience An Analysis of Scientific Experience in Early Modern Germany Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen (Eng6-1023), Engelska Parken, Humanistiskt centrum, Thunbergsvägen 3P, Uppsala, Friday, 9 June 2017 at 10:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in Swedish. Faculty examiner: Kristiina Savin (Lunds universitet, Institutionen för kulturvetenskaper). Abstract Rydberg, A. 2017. Inner Experience. An Analysis of Scientific Experience in Early Modern Germany. Uppsala Studies in History of Ideas 48. 245 pp. Uppsala: Acta Universitatis Upsaliensis. ISBN 978-91-554-9926-6. In the last decades a number of studies have shed light on early modern scientific experience. While some of these studies have focused on how new facts were forced out of nature in so-called experimental situations, others have charted long-term transformations. In this dissertation I explore a rather different facet of scientific experience by focusing on the case of the Prussian university town Halle in the period from the late seventeenth till the mid-eighteenth century. At this site philosophers, theologians and physicians were preoccupied with categories such as inner senses , inner experience, living experience, psychological experiments and psychometrics. In the study I argue that these hitherto almost completely overlooked categories take us away from observations of external things to the internal organisation of experience and to entirely internal objects of experience. Rather than seeing this internal side of scientific experience as mere theory and epistemology, I argue that it was an integral and central part of what has been referred to as the cultura animi tradition, that is, the philosophical and medical tradition of approaching the soul as something in need of cultivation, education, disciplination and cure.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science"
    "Hermann Cohen's History and Philosophy of Science" Lydia Patton Department of Philosophy McGill University, Montreal October, 2004 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree ofPh.D. © Lydia Patton 2004 Library and Bibliothèque et 1+1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de l'édition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada Your file Votre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 Our file Notre référence ISBN: 0-494-06335-1 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant à la Bibliothèque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par télécommunication ou par l'Internet, prêter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des thèses partout dans loan, distribute and sell th es es le monde, à des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, électronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriété du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protège cette thèse. this thesis. Neither the thesis Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels de nor substantial extracts from it celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés ou autrement may be printed or otherwise reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Psychology Faculty Publications Psychology 1982 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/psychology-faculty- publications Part of the Theory and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Leary, David E. "Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology." In The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth- Century Thought, edited by William Ray Woodward and Mitchell G. Ash, 17-42. New York, NY: Praeger, 1982. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary Few thinkers in the history of Western civilization have had as broad and lasting an impact as Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). This "Sage of Konigsberg" spent his entire life within the confines of East Prussia, but his thoughts traveled freely across Europe and, in time, to America, where their effects are still apparent. An untold number of analyses and commentaries have established Kant as a preeminent epistemologist, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, aestheti­ cian, and metaphysician. He is even recognized as a natural historian and cosmologist: the author of the so-called Kant-Laplace hypothesis regarding the origin of the universe. He is less often credited as a "psychologist," "anthropologist," or "philosopher of mind," to Work on this essay was supported by the National Science Foundation (Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Logik by Rudolf Hermann Lotze: the Concept of Geltung
    The Logik by Rudolf Hermann Lotze: the concept of Geltung Michele Vagnetti Abstract: The subject of this paper is Rudolf Hermann of his Logik,2 published in Lipsia in 1874. The original Lotze’s concept of Geltung as him outlines it in the sec- version, first printed in Berlin in 1843, merges completely ond Logik (1874). This paper, through the notions of into the first book of the 1874 edition and is entitled Vom gnoseological immanentism and anti-psychologism, aims Denken. The subject of this first part of Lotze's Logik is to shed light on the notion of validity (Geltung). The Gel- not new, dealing as it does with formal logic and the theo- tung’s concept is very interesting not only for the role that ries of concept, judgment and syllogism. However, the it plays in Lotze’s philosophy, but also for the importance second (Vom Untersuchen) and the third (Vom Erkennen) that Lotze’s validity has in the philosophical debate until books go on to discuss applied logic (Angewandte Logik) the 1930s. and the theory of knowledge. It was precisely this ex- panded version of Logik, the first part of a System der Keywords: Lotze, Geltung, Logik, Gnoseological Imma- Philosophie, which Lotze never completed, that aroused nentism, Anti-Psychologism. such interest in so many academic philosophers. The concept of validity (Geltung) is central to the en- tire 1874 work and it must therefore be analysed carefully A brief introduction to the theme of «validity» in so as to understand both its origin and its significance for Lotze's Logik academic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermann Lotze and Franz Brentano Dr
    Hermann Lotze and Franz Brentano Dr. Nikolay Milkov 1. The Neo-Brentanists Franz Brentano was not a solitary figure who propounded his philosophy in lonely isolation from other contemporary philosophers in Germany, as some neo-Brentanists have claimed over the last thirty to forty years. The aim in what follows is to correct such misconceptions by establishing that Brentano developed his philosophical psychology while actively engaged in the rich intellectual-historical and academic context of his time—in particular, under the influence of Hermann Lotze. The misleading image of Brentano as a solitary genius promulgated by the likes of Neo-Brentanists such as Barry Smith is analogous to the picture of Gottlob Frege passed off as historical truth by influential Neo-Fregeans—Michael Dummett, for one. In both cases, we find a distinguished thinker portrayed as the reclusive, solitary man of genius. Thanks, however, to the researches of Hans Sluga, Gottfried Gabriel, and others, we now know that in the case of Frege it was as an active player in the culture of nineteenth-century German philosophy that he propounded the innovations in symbolic logic for which he is famous. The same holds for Franz Brentano and the introduction of his philosophical psychology, as we shall see presently by probing and assessing the historical, epistolary, and textual evidence. As opposed to the image of the neo-Brentanists, Brentano in no way saw himself as an intellectually and institutionally isolated thinker, and he certainly never represented himself as such. In perhaps his most important work, Psychology from an empirical Standpoint, Brentano admitted that “his view, at least from one side or the other, had already begun” to be developed by other authors before him (1874, 4).
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemology1 Niels Wildschut
    This is the penultimate draft of an article that is published in Martin Kusch, Katherina Kinzel, Johannes Steizinger, Niels Wildschut (eds.): The Emergence of Relativism: German Thought from the Enlightenment to National Socialism Epistemology1 Niels Wildschut From the moment Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) declared that “nature” was nothing but the whole of experience, and that any enquiry into nature first required a critical assessment of the necessary preconditions and limitations of experience, many philosophers began to see it as their central task to provide the sciences with their epistemological foundations. In the nineteenth century, however, the Kantian self-understanding of the philosopher was also challenged from various sides. For example, the institutionalization of history as a scientific discipline raised the question: How can the philosopher’s methodologies of critique and of transcendental deduction be reconciled with the insight that all of life on earth, including the philosopher’s own standpoint, is thoroughly historical? Furthermore, various natural sciences posed their own challenges to philosophy, for example by uncovering the psycho-physiological processes within human cognition, and by stressing the very earthly and material nature of the soul (and thus presumably also of the “transcendental subject”). From within Kant’s transcendental philosophy, many of these challenges seemed easy to block. Within the scientific community as well as the general (and rapidly expanding) reading public, however, these Kantian defenses
    [Show full text]
  • History of Ontology from Suã¡Rez to Kant (1597-1781)
    History of Ontology from Suárez to Kant (1597-1781) https://www.ontology.co/history.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Birth of a New Science: the History of Ontology from Suárez to Kant INTRODUCTION "To begin with we want to state that ontology should be seen only as an interdiscipline involving both philosophy and science. It is a discipline which points out the problems of the foundations of the sciences as well as the borderline questions, and which further attempts to solve these problems and questions. Ontology is not a discipline which exists separately and independently from all the other scientific disciplines and also from other branches of philosophy. Rather, ontology derives the general structure of the world; it obtains the structure of the world as it really is from knowledge embodied in other disciplines. If one examines the history of philosophy one sees that ontology has never solved or attempted to solve the questions about the structures of our world independently, apart from the other philosophical disciplines or apart from the sciences. As is expressed by this symposium's topic, "Language and Ontology", ontology has derived the world's structure from other disciplines which describe reality, and has thus relied upon the languages of other disciplines. A common belief is that this derivation of the world's most general structures from the knowledge of other disciplines is ontology's only task. But now the belief is that in doing ontology one always selects the most important and most general laws from among all the laws which the various disciplines have to offer at any given time.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Debt to Lotze Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci
    Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 39 (2008) 186–193 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Russell’s debt to Lotze Nikolay Milkov Institut für Humanwissenschaften: Philosophie, Universität Paderborn, Warburger Straße 100, D–33098 Paderborn, Germany article info abstract Keywords: Between 1896 and 1898 Russell’s philosophy was considerably influenced by Hermann Lotze. Lotze’s Anthropology influence on Russell was especially pronounced in introducing metaphysical—anthropological, in partic- Judgement ular—assumptions in Russell’s logic and ontology. Three steps in his work reflect this influence. (i) The G. E. Moore first such step can be discerned in the Principle of Differentiation, which Russell accepted in the Essay R. H. Lotze (finished in October 1986); according to this Principle, the objects of human cognition are segmented B. Russell Space complexes which have diverse parts (individuals). (ii) After Russell reread Lotze in June 1897, he claimed Time that the solution of the dilemma of pluralism or monism depends on how we see space and time: as rela- tional or as adjectival? (iii) Russell decided for the relational conception only after he attended lectures by McTaggart on Lotze in January to February 1898. The lectures helped Russell to advance (from April to June 1898) a new theory of judgment according to which judgments relate terms (individuals) which are distinct one from another. Space and time moreover are series of moments and places with external relations between themselves. The discussions Russell had with Moore in May to June 1898 took place only after Russell developed this conception; they did not cause his philosophical turn.
    [Show full text]
  • Phd in Philosophy
    PhD in Philosophy CYCLE XXXII COORDINATOR Prof. Adriano Fabris Hermann Lotze on the Mind–Body Problem and the 19th Century Philosophy and Psychology: With Special Attention to William James Academic Discipline (SSD) M-FIL/06 Doctoral Candidate Supervisors Michele Vagnetti Prof. Alessandro Pagnini Apl. Prof. Dr. Nikolay Milkov Coordinator Prof. Fabris Adriano Years 2017/2020 CONTENTS 1. Preliminary remarks on Hermann Lotze’s metaphysics 1 1.1. Lotze on science and metaphysics 1 1.2. Lotze’s atomism 6 1.3. Philosophy of space: metaphysics and geometry 12 2. Physiological and psychological studies in the first half of the 19th century 26 2.1. The study of the nervous system 26 2.2. Hermann Lotze on phrenology and the question of the location of the mind 35 2.3. Three scientific psychologists 39 2.3.1. Ernst Heinrich Weber 39 2.3.2. Gustav Theodor Fechner 44 2.3.3. Alfred Wilhelm Volkmann 53 3. The reductionist approach to the mind–body problem and its critics 54 3.1. Hermann von Helmholtz 56 3.2. The dispute between Büchner and Lotze 60 3.3. Two further scholars 64 3.3.1. J. F. Herbart 64 3.3.2. J. F. Fries 69 4. Hermann Lotze on the relation between body and mind 78 4.1. Pilosophical psychology and perspectivism 86 4.2. Physiological psychology between materialism and mentalism 94 4.3. The psycho-physical mechanism: the occasionalist way 103 I 4.4. The psycho-physical mechanism: the interaction 110 4.5. Lotze’s theory of local signs 113 4.6.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology: Common Roots, Related Results
    Early Analytic Philosophy and Phenomenology: Common Roots, Related Results Abstract In this paper we shall open a perspective from which the relatedness between the early analytic philosophy and Husserl‘s phenomenology is so close that we can call the two programs with one name: ―rigorous philosophy‖, or ―theory of forms‖. Moreover, we shall show that the close relatedness between the two most influential philosophical movements of the 20th century has its roots in their common history. At the end of the paper we shall try to answer the question why being rather related at the beginning, their ways parted in the subsequent years. 1. Introduction In what follows, we are going to use the results we have achieved in our investigation of the relatedness and difference between Husserl‘s and Russell‘s philosophy in another paper (cf. Milkov 2016a) in order to outline the relatedness between Husserl‘s phenomenology and the early analytic philosophy in general—two movements that dominated the philosophy of the twentieth century. We shall try to set out why they were closely related, pointing at their common theoretical roots and common ancestors, and also why did they develop in different directions. Moreover, we shall try to formulate their common denominator, in particular as developed immediately after 1917–18 by the later Husserl and the later Russell, but also by the first generation of their acolytes. 2. Common roots: the German logocentrism in philosophy The first point we would like to underline discussing this problem is that there was one common theoretical source of the early analytic philosophy and phenomenology and it was the movement of logicization of philosophy that started in Germany with Leibniz, was continued by Christian Wolff, J.
    [Show full text]
  • Excerpt from Medicinische Psychologie Oder Physiologie Der Seele G
    Excerpt from Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele G. E. Berrios To cite this version: G. E. Berrios. Excerpt from Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele. History of Psychi- atry, SAGE Publications, 2005, 16 (1), pp.117-127. 10.1177/0957154X05052531. hal-00570824 HAL Id: hal-00570824 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00570824 Submitted on 1 Mar 2011 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. HPY 16(1) Classic Text 61 1/28/05 9:13 AM Page 1 History of Psychiatry, 16(1): 117–127 Copyright © 2005 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) www.sagepublications.com [200503] DOI: 10.1177/0957154X05052531 Classic Text No. 61 Excerpt from Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele* by Dr Rudolph Hermann Lotze Introduction and translation by G. E. BERRIOS** Hermann Lotze (1817–81) is a neglected figure in the history of psychiatry although it has been claimed that his early views were influential, for example, on the young Griesinger. Trained as a physician, psychologist and philosopher he saw better than many the impending epistemological crisis that was to affect disciplines such as psychology and medical psychology as they were being taken over by the natural sciences.
    [Show full text]