The Independence Axiom Versus the Reduction Axiom: Must We Have Both?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Independence Axiom Versus the Reduction Axiom: Must We Have Both? 7 THE INDEPENDENCE AXIOM VERSUS THE REDUCTION AXIOM: MUST WE HAVE BOTH? Uzi Segal Introduction Since the early 18th Century, expected utility theory became the leading theory in explaining behavior of decision makers under uncertainty. For most of this time it was used as a purely descriptive theory. For example, Ramsey (1931) explicitly assumed that people evaluate a risky prospect by its expected utility. He expressed this idea in the following words: I suggest that we introduce as a law of psychology that his Ithe decision maker's] behavior is governed by what is called the mathematical expectation: that is to say that, if p is a proposition about which he is doubtful. any goods or bads for whose realization p is in his view a necessary and sufficient condition enter into his calculations multiplied by the same fraction, which is called the 'degree of his belief in p'. This theory changed its status sometime in the late forties when different authors tried to give it an axiomatic basis, that is, a set of decision rules implying expected utility maximization. Some of the early axiomatizations were suggested by von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947), Marschak (1950), and Samuelson (1952). W. Ed ••..ards (ed.), UTILITY THEORIES: MEASUNEMEN7:\' AND AI'I'L1CATIONS. Copyright © 1992. Kluwcr AClIdemic Publishers. lIos/()/I. All riKht.1 reserl'ed. 166 UTILITY THEORIES: MEASUREMENTS AND APPLICATI()N~ These sets of axioms were usually considered normative. that is rules that must be obeyed by "rational" decision makers. The commor belief is (or at least was) that violating these rules implies that decision makers are willing to give something for nothing. a violations of the most sacred rule in Economics. that more is better. But axioms have another important role. which is their descriptive value. A certain theory mayor may not be used by decision makers. Although we may find by chance a behavioral violation of a theory, it may be considered an insignificant mistake. However. if we find that people systematically violate one of the rules that necessarily follow from a certain theory. then this evidence will probably carry more value. Moreover. it should be easier to find counterexamples to well-defined rules than to the theory itself. This approach has also a positive value. Obviously, it is impossible to verify the validity of a theory by any finite number of observations. However. if we can isolate some rules and test them directly. then we will be presumably more willing to accept them. If these rules imply a certain decision theory. we are then thus bound to accept the theory as well. Undoubtedly. the existence of an axiomatic basis for expected utility theory helped those who claimed that decision makers do not follow it to find behavioral departures from this theory. The first. and by far the most famous type of nonexpected utility behavior. was suggested by Allais (1953) shortly after the first axiomatizations were found. Since then a lot of other evidence against this theory was accumulated. (See. for example, ElIsberg. 1961; Kahneman and Tversky. 1979; MacCrimmon and Larsson. 1979.) Obviously. if a certain set of axioms implies a certain theory. and empirical evidence fails to support this theory, then one or more of these axioms must be violated. Some axioms have more appeal than ot-hers, thus, we would prefer to try to keep these axioms at the cost of the less appealing ones. Moreover. if a certain axiom is widely used, not only in theories of decision making under uncertainty, but in general decision problems as well, then we will probably be more reluctant to abandon it. This is one of the reasons why economists are so unwilling to give up the transitivity axiom. Since the continuity and completeness axioms carry a similar. or even a higher value. the only disposable axiom is the independence axiom. Let X. Y. and Z be lotteries. According to the independence axiom. the lottery aX + (I - a)Z is preferred to the lottery a Y + (I - a)Z if and only if X is preferred to Y. The normative justification for this axiom is that if X is preferred to Y, it should also be so when receiving these lotteries becomes uncertain. Recent authors in the field of decision theory are of course well aware of the normative appeal of this axiom, THE INDEPENDENCE AXIOM VERSUS THE REDUCTION AXIOM ]( but claim that whether we like it or not, decision makers do not accept i In other words, even if nonexpected utility theories cannot be used a normative grounds because they violate the independence or the trar, sitivity axioms (for the latter, see Fishburn, 1983; Loomes and Sugden 1986; MacCrimmon and Larsson, 1979), they are still superior to expectel utility as descriptive theories. But do decision makers really violate the independence axiom? Afte all, the idea that a preference relation should not depend on outcome that were never realized is very compelling even on a purely behaviora basis. Moreover, this rule appears in a lot of other areas of economil theory. Indeed, there is not much difference between the reasonin! behind this axiom and the justification for the axiom of revealed pre· ferences (Samuelson, 1938) or Arrow's rule of independence of irrelevanl alternatives. This does not mean that decision makers necessarily folio •••• this axiom, but it raises the theoretical price we have to pay to exclude it. I claim below that most of the evidence against expected utility theory, as well as some other evidence, can be analyzed as a violation of the reduction of compound lotteries axiom. Moreover, in an appropriate setting, this axiom has less normative value than is usually believed. This analysis follows closely the one presented in Segal (1990), where the model is more formally presented. Of course, it is nicer to have a model in which this axiom is accepted. But it is my belief that releasing the reduction axiom is the lesser of the many other evils we may choose. This point appears in several former works. Luce and Narens (1985) analyze, among other things, a model where multi-stage uncertainty is different from a single-stage uncertainty with the same compound prob• abilities. Luce (1988) gives an axiomatization of the rank dependent model (Quiggin, 1982) based on the assumption that in some cases, the order at which uncertainty is resolved makes no difference to the decision maker. For different axiomatizations of the same model, based on other versions of order indifference, see Segal (1989), and Chew (1989). For some references to the experimental literature, see Segal, 1990. The chapter is organized as follows. In the next section I discuss two• stage lotteries with the reduction of compound lotteries axiom and the (compound) independence axiom. Section three analyzes a Dutch book in support of the reduction axiom. In section four I show how this approach may be useful in analyzing some empirical evidence dealing with two• stage lotteries. The Ellsberg paradox is discussed in section five. Section six concludes with some further remarks on the independence axiom. 168 UTILITY THEORIES: MEASUREMENTS AND APPLICATIO~ Two-Stage Lotteries There are situations where uncertainty is resolved in more than on stage. This may be because some real time elapses between the poir when the uncertainty begins to be resolved and the point where all th uncertainty is resolved, or because the decision maker's concept of th uncertainty is multi-stage, even if no real time is involved. In this sectiol I describe the formal structure of such lotteries. For a more detaile( discussion see Segal (1990). Let LI be the set of lotteries with outcomes in a bounded interva [-M, MI. That is, L, = {(x" PI:"': x". PII): X" ...• XII E [-M. M] p), ... , PII ~ 0, and 'Lp; = I}. Elements of L, are denoted X, Y, etc. We usually assume that the outcomes of these lotteries are monetar) outcomes. Let ~I be a complete, transitive, monotonic. and continuous preference relation on L,. We say that X>, Y if X~, Y but not Y ~I X and that X -I Y if X ~I Yand Y ~I X. A function V: L, -> IR is said to represent the order ~I if VeX) ~ V(Y) if and only if X ~I Y. For X ELI, let CE(X), the certainty equivalent of X, be defined by X -I (CE(X). I). A two-stage lottery is a lottery where the outcomes are tickets for simple lotteries in LI' Formally, let L2 = {(X), q,: ... ; X"" q",): XI,' .. ,X", E L), q), ... ,q", ~ 0, L'q; = I}. Elements of L2 are denoted A, B, etc. A preference relation on L2 is denoted ~2' We assume throughout that such a preference relation is complete and transitive. Two subsets of Lz are of special interest. Let L1 = {(X. I): X E L,} C L2• LJ is the set of all two-stage lotteries which have no uncertainty in the first stage-the decision maker knows that with probability one he will receive a ticket for lottery X. In other words, all the uncertainty is resolved in the second stage. Let r = {((XI' 1), PI;"'; (x"' I), PII):(X" p,; ... ; X". PII) E L d. r is the set of all lotteries where all the uncertainty is resolved in the first stage. With probability P; the decision maker knows that he has won a ticket for the lottery (x;, I), that is. a sure gain of Xi dollars. In other words. both rand LJ are L, type spaces. Let X = (x,. PI;' .. : x"' p,,) E L, be a simple, one-stage lottery. Define the two lotteries Yx E r and ()x E LJ as follows: Yx = ((XI' I), PI;' ., : (XII' I), PII) ()x = ((XI' PI;"'; x"' p,,).
Recommended publications
  • The Allais Paradox: What It Became, What It Really Was, What It Now Suggests to Us
    Economics and Philosophy (2019), 35, 423–459 doi:10.1017/S0266267118000469 ARTICLE The Allais paradox: what it became, what it really was, what it now suggests to us Philippe Mongin GREGHEC, 1 rue de la Libération, F-78350 Jouy-en-Josas, France Email: [email protected] (Received 11 June 2018; revised 24 August 2018; accepted 27 August 2018; first published online 30 January 2019) Abstract Whereas many others have scrutinized the Allais paradox from a theoretical angle, we study the paradox from an historical perspective and link our findings to a suggestion as to how decision theory could make use of it today. We emphasize that Allais proposed the paradox as anormativeargument, concerned with ‘the rational man’ and not the ‘real man’,touse his words. Moreover, and more subtly, we argue that Allais had an unusual sense of the normative, being concerned not so much with the rationality of choices as with the rationality of the agent as a person. These two claims are buttressed by a detailed investigation – the first of its kind – of the 1952 Paris conference on risk, which set the context for the invention of the paradox, and a detailed reconstruction – also the first of its kind – of Allais’s specific normative argument from his numerous but allusive writings. The paper contrasts these interpretations of what the paradox historically represented, with how it generally came to function within decision theory from the late 1970s onwards: that is, as an empirical refutation of the expected utility hypothesis, and more specifically of the condition of von Neumann–Morgenstern independence that underlies that hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism
    I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism by Jesse Kozler A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2019 Advisor: Professor James Joyce Second Reader: Professor David Manley Acknowledgments This thesis is not the product of solely my own efforts, and owes its existence in large part to the substantial support that I have received along the way from the many wonderful, brilliant people in my life. First and foremost, I want to thank Jim Joyce who eagerly agreed to advise this project and who has offered countless insights which gently prodded me to refine my approach, solidify my thoughts, and strengthen my arguments. Without him this project would never have gotten off the ground. I want to thank David Manley, who signed on to be the second reader and whose guidance on matters inside and outside of the realm of my thesis has been indispensable. Additionally, I want to thank Elizabeth Anderson, Peter Railton, and Sarah Buss who, through private discussions and sharing their own work, provided me with inspiration at times I badly needed it and encouraged me to think about previously unexamined issues. I am greatly indebted to the University of Michigan LSA Honors Program who, through their generous Honors Summer Fellowship program, made it possible for me to stay in Ann Arbor and spend my summer reading and thinking intentionally about these issues. I am especially grateful to Mika LaVaque-Manty, who whipped me into shape and instilled in me a work ethic that has been essential to the completion of this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk
    Victory and Defeat in a Model of Behavior in Games and Toward Risk William S. Neilson Department of Economics Texas A&M University College Station, TX 77843-4228 [email protected] January 24, 2000 The standard expected utility model is augmented by allowing individuals to receive additional utility in states in which they consider themselves victorious and to lose a utility increment in which they consider themselves defeated. The resulting event-dependent expected utility model is used to explain behavior in games and toward risk. In games, players consider themselves defeated when their monetary payoffs are low compared to their opponents' payoffs, and they consider themselves victorious when their payoffs are high, but not too high, compared to their opponents' payoffs. Under these conditions the model can accommodate behavior that has been interpreted elsewhere as inequity aversion, as well as cooperation in the prisoner's dilemma and in public good provision games. In situations of risk, individuals consider themselves victorious (defeated) when they receive an unlikely, avoidable, high (low) outcome. Under these conditions the model can accommodate such behavior as the Allais paradox, boundary effects, and simultaneous gambling and insurance. Keywords: Event-dependent preferences, behavioral economics, inequity aversion, Allais paradox, boundary effects JEL codes: D81, C72 I am grateful to Robert Slonim and participants at the 1999 Lonestars Conference for helpful comments, and to the Private Enterprise Research Center for financial support. 1. Introduction People like winning and dislike losing, yet this feature has never been incorporated into the study of games. This paper remedies that situation. It is assumed that besides the utility he receives from his monetary payoff, a player gets a positive utility increment in situations in which he considers himself victorious, and suffers a negative utility increment in any situation that he considers a defeat.
    [Show full text]
  • New Paradoxes in Intertemporal Choice
    Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No. 2, February 2011, pp. 122–129 New paradoxes in intertemporal choice Li-Lin Rao∗ Shu Li† Abstract Similar to research on risky choice, the traditional analysis of intertemporal choice takes the view that an individual behaves so as to maximize the discounted sum of all future utilities. The well-known Allais paradox contradicts the fundamental postulates of maximizing the expected value or utility of a risky option. We describe a violation of the law of diminishing marginal utility as well as an intertemporal version of the Allais paradox. Keywords: intertemporal choice, risky choice, cancellation. 1 Introduction The most prominent idea to account for these anoma- lies is the hyperbolic discounting model (Ainslie, 1975). In the field of intertemporal choice, the discounted-utility This model suggests that the discount rate is not dy- (DU) theory proposed by Paul Samuelson in 1937 was namically consistent but that the rate is higher be- presented not only as a valid normative standard but also tween the present and near future and lower between as a descriptive theory of actual intertemporal choice be- the near and far distant future. Numerous theories have havior (Frederick, Loewenstein, & O’Donoghue, 2002; been developed by transforming the discount function Samuelson, 1937). In its general form, the DU theory to other forms, from one-parameter hyperbolic discount- proposes that the value of an option, (x; t), is the prod- ing (Mazur, 1984) to generalized hyperbolic discounting uct of its present utility, U(x), and an exponential tem- (Loewenstein & Prelec, 1992), to proportional discount- poral discounting function, F(t), where t is the time at ing (Harvey, 1994), and to quasi-hyperbolic discount- which x is acquired.
    [Show full text]
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • Learning in the Allais Paradox
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Erasmus University Digital Repository J Risk Uncertainty (2006) 33:155–164 DOI 10.1007/s11166-006-0390-3 Learning in the Allais paradox Gijs van de Kuilen · Peter P. Wakker∗ C Springer Science + Business Media, LLC 2006 Abstract Whereas both the Allais paradox, the first empirical challenge of the classical ra- tionality assumptions, and learning have been the focus of many experimental investigations, no experimental study exists today into learning in the pure context of the Allais paradox. This paper presents such a study. We find that choices converge to expected utility maxi- mization if subjects are given the opportunity to learn by both thought and experience, but less so when they learn by thought only. To the extent that genuine preferences should be measured with proper learning and incentives, our study gives the first pure demonstration that irrationalities such as in the Allais paradox are less pronounced than often thought. Keywords Learning . Rational choice . Allais paradox . Nonexpected utility JEL Classification D81 . D83 The first empirical challenge of the classical rationality assumption in economics was made by Allais (1953), through his famous choice paradox for decision under risk. It showed that the majority of people systematically violate expected utility, the model commonly accepted as the hallmark of rationality for choice under risk in those days. Allais’ paradox initiated a flurry of empirical demonstrations that more and more basic rationality assumptions are violated empirically (Camerer, 1995). To model these findings, theories were developed that explicitly depart from rational choice and only pretend to be descriptive, such as prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979).
    [Show full text]
  • How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: the Case of Samuelson and Savage
    Journal of Economic Perspectives—Volume 30, Number 2—Spring 2016—Pages 219–236 Retrospectives How Economists Came to Accept Expected Utility Theory: The Case of Samuelson and Savage Ivan Moscati This feature addresses the history of economic terms and ideas. The hope is to deepen the workaday dialogue of economists, while perhaps also casting new light on ongoing questions. If you have suggestions for future topics or authors, please contact Joseph Persky, Professor of Economics, University of Illinois, Chicago, at [email protected]. Introduction In the expected utility approach to decision-making under risk, the utility of a risky prospect is given by the sum of the utilities u of the alternative possible outcomes of the prospect, each weighted by the probability that the outcome will occur. Thus, for example, the utility of a lottery yielding either a trip to London with probability p or a payment of $2,000 with probability (1 p) is given by − (u(trip to London) p) (u($2,000) (1 p)). According to expected utility × + × − theory, the decision maker will choose among these risky prospects, or lotteries, and will choose the one with the highest expected utility. This theory dominated the economic analysis of individual decision-making under risk from the early 1950s to the 1990s. Beginning in the late 1970s, the accumulation of robust experi- mental evidence against the expected utility hypothesis prompted decision theorists ■ Ivan Moscati is Associate Professor of Economics, University of Insubria, Varese, Italy. He also teaches History of Economics at Bocconi University, Milan, Italy. His email address is [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • The Economics of Risk
    Upjohn Press Upjohn Research home page 1-1-2003 The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University Follow this and additional works at: https://research.upjohn.org/up_press Part of the Economics Commons, and the Insurance Commons Citation Meyer, Donald J., ed. 2003. The Economics of Risk. Kalamazoo, MI: W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. https://doi.org/10.17848/9781417505937 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 4.0 License. This title is brought to you by the Upjohn Institute. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Economics of Risk The Economics of Risk Donald J. Meyer Editor 2003 W.E.Upjohn Institute for Employment Research Kalamazoo, Michigan Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data © 2003 W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research 300 S. Westnedge Avenue Kalamazoo, Michigan 49007–4686 The facts presented in this study and the observations and viewpoints expressed are the sole responsibility of the authors. They do not necessarily represent positions of the W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research. Cover design by Alcorn Publication Design. Index prepared by Diane Worden. Printed in the United States of America. Printed on recycled paper. Contents Introduction 1 Donald J. Meyer Western Michigan University 1 Risk and Risk Management 9 Keith J. Crocker University of Michigan Business School 2 States of the World and the State of Decision Theory 17 Mark J. Machina University of California, San Diego 3 Gambling with the Future 51 William R. Eadington University of Nevada, Reno 4 Common Value Auctions and the Winner’s Curse 65 John H.
    [Show full text]
  • Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences
    Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences Florian Brandl Felix Brandt Technische Universität München {brandlfl,brandtf}@in.tum.de We consider social welfare functions that satisfy Arrow’s classic axioms of in- dependence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto optimality when the outcome space is the convex hull of some finite set of alternatives. Individual and col- lective preferences are assumed to be continuous and convex, which guarantees the existence of maximal elements and the consistency of choice functions that return these elements, even without insisting on transitivity. We provide char- acterizations of both the domains of preferences and the social welfare functions that allow for anonymous Arrovian aggregation. The domains admit arbitrary preferences over alternatives, which completely determine an agent’s prefer- ences over all mixed outcomes. On these domains, Arrow’s impossibility turns into a complete characterization of a unique social welfare function, which can be readily applied in settings involving divisible resources such as probability, time, or money. 1. Introduction A central concept in welfare economics are social welfare functions (SWFs) in the tradition of Arrow, i.e., functions that map a collection of individual preference relations over some set of alternatives to a social preference relation over the alternatives. Arrow’s seminal arXiv:1703.05519v6 [cs.GT] 12 Apr 2019 theorem states that every SWF that satisfies Pareto optimality and independence of ir- relevant alternatives is dictatorial (Arrow, 1951). This sweeping impossibility significantly strengthened an earlier observation by Condorcet (1785) and sent shockwaves throughout welfare economics, political philosophy, economic theory, and even seemingly unrelated disciplines such as philosophy of science and engineering design (see, e.g., Maskin and Sen, 2014; Sen, 2017; Gaertner, 2019).
    [Show full text]
  • The First Challenge to Economic Rationality: Revisiting Allais Paradox
    Review International of Journal Management and Social Researches Uluslararası Yönetim ve Sosyal Araştırmalar Dergisi ISSN:2148-1415/ e-ISSN:2651-3072 Makale Başvuru/Kabul Tarihleri: Received/Accepted Dates: Volume 7, Issue 13, Year 2020 02.10.2019/17.12.2019 The First Challenge to Economic Rationality: Revisiting Allais Paradox Assoc. Prof. Dr. Gelengül KOÇASLAN Istanbul University, Faculty of Economics [email protected] Abstract Allais Paradox is the first revealed violation of the underlying tenets of the theory of expected utility which has been the basic reference on economic behavior and economic decision making under risk since it was first suggested in 1944 by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern. What makes Allais Paradox special is the paradox does not only violate the basic tenets of the theory of expected utility but also violates the independence axiom which is known as the heart of it. This violation provides evidence that adding a third alternative to the existing preferences matters. The aim of the study is to explain the first challenge to economic rationality; Allais Paradox and to show how the independence axiom which is known as the heart axiom of the theory of expected utility is violated. By revealing the paradox and the axiom; it is also aimed to call attention to the importance of this violation with regard to asset and insurance markets for future research. Keywords: Rationality, Allais Paradox, Axioms, Independence Axiom, The Theory of Expected Utility, Prospect Theory. INTRODUCTION Still being a basic reference in economics research; the theory of expected utility examining economic behavior under risk and uncertainty was suggested by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1944.
    [Show full text]
  • Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making
    Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making Andrej Démuth Edition Cognitive Studies Game Theory and the Problem of Decision–Making Andrej Démuth Edition Cognitive Studies Peer reviewers Content Prof. PhDr. Silvia Gáliková, CSc., RNDr. Mgr. Reginald Adrián Slavkovský, Ph.D. Editorial Board Doc. Andrej Démuth ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Josef Dolista ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Silvia Gáliková ∙ Trnavská univerzita Prof. Peter Gärdenfors ∙ Lunds Universitet Dr. Richard Gray ∙ Cardiff University Doc. Marek Petrů ∙ Univerzita Palackého ∙ Olomouc 1. Game theory and the problem Dr. Adrián Slavkovský ∙ Trnavská univerzita of decision–making ................................. 12 1.1 What is game theory? ............................... 12 1.2 Why study game theory? ........................... 13 1.3 Who studies game theory? ......................... 13 1.4 History of game theory .............................. 14 1.5 Game theory and philosophy . 18 1.6 Recommended literature ............................ 18 2. Terminology ......................................... 19 2.1 The game ............................................. 19 2.2 Choice and strategy ................................. 20 2.3 Probability and the theory of possible worlds . 21 2.4 Outcomes ............................................ 21 2.5 Starting points ...................................... 22 2.6 Deciding with certainty, imperfect The publication of this book is part of the project Innovative Forms of Education in Transform- information and with risk ..........................
    [Show full text]