<<

IOSR Journal of Mathematics (IOSR-JM)

e-ISSN: 2278-5728,p-ISSN: 2319-765X, Volume 7, Issue 4 (Jul. - Aug. 2013), PP 43-47 www.iosrjournals.org

A new argument for the non-existence of Closed Timelike

Sanath Devalapurkar1 1(Physics, Center for Fundamental Research and Creative Education, India)

Abstract: In this paper, we attempt to present a short argument, different from that of the original proofs by that of Hawking, for a theorem stated that no closed timelike curves can exist. In a later paper, we apply this to quantum gravity and relate the of to this theorem. Also, we present this paper as a preliminary introduction to the complete argument of this, and we also provide a preliminary notion of the concepts which will be narrated in the later papers. We also use this as a starting basis for a true for a theory of everything. We use the notation of [1] and of [2]. Keywords: Theoretical Physics, Quantum Gravity, , , Quantum Mechanics

I. The elimination of Closed Timelike Curves in Loop Quantum Gravity Theorem : There exists no closed timelike in the physical world. To prove this, we introduce spacetime as (ℳ, (4)푔) where we can define ℳ as a four dimensional and (4)푔 as a Lorentzian metric on it. In the third part, we introduce a ADM 3 + 1 split of the four dimensional (ℳ, (4)푔). II. ADM 3+1 split of classical four dimensional (퓜, (ퟒ)품) In this section, we mainly reconstruct the topics in [1]. To do a 3+1 split of classical four dimensional (ℳ, (4)푔), we need (ℳ, (4)푔) to be homeomorphic to the direct product space formed by ℝ × 훴, where 훴 is a three-manifold representing space and 푡 ∈ ℝ represents time. (ℳ, (4)푔) needs to be globally hyperbolic, and we assume , that is, no closed timelike curves (CTC) exist. We define closed timelike curves in the following manner. A curve 휋 such that, we have, in a particular coordinate system 픎 on (ℳ, (4)푔), the following equations satisfied: 휋: 푆1 → (ℳ, (4)푔) 1)

And in a shifted coordinate system, 픎1, we have 푔(휋픎1, 휋픎1) < 0 2)

This allows us to state that the time function is regular. A particular slicing of spacetime, though, would be a matter of choice. A choice of slicing is equivalent to the choice of a regular function $f$ (i.e., a scalar field on (ℳ, (4)푔)) for which 휕휇 푡 is timelike.

Suppose there exist two spaces, so that there is a mapping of some sort between them, defined as Proposition 1: 푓 on 𝒜 maps to ℬ. Then, it could be said that {푓} is a space itself, multiplied (i.e., it forms a product space with) by 𝒜 to yield ℬ. Then we could say that {푓} = ℬ/𝒜. I.e., if 푓: 𝒜 → ℬ 3)

Then we have {푓} = ℬ/𝒜 4)

Proof: If 푓 is defined as 푓: 𝒜 → ℬ 5)

Then we need ℬ and 𝒜 to have their points as discrete eigenvalues of some operator corresponding to each space (we wish to call this the soperator). Thus, as 푓 should have eigenvalues corresponding to each soperator, we need 푓 to eigenvalues which exist in both the spaces, which is obviously the union of the two, which is given by

www.iosrjournals.org 43 | Page A new argument for the non-existence of Closed Timelike Curves

{푓} = ℬ/𝒜 6) ∎ −1 The regular values of 푓 then form 3-, our 훴, defined by 훴(푡0) = 푓 (푡0). Using the submersion theorem, we can find a local coordinate system {푥휇 } over the open set 푈, where ∀ 푝 ∈ 푈, 푓(푝) = 푓(푥0(푝), 푥1 (푝), 푥2(푝), 푥3(푝)) = 푥0(푝). The 1-form 푑푓 is then 푑푥0 and the intrinsic coordinates of each hypersurface are given by 푥1 , 푥2, 푥3. 휕 Thus the vectors 휕 : = span the target space to each hypersurface. We can express the components of each 훼 휕푥 푎 훼 vector field in terms of a general basis {푦 } as 푒푣 : 휕 휕푥푎 휕 7) = =: 푒훼 휕 휕푥푣 휕푥푣 푦훼 푣 훼

Similar to [1], √4 means the metric dual to 푑푥0 . We have a vector field 0 √4 (4) 0 (4) 0푣 (푑푥 ) : = 푔(푑푥 ,∙) = ( 푔) 휕푣 8)

(4) 0푣 휇 Thus the vector field with components 휕푣푓 or ( 푔) is a normal to the hypersurface. If 푛 is the unit 휇 normal to 훴, then on decomposing 휕0 into its components parallel to the hypersurface 푁 and orthogonal to is 푁푛휇 , we obtain

휕0 = 푁푛 + 푁 9)

0 Since we have 푑푥 (휕0) = 1, we see that we must have −푁2 = ((4)푔)00 = −||푑푥0||2 10)

III. Loop Part We first look at Definition 1.0.2. So, we can define elements of a curve as Definition : If there exists a curve 훾, then the elements of it are its 푥, 푦, 푧 and/or 푡 components, given 푎 by 훾 , or by 훾푎 . So, using this convention, we have a new definition of a : Definition : A curve 휋 such that, we have, in a particular coordinate system 픎 on (ℳ, (4)푔), the following equations satisfied: 휋: 푆1 → (ℳ, (4)푔) 11)

And in a shifted coordinate system, 픎1, we have (4) 픎1 푎 픎1 푏 ( 푔)푎푏 휋 , 휋 < 0 12)

We then define a set of all possible timelike curves defined by 휋: 푆1 → (ℳ, (4)푔). This set we call the timelike loop space of (ℳ, (4)푔) and call it 훺(ℳ, (4)푔). Now, if we consider our coordinate system change, to the system 픎1, we would have the following: 훺 ℳ, 4 푔 = ∅ 13)

Therefore, we may define the coordinate shift such that the causal structure makes the timelike loops (that is, curves) to vanish and therefore make 훺 ℳ, 4 푔 = ∅. The 휋픎1 may lie on ℝ or 훴. If 휋픎1 lies on 훴, then we need 휋픎1 to lie on the regular values of 푓. But the introduction of a metric in ℳ, 4 푔 induces a metric on 훴, which in turn causes a causal structure to be formed. Since spacetime is not necessarily Ricci flat, 휋픎1 must, to introduce a causal structure on ℳ, 4 푔 , exist on ℝ. Then we may define ℝ as having no causal structure. The coordinate shift creates the closed timelike curves on the ℝ, and therefore a restriction of vectors tangential to ℝ must not exist. This is wrong. But ℝ is Riemannian, therefore 휋픎1 must not exist. That is, slicing causing closed timelike curves do not exist. This means that all slicings of ℝ × 훴 have no closed timelike curves in them, even on coordinate shifts, and therefore ℳ, 4 푔 is globally hyperbolic, ∀ ℳ, 4 푔 and 4 푔. This is the proof of the proposition. ∎

www.iosrjournals.org 44 | Page A new argument for the non-existence of Closed Timelike Curves

IV. Introduction to the preliminaries of Future Papers 훼 훼 푎 훼 Define 푡 = 푁푛 + 푁 푒푎 as the components of 휕0. We then obtain from [1], the following equation: 퐷(푎 푡푏) = 푛(훼 푁;훽) + 푁퐷(훽 푛훼) + 퐷(훼 푁훽) 14)

We then obtain the extrinsic curvature as 1 15) 퐾 = (푔 푎푏 − 2푁 ) 푎푏 2푁 (푎;푏)

Now we use the Ashtekar approach. The canonical variables (these are 푥휇 ) are components of the inverse 3-metric 푔푎푏 intrinsic to 훴 and the components of the spin connection ∇ on 훴. The spin connection ∇ defines a bundle connection with base space 훴 and the spin space 핊. ∇ is then given by ∇= ∇intrinsic + 푖푲 16)

Defining a particular 휇 = 0 would lead to 푓 being a component of 푔푎푏 intrinsic to 훴 and the components of the spin connection ∇ on 훴. For the 3 + 1 split, we say that ℳ, 4 푔 = 훴 × ℝ, and in the spin connections's space, 훴 × 핊. We now define 훴 × 핊 as a five-dimensional space 풟, 5 푔 , with a 5-metric. We may perform a 4 + 1 split of 풟, 5 푔 , by stating that 핊 would have a 1 + 1 split on it, so we can define 핊 = ℝ × 풬. What is 풬? We can define the points of 풬 as below: Definition : 풬 is defined as ∀푝 ∈ 풬, 푝 × ℝ is a vector in 핊. Here ℝ denotes time, and 풬 denotes space. (We can see the reasons for this split later.) Consider the following equation: 풟, 5 푔 = 훴 × ℝ × 풬 17)

Look at the first part of the right hand side. It has 훴 × ℝ, which is the 3 + 1 split of gravity! So, this can be reformulated as 풟, 5 푔 = ℳ, 4 푔 × 풬 18)

The spin connection is basically a functional derivative‟s component, that is, 훿 19) 푔휇푣 = 푖ℏ 훿∇휇푣

The metric made is 푔휇푣 = 4 푔휇푣 + 푛휇 푛푣. Therefore, we have a refined equation, that is 4 훿 20) 푔휇푣 + 푛휇 푛푣 = 푖ℏ 훿∇휇푣 For uncontrollable infinities to vanish, we need ∇휇푣 ≠ 0, else the 3-dimensional metric would yield infinite distances between any two (even infinitesimally close) points as ∞. Now we ask ourselves a question. In the above statement, why was “3-dimensional metric” mentioned? Why not “the metric” or “4-dimensional metric”? To answer this, look at the fact that 푔휇푣 = 4 푔휇푣 + 푛휇 푛푣. We need the 4-metric 4 푔 to be finite, so we 휇 푣 휇 4 can introduce 푛 푛 = −∞ + 훿푣 . This then yields a finite answer for the 4-metric 푔, but what about the effect on 훴? Look at how we had defined 푛휇 – “푛휇 is the unit normal to 훴…”. The unit normal cannot be infinity, so saying that the 3-dimensional metric would yield infinite distances between any two (even infinitesimally close) points as ∞ is equivalent to saying that the 4-dimensional metric would yield infinite distances between any two (even infinitesimally close) points as ∞. 4 휇푣 휇 푣 훿 4 휇푣 휇 푣 In the classical limit, 푔 + 푛 푛 = 푖ℏ becomes 푔 = −푛 푛 as we estimate limℏ→0 ℏ, and 훿∇휇푣 4 휇 푣 휇 푣 therefore we need −1 = 푔휇푣 푛 푛 , so that 푛 and 푛 are negatively normalized to each other. The space of the spin connection is ℳ, 4 푔 × 풬, and we have a Dirac spinorial wavefunction, defined as 훹 = 훼퐴, 훽퐴′ . ∇ tells us how to carry the (two) spinor 훼퐴, (and also 훽퐴′ ), parallel to itself with respect to the ℳ, 4 푔 ‟s metric connection along some curve 훿 that lies on 훴, defined as Definition : A curve 훿 such that, we have, in a particular coordinate system 픎 on 훴, the following equations satisfied: 훿: 푆1 → 훴. Since ℳ, 4 푔 is globally hyperbolic, from the above discussion, and ℝ is flat, 훴 may be considered to be the global hyperbolicity “generator”. We are using the 훿 on a globally hyperbolic surface, and the curve then becomes a timelike loop, but with restriction that if www.iosrjournals.org 45 | Page A new argument for the non-existence of Closed Timelike Curves

Proposition 2: If 훿: 푆1 → 훴 then we should have 훿: 푆1 × ℝ → 훴 × ℝ so that 훿 ≠ 휋픎1, i.e., 훿 is not a closed timelike curve. Define the connection now as ∇ tells us how to carry the two spinor 훹 parallel to itself with respect to the ℳ, 4 푔 's metric connection along some curve 훿 that lies on 훴, defined as Definition : A curve 훿 such that, we have, in a particular coordinate system 픎 on 훴, the following equation satisfied 훿: 푆1 → 훴. This new definition allows us to say that ∇ causes a linear transformation of the spin space ℝ × 풬, by a 퐵 퐵 matrix 픗퐴 and 픗퐴 , when acted on ℝ may/may not yield ℝ, but the space 풬 is for sure transformed. 5 퐵 퐵 퐵 As we split 풟, 푔 , we can say that 픗퐴 on ℝ would transform, but 픗퐴 on 풬 would yield 풬. 픗퐴 then 4 퐵 operates only on ℳ, 푔 ‟s ℝ components. The elements of 픗퐴 are determined by some sort of basis 훽 in 훴. We need the basis 훽 to be extended to ℳ, 4 푔 , so we do a direct product by ℝ on ℳ, 4 푔 × 풬 and 4 퐵 ℳ, 푔 , and retrieve back the full spin space (with the 1 + 1 split). This ensures that the 픗퐴 are determined by some sort of basis 픅 in ℳ, 4 푔 . This allows wavefunctions to be existent as functions of time, so that 휕 푖 ℏ 훹 is not necessarily 0. 휕푡 See that if the direct product by ℝ had not been done, we would have had a vanishing Hamiltonian and therefore a Ricci flat spacetime, that is . It must be noted that after the direct product, we end up with a 6-dimensional spin connection space and a 5-dimensional spacetime, not necessarily Ricci flat. How are we to explain the sudden introduction of mass into the spacetime picture by doing a direct product? This we will try examining later. We have already split our 5-dimensional spacetime ℳ, 5 푔 as a (3 + 1) + 1 split, as we have ℳ, 5 푔 = 훴 × ℝ × ℝ. ℝ × ℝ, the direct product, is the 2-dimensional ℝ2. We then have the 휇푣 two main equations 풟, 6 푔 = 훴 × ℝ2 × 풬 and ℳ, 5 푔 = 훴 × ℝ × ℝ. The 6-metric 6 푔 is defined 휇푣 6 휇 푣 훿 as 푔 + 푛 푛 = 푖 ℏ . We need 휇 , 푣 to run over 0, … ,5. A problem here is that ∇휇푣 wanders away 훿 ∇휇푣 6 from its original background space – if 휇 , 푣 is to run over 0, … ,5, then ∇휇푣 would exist on 풟, 푔 , and it has obviously deviated from its original background space 훴 . So, for ∇휇푣 , we define different indices 푕, 푘 which 휇푣 훿 run over 0, … ,2, so the above equation becomes 6 푔 + 푛 휇 푛 푣 = 푖 ℏ . 훿 ∇푕푘 Our − + + + metric is formed by restricting the Killing form of the group 풢 's (of ℳ, 6 푔 ) Lie algebra 픤 to its Cartan subalgebra, say 픤 0. If the (Killing form) field equations vanish, a topological field theory (TFT) can be created on ℳ,∙ , and so even the ∇푕푘 vanishes. If we do the Chas-Sullivan timelike loop product 푎 푏 of any two timelike loops ∇푕푘 and ∇푕푘 , we need to have the Killing form of the Lie group to be restrictable to its Cartan subalgebra. If the Killing form vanishes, we have a TFT and the timelike loops vanish. Now we ask ourselves, is it a local or global TFT? The group of ℳ,∙ can be said to be 풢 푢 . \emph{If 풢 푢 has a locally different structure from the global structure of 풢 푢 , and if the local structure of 풢 푢 has a non-restrictable Killing form, then the TFT is local. For an Abelian 풢 푢 , the TFT vanishes, but for a non-Abelian G, the TFT may vanish.} We see that we can define the proposition in section 1 as a theorem: Theorem : There exists no closed timelike curve in the physical world. It seems that the above can also be stated alternatively, as a corollary, as below: Corollary : There exists no map between any two charts on $(\mathcal{M}, ^{(4)}g)$ such that causality is violated in any of them, i.e.,t here exists no map between any two charts on $(\mathcal{M}, ^{(4)}g)$ such that closed timelike structures (here proved only for curves) is violated in any of them. Proof : Basically, the main concept we assume is that causality exists. If that exists, then it should hold in all coordinate systems. According to the definition of closed timelike curves, if there exists a map between the two coordinate systems, say ℧: 픎 → 픎1, and the above theorem is false, then 훺 ℳ, 4 푔 = ∅. ∎ If we look at proposition 1, then if we look at the transition map between two charts, 픎 and 픎1, and compare it with the above then we see that we can propose: Proposition 3: The transition map between two charts, 픎 and 픎1, does not exist. Proof :We have, if 픎/픎1 exists (as it should), a map ℧: 픎 → 픎1. Then, from proposition 1, 픎/픎1 = {℧}. As {℧} does not exist, by the definition of a transition map, 휏 : {℧} → {℧} also cannot exist. ∎

www.iosrjournals.org 46 | Page A new argument for the non-existence of Closed Timelike Curves

V. Conclusion In this paper, we have proved the theorem which states that no CTCs can exist. Also, we have a concept simply stated as “functions as spaces”. This has many great implications, as can be exhibited: In future papers, we see that the symmetry group of the quantum universe during the so-called „quantum super-bounce‟ of super-LQC must have been 푆푈 (14) (due to complex reasons explained in those papers). We can easily perform a breaking as 푆푈 (14) → 푆푈 (5) × 푆푈 (9), where 푆푈 (9) is the symmetry group of loop quantum supergravity (due to complex reasons explained in those papers) and 푆푈 (5) is the Georgi-Glashow model. We obtain gravity, QCD, and the Electroweak force. By this method, we can obtain quantum electrodynamics as a unitary representation of the 푆푈 (14) group through the concept “functions as spaces”.

Acknowledgements The results of this paper were obtained during my studies at CFRCE (Center for Fundamental Research and Creative Education). I would like to express deep gratitude to my friends Madhavan Venkatesh and Vasudev Shyam, and my mentor Prof. Dr. B. S. Ramachandra whose guidance and support were crucial for the successful completion of this project. I would like to acknowledge the Director Ms. Pratiti B R for creating the highly charged research atmosphere at CFRCE. I would also like to thank Mrs. Manogna Shastry for the introduction of LaTex and help in my calculations.

References Theses: [1] de A. Gomes, Henrique, The Dynamics of Shapes, Ph.D., University of Nottingham, 2011 Books: [2] R.Penrose, The Road to Reality (Vintage Books, 2004).

www.iosrjournals.org 47 | Page