PPL-UK DOE N1 40..164

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PPL-UK DOE N1 40..164 74 non-expected utility theory Bibliography Schafer, W. and Sonnenschein, H. 1975. Equilibrium in Baye, M., Tian, G. and Zhou, J. 1993. Characterizations of Abstract economies without ordered preferences. Journal the existence of equilibria in games with discontinuous of Mathematical Economics 2, 345–8. and non-quasiconcave payoffs. Review of Economic Simon, L. 1987. Games with discontinuous payoffs. Review Studies 60, 935–48. of Economic Studies 54, 569–97. Bertrand, J. 1883. The´orie mathe´matique de la richesse Simon, L. and Zame, W. 1990. Discontinuous games and sociale. Journal des Savants 67, 499–508. endogenous sharing rules. Econometrica 58, 861–72. Billingsley, P. 1968. Convergence of Probability Measures.New Sion, M. 1958. On general minimax theorems. Pacific York: John Wiley and Sons. Journal of Mathematics 8, 171–6. Cournot, A. 1838. Researches into the Mathematical Vives, X. 1990. Nash equilibrium with strategic Principles of the Theory of Wealth, ed. N. Bacon. New complementarities. Journal of Mathematical Economics York: Macmillan, 1897. 19, 305–21. Dasgupta, P. and Maskin, E. 1986. The existence of von Neumann, J. 1928. Zur Theorie der Gesellshaftspiele. equilibrium in discontinuous economic games, I: theory. Mathematische Annalen 100, 295–320. Trans. S. Bargmann Review of Economic Studies 53, 1–26. [On the theory of games of strategy] in Contributions to Debreu, G. 1952. A social equilibrium existence theorem. the Theory of Games, vol. 4, ed. R. Luce and A. Tucker. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 38, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1959. 386–93. Fudenberg, D., Gilbert, R., Stiglitz, J. and Tirole, J. 1983. Preemption, leapfrogging, and competition in patent races. European Economic Review 22, non-expected utility theory 3–31. Although the expected utility model has long been the Glicksberg, I. 1952. A further generalization of the Kakutani standard theory of individual choice under objective and fixed point theorem. Proceedings of the American subjective uncertainty, experimental work by both psy- Mathematical Society 3, 170–4. chologists and economists has uncovered systematic Hotelling, H. 1929. The stability of competition. Economic departures from the expected utility hypothesis, which Journal 39, 41–57. has led to the development of alternative models of Jackson, M. and Swinkels, J. 2005. Existence of equilibrium preferences over uncertain prospects. in single and double private value auctions. Econometrica 73, 93–139. The expected utility model Jackson, M., Simon, L., Swinkels, J. and Zame, W. 2002. In one of the simplest settings of choice under economic Communication and equilibrium in discontinuous uncertainty, the objects of choice consist of finite- games of incomplete information. Econometrica 70, outcome objective lotteries of the form P ¼ðx1; p1; ...; 1711–40. x ; p Þ, yielding a monetary payoff of x with probability Milgrom, P. and Roberts, J. 1990. Rationalizability, n n i pi, where p1 þ ...þ pn ¼ 1. In such a case, the expected learning, and equilibrium in games with utility model of risk preferences assumes (or posits axi- strategic complementarities. Econometrica 58, oms sufficient to imply) that the individual ranks these 1255–77. prospects on the basis of an expected utility preference Milgrom, P. and Weber, R. 1982. A theory of auctions function of the form and competitive bidding. Econometrica 50, 1089–122. V EU ðPÞV EU ðx1; p1;...;xn; pnÞ Milgrom, P. and Weber, R. 1985. Distributional strategies for Uðx Þp þ ...þ Uðx Þp games with incomplete information. Mathematics of 1 1 n n Operations Research 10, 619–32. in the standard economic sense that the individual Nash, J. 1950. Equilibrium points in n-person games. n n n n n prefers lottery P ¼ðx1 ; p1 ;...;xnn ; pnn Þ over lottery P ¼ Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 36, n ðx1; p1;...;xn; pnÞ if and only if V EU ðP Þ4V EU ðPÞ, and 48–9. n is indifferent between them if and only if VEU ðP Þ¼ Nash, J. 1951. Non-cooperative games. Annals of V EU ðPÞ. U( Á ) is termed the individual’s von Neumann– Mathematics 54, 286–95. Morgenstern utility function (von Neumann and Osborne, M. and Rubinstein, A. 1994. A Course in Game Morgenstern, 1944; 1947; 1953), and its various math- Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ematical properties serve to characterize various features Reny, P. 1999. On the existence of pure and mixed strategy of the individual’s attitudes toward risk, for example: Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econometrica 67, 1029–56. VEU( Á ) exhibits first-order stochastic dominance pref- Robson, A. 1994. An ‘informationally robust’ equilibrium in erence (a preference for shifting probability from lower two-person nonzero-sum games. Games and Economic to higher outcome values) if and only if U(x)isan Behavior 2, 233–45. increasing function of x. non-expected utility theory 75 VEU( Á ) exhibits risk aversion (an aversion to all mean- 1 preserving increases in risk) if and only if U(x)isa concave function of x. n V EU ðÞ is at least as risk averse as VEU( Á ) (in several equivalent senses) if and only if its utility function UÃ( Á ) is a concave transformation of U( Á ) (that is, if Increasing preference and only if U nðxÞrðUðxÞÞ for some increasing concave function r( Á )). As shown by Bernoulli (1738), Arrow (1965), Pratt (1964), Friedman and Savage (1948), Markowitz (1952) and others, this model admits of a tremendous p3 flexibility in representing attitudes towards risk, and can be applied to many types of economic decisions and markets. But in spite of its flexibility, the expected utility model has testable implications which hold regardless of the shape of the utility function U( Á ), since they follow from the linearity in the probabilities property of the preference function V ( Á ). These implications can be best EU p expressed by the concept of an a : ð1 À aÞ probability 011 mixture of two lotteries P ¼ðx1; p1;...;xn; pnÞ and n n n n n Figure 1 Expected utility indifference curves in the probability P ¼ðx ; p ;...;x n ; p n Þ, which is defined as the single- 1 1 n n n triangle stage lottery a Á P þð1 À aÞP ¼ðx1; a Á p1;...; xn; a Á n n n n pn; x1 ; ð1À aÞp1 ;...;xnn ; ð1 À aÞpnn Þ. The mixture a Á P þð1 À aÞPn can be thought of as a coin flip yielding à lotteries P and P with probabilities a : ð1 À aÞ, where fixed p1) represent shifting probability from outcome x¯2 the uncertainty in the coin and in the subsequent lottery up to x¯3, and leftward movements represent shifting is resolved simultaneously. Linearity in the probabilities probability from x¯1 up to x¯2, such movements constitute is equivalent to the following property, which serves as first-order stochastically dominating shifts and will thus the key foundational axiom of the expected utility model always be preferred. Expected utility indifference (Marschak, 1950): curves (loci of constant expected utility) are given by the formula Independence Axiom If lottery Pà is preferred (indiffer- n ent) to lottery P, then the probability mixture a Á P þ Uðx¯1Þp1 þ Uðx¯2Þ½1 À p1 À p3 ð1 À aÞPÃà is preferred (indifferent) to a Á P þð1 À aÞ þ Uðx¯3Þp ¼ constant PÃà for every lottery PÃà and every mixture probability 3 a 2ð0; 1. and are thus seen to be parallel straight lines of slope ½Uðx¯2ÞUðx¯1Þ=½Uðx¯3ÞUðx¯2Þ, as indicated by the This axiom can be interpreted as saying ‘given an a : solid lines in the figure. The dotted lines in Figure 1 are à ð1 À aÞ coin, the individual’s preferences for receiving P loci of constant expected value, given by the formula versus P in the event of a head should not depend upon x¯ Á p þx¯ ½1Àp À p þx¯ Á p ¼ constant, with slope Ãà 1 1 2 1 3 3 3 the prize P that would be received in the event of a tail, ½x¯2 À x¯1=½x¯3 À x¯2. Since north-east movements along nor upon the probability a of landing heads (so long as the constant expected value lines shift probability from x¯2 this probability is positive)’. The strong normative appeal down to x¯1 and up to x¯3 in a manner that preserves the of this axiom has contributed to the widespread adoption mean of the distribution, they represent simple increases of the expected utility model. in risk (Rothschild and Stiglitz, 1970; 1971). When U( Á ) The property of linearity in the probabilities, as well as is concave (that is, risk averse), its indifference curves the senses in which it has been found to be empirically will have a steeper slope than these constant expected violated, can be illustrated in the special case of prefer- value lines, and such increases in risk move the individual ences over all lotteries P ¼ðx¯1; p1; x¯2; p2; x¯3; p3Þ over a from more to less preferred indifference curves, as illus- fixed set of outcome values x¯1ox¯2ox¯3. Since we must trated in the figure. It is straightforward to show that the have p2 ¼ 1 À p1 À p3, each such lottery can be com- indifference curves of any expected utility maximizer pletely summarized by its pair of probabilities (p1, p3), as with a more risk-averse (that is, more concave) utility plotted in the ‘probability triangle’ of Figure 1. Since function UÃ( Á ) will be steeper than those generated upward movements in the diagram (increasing p3 for by U( Á ). 76 non-expected utility theory Systematic violations of the expected utility 1 hypothesis In spite of its normative appeal, researchers have uncov- ered several types of widespread systematic violations of the expected utility model and its underlying assumptions.
Recommended publications
  • The Allais Paradox: What It Became, What It Really Was, What It Now Suggests to Us
    Economics and Philosophy (2019), 35, 423–459 doi:10.1017/S0266267118000469 ARTICLE The Allais paradox: what it became, what it really was, what it now suggests to us Philippe Mongin GREGHEC, 1 rue de la Libération, F-78350 Jouy-en-Josas, France Email: [email protected] (Received 11 June 2018; revised 24 August 2018; accepted 27 August 2018; first published online 30 January 2019) Abstract Whereas many others have scrutinized the Allais paradox from a theoretical angle, we study the paradox from an historical perspective and link our findings to a suggestion as to how decision theory could make use of it today. We emphasize that Allais proposed the paradox as anormativeargument, concerned with ‘the rational man’ and not the ‘real man’,touse his words. Moreover, and more subtly, we argue that Allais had an unusual sense of the normative, being concerned not so much with the rationality of choices as with the rationality of the agent as a person. These two claims are buttressed by a detailed investigation – the first of its kind – of the 1952 Paris conference on risk, which set the context for the invention of the paradox, and a detailed reconstruction – also the first of its kind – of Allais’s specific normative argument from his numerous but allusive writings. The paper contrasts these interpretations of what the paradox historically represented, with how it generally came to function within decision theory from the late 1970s onwards: that is, as an empirical refutation of the expected utility hypothesis, and more specifically of the condition of von Neumann–Morgenstern independence that underlies that hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism
    I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism by Jesse Kozler A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2019 Advisor: Professor James Joyce Second Reader: Professor David Manley Acknowledgments This thesis is not the product of solely my own efforts, and owes its existence in large part to the substantial support that I have received along the way from the many wonderful, brilliant people in my life. First and foremost, I want to thank Jim Joyce who eagerly agreed to advise this project and who has offered countless insights which gently prodded me to refine my approach, solidify my thoughts, and strengthen my arguments. Without him this project would never have gotten off the ground. I want to thank David Manley, who signed on to be the second reader and whose guidance on matters inside and outside of the realm of my thesis has been indispensable. Additionally, I want to thank Elizabeth Anderson, Peter Railton, and Sarah Buss who, through private discussions and sharing their own work, provided me with inspiration at times I badly needed it and encouraged me to think about previously unexamined issues. I am greatly indebted to the University of Michigan LSA Honors Program who, through their generous Honors Summer Fellowship program, made it possible for me to stay in Ann Arbor and spend my summer reading and thinking intentionally about these issues. I am especially grateful to Mika LaVaque-Manty, who whipped me into shape and instilled in me a work ethic that has been essential to the completion of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk
    Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk William S. Neilson Department of Economics Texas A&M University College Station, TX 77843-4228 [email protected] January 24, 2000 The standard expected utility model is augmented by allowing individuals to receive additional utility in states in which they consider themselves victorious and to lose a utility increment in which they consider themselves defeated. The resulting event-dependent expected utility model is used to explain behavior in games and toward risk. In games, players consider themselves defeated when their monetary payoffs are low compared to their opponents' payoffs, and they consider themselves victorious when their payoffs are high, but not too high, compared to their opponents' payoffs. Under these conditions the model can accommodate behavior that has been interpreted elsewhere as inequity aversion, as well as cooperation in the prisoner's dilemma and in public good provision games. In situations of risk, individuals consider themselves victorious (defeated) when they receive an unlikely, avoidable, high (low) outcome. Under these conditions the model can accommodate such behavior as the Allais paradox, boundary effects, and simultaneous gambling and insurance. Keywords: Event-dependent preferences, behavioral economics, inequity aversion, Allais paradox, boundary effects JEL codes: D81, C72 I am grateful to Robert Slonim and participants at the 1999 Lonestars Conference for helpful comments, and to the Private Enterprise Research Center for financial support. 1. Introduction People like winning and dislike losing, yet this feature has never been incorporated into the study of games. This paper remedies that situation. It is assumed that besides the utility he receives from his monetary payoff, a player gets a positive utility increment in situations in which he considers himself victorious, and suffers a negative utility increment in any situation that he considers a defeat.
    [Show full text]
  • New Paradoxes in Intertemporal Choice
    Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011, pp. 122–129 New paradoxes in intertemporal choice Li-Lin Rao∗ Shu Li† Abstract Similar to research on risky choice, the traditional analysis of intertemporal choice takes the view that an individual behaves so as to maximize the discounted sum of all future utilities. The well-known Allais paradox contradicts the fundamental postulates of maximizing the expected value or utility of a risky option. We describe a violation of the law of diminishing marginal utility as well as an intertemporal version of the Allais paradox. Keywords: intertemporal choice, risky choice, cancellation. 1 Introduction The most prominent idea to account for these anoma- lies is the hyperbolic discounting model (Ainslie, 1975). In the field of intertemporal choice, the discounted-utility This model suggests that the discount rate is not dy- (DU) theory proposed by Paul Samuelson in 1937 was namically consistent but that the rate is higher be- presented not only as a valid normative standard but also tween the present and near future and lower between as a descriptive theory of actual intertemporal choice be- the near and far distant future. Numerous theories have havior (Frederick, Loewenstein, & O’Donoghue, 2002; been developed by transforming the discount function Samuelson, 1937). In its general form, the DU theory to other forms, from one-parameter hyperbolic discount- proposes that the value of an option, (x; t), is the prod- ing (Mazur, 1984) to generalized hyperbolic discounting uct of its present utility, U(x), and an exponential tem- (Loewenstein & Prelec, 1992), to proportional discount- poral discounting function, F(t), where t is the time at ing (Harvey, 1994), and to quasi-hyperbolic discount- which x is acquired.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • Learning in the Allais Paradox
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Erasmus University Digital Repository J Risk Uncertainty (2006) 33:155–164 DOI 10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3 Learning in the Allais paradox Gijs van de Kuilen · Peter P. Wakker∗ C Springer Science + Business Media, LLC 2006 Abstract Whereas both the Allais paradox, the first empirical challenge of the classical ra- tionality assumptions, and learning have been the focus of many experimental investigations, no experimental study exists today into learning in the pure context of the Allais paradox. This paper presents such a study. We find that choices converge to expected utility maxi- mization if subjects are given the opportunity to learn by both thought and experience, but less so when they learn by thought only. To the extent that genuine preferences should be measured with proper learning and incentives, our study gives the first pure demonstration that irrationalities such as in the Allais paradox are less pronounced than often thought. Keywords Learning . Rational choice . Allais paradox . Nonexpected utility JEL Classification D81 . D83 The first empirical challenge of the classical rationality assumption in economics was made by Allais (1953), through his famous choice paradox for decision under risk. It showed that the majority of people systematically violate expected utility, the model commonly accepted as the hallmark of rationality for choice under risk in those days. Allais’ paradox initiated a flurry of empirical demonstrations that more and more basic rationality assumptions are violated empirically (Camerer, 1995). To model these findings, theories were developed that explicitly depart from rational choice and only pretend to be descriptive, such as prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979).
    [Show full text]
  • How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: the Case of Samuelson and Savage
    Journal of Economic Perspectives—Volume 30, Number 2—Spring 2016—Pages 219–236 Retrospectives How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: The Case of Samuelson and Savage Ivan Moscati This feature addresses the history of economic terms and ideas. The hope is to deepen the workaday dialogue of economists, while perhaps also casting new light on ongoing questions. If you have suggestions for future topics or authors, please contact Joseph Persky, Professor of Economics, University of Illinois, Chicago, at [email protected]. Introduction In the expected utility approach to decision-making under risk, the utility of a risky prospect is given by the sum of the utilities u of the alternative possible outcomes of the prospect, each weighted by the probability that the outcome will occur. Thus, for example, the utility of a lottery yielding either a trip to London with probability p or a payment of $2,000 with probability (1 p) is given by − (u(trip to London) p) (u($2,000) (1 p)). According to expected utility × + × − theory, the decision maker will choose among these risky prospects, or lotteries, and will choose the one with the highest expected utility. This theory dominated the economic analysis of individual decision-making under risk from the early 1950s to the 1990s. Beginning in the late 1970s, the accumulation of robust experi- mental evidence against the expected utility hypothesis prompted decision theorists ■ Ivan Moscati is Associate Professor of Economics, University of Insubria, Varese, Italy. He also teaches History of Economics at Bocconi University, Milan, Italy. His email address is [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • The Economics of Risk
    Upjohn Press Upjohn Research home page 1-1-2003 The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University Follow this and additional works at: https://research.upjohn.org/up_press Part of the Economics Commons, and the Insurance Commons Citation Meyer, Donald J., ed. 2003. The Economics of Risk. Kalamazoo, MI: W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. https://doi.org/10.17848/9781417505937 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 License. This title is brought to you by the Upjohn Institute. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Economics of Risk The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Editor 2003 W.E.Upjohn Institute for Employment Research Kalamazoo, Michigan Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data © 2003 W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research 300 S. Westnedge Avenue Kalamazoo, Michigan 49007–4686 The facts presented in this study and the observations and viewpoints expressed are the sole responsibility of the authors. They do not necessarily represent positions of the W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. Cover design by Alcorn Publication Design. Index prepared by Diane Worden. Printed in the United States of America. Printed on recycled paper. Contents Introduction 1 Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University 1 Risk and Risk Management 9 Keith J. Crocker University of Michigan Business School 2 States of the World and the State of Decision Theory 17 Mark J. Machina University of California, San Diego 3 Gambling with the Future 51 William R. Eadington University of Nevada, Reno 4 Common Value Auctions and the Winner’s Curse 65 John H.
    [Show full text]
  • Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences
    Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences Florian Brandl Felix Brandt Technische Universität München {brandlfl,brandtf}@in.tum.de We consider social welfare functions that satisfy Arrow’s classic axioms of in- dependence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto optimality when the outcome space is the convex hull of some finite set of alternatives. Individual and col- lective preferences are assumed to be continuous and convex, which guarantees the existence of maximal elements and the consistency of choice functions that return these elements, even without insisting on transitivity. We provide char- acterizations of both the domains of preferences and the social welfare functions that allow for anonymous Arrovian aggregation. The domains admit arbitrary preferences over alternatives, which completely determine an agent’s prefer- ences over all mixed outcomes. On these domains, Arrow’s impossibility turns into a complete characterization of a unique social welfare function, which can be readily applied in settings involving divisible resources such as probability, time, or money. 1. Introduction A central concept in welfare economics are social welfare functions (SWFs) in the tradition of Arrow, i.e., functions that map a collection of individual preference relations over some set of alternatives to a social preference relation over the alternatives. Arrow’s seminal arXiv:1703.05519v6 [cs.GT] 12 Apr 2019 theorem states that every SWF that satisfies Pareto optimality and independence of ir- relevant alternatives is dictatorial (Arrow, 1951). This sweeping impossibility significantly strengthened an earlier observation by Condorcet (1785) and sent shockwaves throughout welfare economics, political philosophy, economic theory, and even seemingly unrelated disciplines such as philosophy of science and engineering design (see, e.g., Maskin and Sen, 2014; Sen, 2017; Gaertner, 2019).
    [Show full text]
  • The First Challenge to Economic Rationality: Revisiting Allais Paradox
    Review International of Journal Management and Social Researches Uluslararası Yönetim ve Sosyal Araştırmalar Dergisi ISSN:2148-1415/ e-ISSN:2651-3072 Makale Başvuru/Kabul Tarihleri: Received/Accepted Dates: Volume 7, Issue 13, Year 2020 02.10.2019/17.12.2019 The First Challenge to Economic Rationality: Revisiting Allais Paradox Assoc. Prof. Dr. Gelengül KOÇASLAN Istanbul University, Faculty of Economics [email protected] Abstract Allais Paradox is the first revealed violation of the underlying tenets of the theory of expected utility which has been the basic reference on economic behavior and economic decision making under risk since it was first suggested in 1944 by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern. What makes Allais Paradox special is the paradox does not only violate the basic tenets of the theory of expected utility but also violates the independence axiom which is known as the heart of it. This violation provides evidence that adding a third alternative to the existing preferences matters. The aim of the study is to explain the first challenge to economic rationality; Allais Paradox and to show how the independence axiom which is known as the heart axiom of the theory of expected utility is violated. By revealing the paradox and the axiom; it is also aimed to call attention to the importance of this violation with regard to asset and insurance markets for future research. Keywords: Rationality, Allais Paradox, Axioms, Independence Axiom, The Theory of Expected Utility, Prospect Theory. INTRODUCTION Still being a basic reference in economics research; the theory of expected utility examining economic behavior under risk and uncertainty was suggested by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1944.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making
    Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making Andrej Démuth Edition Cognitive Studies Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making Andrej Démuth Edition Cognitive Studies Peer reviewers Content Prof. PhDr. Silvia Gáliková, CSc., RNDr. Mgr. Reginald Adrián Slavkovský, Ph.D. Editorial Board Doc. Andrej Démuth ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Josef Dolista ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Silvia Gáliková ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Peter Gärdenfors ∙ Lunds Universitet Dr. Richard Gray ∙ Cardiff University Doc. Marek Petrů ∙ Univerzita Palackého ∙ Olomouc 1. Game theory and the problem Dr. Adrián Slavkovský ∙ Trnavská univerzita of decision–making ................................. 12 1.1 What is game theory? ............................... 12 1.2 Why study game theory? ........................... 13 1.3 Who studies game theory? ......................... 13 1.4 History of game theory .............................. 14 1.5 Game theory and philosophy . 18 1.6 Recommended literature ............................ 18 2. Terminology ......................................... 19 2.1 The game ............................................. 19 2.2 Choice and strategy ................................. 20 2.3 Probability and the theory of possible worlds . 21 2.4 Outcomes ............................................ 21 2.5 Starting points ...................................... 22 2.6 Deciding with certainty, imperfect The publication of this book is part of the project Innovative Forms of Education in Transform- information and with risk ..........................
    [Show full text]