Madness in Socratic Philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Epictetus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Madness in Socratic Philosophy: Xenophon, Plato and Epictetus View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by St Andrews Research Repository MADNESS IN SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY XENOPHON, PLATO AND EPICTETU S Matthew James Shelton A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2019 Full metadata for this thesis is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this thesis: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/17447 This item is protected by original copyright This item is licensed under a Creative Commons License https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ MADNESS IN SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY XENOPHON, PLATO AND EPICTETUS Matthew James Shelton This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) at the University of St Andrews September 2018 Candidate's declaration I, Matthew James Shelton, do hereby certify that this thesis, submitted for the degree of PhD, which is approximately 80,000 words in length, has been written by me, and that it is the record of work carried out by me, or principally by myself in collaboration with others as acknowledged, and that it has not been submitted in any previous application for any degree. I was admitted as a research student at the University of St Andrews in September 2014. I received funding from an organisation or institution and have acknowledged the funder(s) in the full text of my thesis. Date Signature of candidate Supervisor's declaration I hereby certify that the candidate has fulfilled the conditions of the Resolution and Regulations appropriate for the degree of PhD in the University of St Andrews and that the candidate is qualified to submit this thesis in application for that degree. Date Signature of supervisor Permission for publication In submitting this thesis to the University of St Andrews we understand that we are giving permission for it to be made available for use in accordance with the regulations of the University Library for the time being in force, subject to any copyright vested in the work not being affected thereby. We also understand, unless exempt by an award of an embargo as requested below, that the title and the abstract will be published, and that a copy of the work may be made and supplied to any bona fide library or research worker, that this thesis will be electronically accessible for personal or research use and that the library has the right to migrate this thesis into new electronic forms as required to ensure continued access to the thesis. I, Matthew James Shelton, confirm that my thesis does not contain any third-party material that requires copyright clearance. The following is an agreed request by candidate and supervisor regarding the publication of this thesis: Printed copy No embargo on print copy. Electronic copy No embargo on electronic copy. Date Signature of candidate Date Signature of supervisor Underpinning Research Data or Digital Outputs Candidate's declaration I, Matthew James Shelton, hereby certify that no requirements to deposit original research data or digital outputs apply to this thesis and that, where appropriate, secondary data used have been referenced in the full text of my thesis. Date Signature of candidate ABSTRACT My central claim is that three Socratic philosophers, Xenophon, Plato and Epictetus, engage with views presented as non-philosophical in their discussions of madness, and this engagement, which has not been sufficiently treated by previous scholarship, plays a key role in each thinker’s distinct rhetorical strategy. Xenophon’s Socrates conserves a popular definition of madness in the Memorabilia, but adds his own account of what is similar to madness. Xenophon does not merely make Socrates transmit conventional views; instead, Socrates’ comparison allows Xenophon to take rhetorical advantage of popular attitudes while enlarging the apotreptic scope of madness. Socrates can use comparisons with madness to deal with a great many people, including his rivals, the natural scientists, and various interlocutors who, unlike the mad, can still benefit from his teaching. In the Phaedrus, Plato’s Socrates employs a concept of madness which, I argue, is applied without equivocation across both of his speeches in the first part of the dialogue. Importantly, Socrates’ inclusion of rational philosophy as a kind of madness is not presented as a distortion of this concept. The connections between madness, love and philosophy are drawn from non- philosophical material, in particular poetry and comedy, and Socrates engages with a popular caricature of the philosopher as eccentric or mad. Instead of rejecting the caricature, Socrates re- evaluates philosophical madness by explaining the transformation of the philosopher’s soul. Epictetus’ view of madness is less compromising, and this is to be expected considering the Stoic doctrine that all who are unwise are mad. Like earlier Stoics, however, Epictetus recognises a surprising range of non-Stoic distinctions within madness. Although he engages with these distinctions, he does so only to undermine them and to bring his audience round to the realisation that they are mad once their own views are applied consistently with respect to Stoic teaching. i ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My first thanks are to my supervisor, Dr Alex Long. Without his continued advice and support, many of the thoughts expressed in this thesis would not have reached fruition. His Stoic patience combined with his Socratic knack for asking just the right questions has helped to shape my work in innumerable ways. Any shortcomings or faults are entirely my own. This research was funded in part by the Professor Ian Kidd Bequest for Classics. I am extremely grateful to the donors, and I am pleased to have included some of Professor Kidd’s work on Posidonius in my chapter on Epictetus and the Stoics. I also extend my thanks to St Leonard’s College for its support. I am indebted to generous funding from the National Research Foundation of South Africa and likewise wish to thank the Oppenheimer Memorial Trust (my thanks especially to Clare Digby). I owe a debt of thanks to all those who have taken time to offer helpful feedback and advice at various points throughout this project. In no particular order, I would like to thank David Konstan, Christopher Gill, Chiara Thumiger, Melissa Lane, Tom Angier, Mary Louise Gill, Naoya Iwata, Aneurin Ellis-Evans, Katherine Van Schaik, James Zainaldin, Clive Chandler and Garrett Fagan†. Additional thanks go to Kate McLachlan, Matthew Payne, Julia Pfefferkorn, Jenny Messenger and Kieta Papier for reading and commenting on drafts. St Andrews has been an ideal place to work, not least because of my wonderful colleagues. I thank my academic mentor in the School of Classics, Stephen Halliwell, who has given me every encouragement. I am also grateful to Emma Gee who first got me thinking about the Phaedrus, and to my annual reviewers who have often given extremely helpful feedback, especially Tom Harrison, Giuseppe Pezzini, Jason König and Jon Hesk. The time I spent in the Greek Reading Group was easily my most stimulating and enjoyable at St Andrews. Many thanks to all the stalwarts of the GRG for the serious discussion and for the laughs, especially to Sarah Broadie and Peter Woodward. ii Writing a PhD can be lonely. I want to thank all my fellow PhD students in the School of Classics for keeping me sane, especially and in no specific order: Ellen MacDougal, Caroline Belanger, Matthew Payne, Jenny Messenger, Alastair Lumsden, Doug Forsyth, Jo Norton-Curry, Chloe Bray, Michael Furman, Gabriel Gabbardo, Mary Dodd, Laura Conroy, Eugenio Rallo, James Crooks, Ben Naylor, Anouk Vermeulen and Manlio Fossati. I also wish to thank the librarians at the St Andrews University Library and the administrative staff in the School of Classics. They made a lot of hard work behind the scenes seem effortless. I have been lucky to have the support of family and friends both in the United Kingdom and in South Africa. Thanks to my Cape Town friends and colleagues, especially Lena Sulik, Berenice Bentel and Jeffrey Murray. Thanks also to Vanessa Everson for restorative retreats at Curley Croft, to my Cambridge family, Alison and Daisy, for their warm hospitality, and to Justin Sulik for helping me find my feet in Scotland. I thank my parents in Cape Town, Lynette and Ian, whose encouragement and love have always helped and inspired me. I also thank my parents in Newfoundland, Peter and Joanne, whose love and generosity have always made me feel at home. Further thanks to my brothers, Jem and Naul, my step-brothers and my sister Ruth. My final thanks go to my partner and my inspiration, Elizabeth Braae. You have always had time for my rambling discussions, and you have suffered through countless drafts. Your insights and help have been simply invaluable, and your effect on this work is felt throughout. Thank you for your love and for believing in me. I dedicate this thesis to the memory of my grandmother, Kate Gwendoline Shelton (née Bain). iii ABBREVIATIONS Abbreviations of the names of ancient authors and the titles of their works are generally those in Hornblower, S., and Spawforth, A. (eds.) (2012) Oxford Classical Dictionary, 4th edn. Oxford. The following additional abbreviations are used for ancient and modern authors and collections: Aff. Dig. Galen, De propriorum animi cuiuslibet affectuum dignotione et curatione CMG Corpus Medicorum Graecorum DK Diels, H., and Kranz, W. (1951-2) Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Berlin. DL Diogenes Laertius EK Edelstein, L., and Kidd, I. G. (1972-99) Posidonius: Fragments. 3 vols. Cambridge. Indelli Indelli, G. (1988) Filodemo, L'ira. Naples. LS Long, A. A., and Sedley, D.
Recommended publications
  • Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod
    https://doi.org/10.31871/WJRR.9.1.9 World Journal of Research and Review (WJRR) ISSN:2455-3956, Volume-9, Issue-1, July 2019 Pages 26-30 Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod Juan S. Gómez-Jeria His diverse pupils, though proclaiming themselves similarly Abstract—I use the cylinder-ladder model presented in the faithful, presented opposing images of him. And in each of previous paper of this series to present and defend the thesis them, legend and history are probably mixed. Some that Sokrates was placed in a step much higher than those that well-known biographic details follow. There is a certain were occupied by almost all mortals regarding the degree of perception of reality and that he could perfectly be situated in possibility that some facts are not exactly as they are told, the category of ‘demigod’ as defined in this paper. Plato´s even that some are just gossip, but that is not important in this Apology is considered the most probable and unique context. Sokratic-like text. Furthermore, I claim that Sokrates knew that he was (relatively) wiser than those around him due to its higher position on the cylinder-ladder. This last statement opens new questions about the response of the Pythia. Sokrates was clear that his discourse would be understood by his listeners accordingly to the place they occupied in the cylinder-ladder model. This is the reason because, after Sokrates death, so many different Socratic schools appeared. Finally, I firmly hold the idea that one day we will discover that our knowledge of Sokrates has not grown one iota since his death.
    [Show full text]
  • The Coherence of Stoic Ontology
    The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Prof. Dorothea Frede, Co-chair Prof. Klaus Corcilius, Co-chair Prof. A.A. Long Spring 2012 Abstract The Coherence of Stoic Ontology by Vanessa de Harven Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Berkeley Professors Dorothea Frede and Klaus Corcilius, Co-chairs Any thoroughgoing physicalist is challenged to give an account of immaterial entities such as thoughts and mathematical objects. The Stoics, who eagerly affirmed that only bodies exist, crafted an elegant solution to this challenge: not everything that is Something (ti) exists. Rather, some things have a derivative mode of reality they call subsistence: these entities are non-existent in that they are not themselves solid bodies, but they are nonetheless Something physical because they depend on bodies for their subsistence. My dissertation uncovers the unifying principles of Stoic subsistence, and shows how they can account for thoughts and other immaterial entities without running afoul of their physicalist commitments. While all commentators agree that the Stoics posited Something as the highest category of being, they have failed to find a coherent physicalist account of Stoic ontology. For instance, (1) a canonical set of incorporeals (time, place, void, and what is sayable (lekton)) is well attested, but there is little agreement as to what these entities have in common as incorporeals, which makes the category look like an ad hoc collection of left-over entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Platons Raumbegriff Verständlich, Desgleichen Der Umstand, Daß Timaios Grenzen Einer Erklärung Der Welt Und Schwierigkeiten Einer Konsistenten Darstellung Hervorhebt
    Der Begriff des Raumes im „Timaios“ im Zusammenhang mit der Naturphilosophie und der Metaphysik Platons Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie der Philosophischen Fakultät der Universität Konstanz vorgelegt von Kyung Jik Lee aus Seoul Referent: Prof. Dr. Jürgen Mittelstraß Korreferent: Prof. Dr. Gereon Wolters Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 19. Juli 1999 Diese Arbeit erscheint im Mai 2000 auch als Buchhandelsausgabe im Verlag Königshausen & Neumann, Würzburg Meinen Eltern gewidmet Inhaltsverzeichnis Vorwort 9 I Die Erklärung der Welt als wahrscheinliche Erklärung (eikôs logos) 11 1 Einleitung 2 Die Synonymität von eikôs mythos und eikôs logos 3 Der eikôs logos als nicht-philosophische Erklärung 4 Der eikôs logos 4.1 Akribês logos? 4.2 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Historische 4.3 Das Wahrscheinliche und das Notwendige 4.4 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als inkonsistente Rede 4.5 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als hypothetische Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände 4.6 Die wahrscheinliche Rede als Begrenzung der Anwendung einer exakten Erklärung auf sinnliche Gegenstände II Der Demiurg und der Logos der Welt 38 1 Einleitung 2 Wer ist der Demiurg im „Timaios“? 3 Demiurg und Gott 4 Demiurg und Weltseele 5 Demiurg und Idee des Guten 6 Demiurg und transzendente Vernunft 7 Schwierigkeiten der Rede vom Demiurgen 7.1 Zur Suche nach dem Demiurgen 7.2 Logos und Ergon 7.3 Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.1 Einleitung 7.3.2 Poiêtês 7.3.3 Weitere Parallelen zwischen Demiurg und Timaios 7.3.4 Gott und Götter 7.4 Der Demiurg
    [Show full text]
  • Willing the Good: Agathon and Prohairesis
    The Roman Stoics: Seneca and Epictetus 3 Willing the Good: Agathon and Prohairesis 1. The Good Benefits, and so Does Virtue (1) Aetius (Greek doxographer, c. 100 CE): “The Stoics said that wisdom (σοφία) is scientific knowledge (ἐπιστήµη, epistēmē) of the divine and the human, and that philosophy is the practice of expertise in utility (φιλοσοφίαν ἄσκησιν ἐπιτηδείου τέχνης). Virtue first and foremost is utility, and virtues, at their most generic, are triple: the physical one (φυσικόν), the ethical one (ἠθικόν), and the logical one (λογικόν). Hence philosophy too has three parts: physics, ethics and logic. Physics is practised whenever we investigate the world and what is in it, ethics is our engagement with human life, and logic our engagement with discourse, which they also call dialectic.” (LS 26A, SVF 2.35). (2) Seneca’s point in The Happy Life, ‘true happiness is located in virtue’ (16.1). So, there is a connection between happiness (eudaimonia), virtue, and the good (ἀγαθὸν, agathon). Aristotle’s idea: the good is the end (aim) of all action. The highest good (i.e. the ariston) is self-sufficient (autarkes) and final (teleion), and so the (super-)end of action (tōn praktōn ousa telos; NE I.7 1097b20). So, formally, the good is what is not done for the sake of anything else. (Note there is a range of ‘lower’ goods—the ‘indifferents’. Their value is instrumental; some of these goods are ‘worth choosing’; see below). (3) The highest (and only real) good is virtue; the only bad is vice. The good constitutes a genuine benefit for the individual, it has utility; it is intrinsically valuable (as just hinted: an end in itself); the key to a happy life.
    [Show full text]
  • Anton Powell, Nicolas Richer (Eds.), Xenophon and Sparta, the Classical Press of Wales, Swansea 2020, 378 Pp.; ISBN 978-1-910589-74-8
    ELECTRUM * Vol. 27 (2020): 213–216 doi:10.4467/20800909EL.20.011.12801 www.ejournals.eu/electrum Anton Powell, Nicolas Richer (eds.), Xenophon and Sparta, The Classical Press of Wales, Swansea 2020, 378 pp.; ISBN 978-1-910589-74-8 The reviewed book is a collection of twelve papers, previously presented at the confe- rence organised by École Normale Supérieure in Lyon in 2006. According to the edi- tors, this is a first volume in the planned series dealing with sources of Spartan his- tory. The books that follow this will deal with the presence of this topic in works by Thucydides, Herodotus, Plutarch, and in archaeological material. The decision to start the cycle from Xenophon cannot be considered as surprising; this ancient author has not only written about Sparta, but also had opportunities to visit the country, person- ally met a number of its officials (including king Agesilaus), and even sent his own sons for a Spartan upbringing. Thus his writings are widely considered as our best source to the history of Sparta in the classical age. Despite this, Xenophon’s literary work remains the subject of numerous controver- sies in discussions among modern scholars. The question of his objectivity is especial- ly problematic and the views about the strong partisanship of Xenophon prevailed for a long time; allegedly, he was depicting Sparta and king Agesilaus in a possibly overly positive light, even omitting inconvenient information.1 In the second half of the 20th century such opinion has been met with a convincing polemic, clearly seen in the works of H.
    [Show full text]
  • Language Logic and Reality: a Stoic Perspective (Spring 2013)
    Language Logic and Reality: A Stoic Perspective Aaron Tuor History of Lingustics WWU Spring 2013 1 Language, Logic, and Reality: A Stoic perspective Contents 1 Introduction: The Tripartite Division of Stoic Philosophy.............................3 2 Stoic Physics...................................................................................................4 3 Stoic Dialectic.................................................................................................4 3.1 A Stoic Theory of Mind: Logos and presentations..........................4 3.2 Stoic Philosophy of Language: Lekta versus linguistic forms.........6 3.3 Stoic Logic.......................................................................................7 3.3.1 Simple and Complex Axiomata........................................7 3.3.2 Truth Conditions and Sentence Connectives....................8 3.3.3 Inference Schemata and Truths of Logic..........................9 3.4 Stoic Theory of Knowledge.............................................................10 3.4.1 Truth..................................................................................10 3.4.2 Knowledge........................................................................11 4 Conclusion: Analysis of an eristic argument..................................................12 4.1 Hermogenes as the Measure of "Man is the measure."...................13 Appendix I: Truth Tables and Inference Schemata...........................................17 Appendix II: Diagram of Communication.........................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato
    Article Hic Sunt Leones: Mythologies and Partisan Constructions of the Good Philosopher in Plato Sergio Alloggio https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7273-3954 University of Pretoria [email protected] Abstract Plato constructs the philosopher in contrast to the sophist. Both sophistical and rhetorical logos, in their epistemic closeness to philosophical logos, require a constant act of demarcation throughout Plato’s works. The challenge posed by the sophists creates a structural, instable tension in several Platonic dialogues. Why is the Athenian philosopher obsessed by a different yet comparable approach to virtue, knowledge and social order? Why does the Athenian philosopher need and, at the same time, reject the sophist when it comes to shaping his own self-image? To try to answer these questions, I will go back to a foundational moment where the Platonic philosopher is theoretically constructed and conceptually produced against the sophist, namely, Plato’s Sophist, Statesman, Protagoras, Gorgias and Phaedrus. The aim of the article is to show how the Platonic philosopher is conveniently defined through a series of partisan demarcations grounded on ontological privilege, epistemic exclusion, ethical circularity and, ultimately, political delegitimation. Keywords: Plato; dialectic; demarcation; partisanship; sophistics; agonistics; delegitimation Decolonization was the preoccupation of two [T]he unconscious has first and foremost to do with groups that propelled the nationalist movement: the grammar … This also has a bit to do, or much to intelligentsia and the political class. They set out to do, or everything to do, with repetition, that is, create the nation, the former to give the with the aspect that is entirely the opposite of what independent state a history and the latter to create a a dictionary is used for … Grammar and repetition common citizenship as the basis of national constitute a completely different aspect from what sovereignty.
    [Show full text]
  • EPICTETUS AS SOCRATIC MENTOR1 in Tom Wolfe's Most Recent Novel, a Man in Full, a Young Californian, Down on His Luck, Converts A
    EPICTETUS AS SOCRATIC MENTOR1 In Tom Wolfe's most recent novel, A Man In Full, a young Californian, down on his luck, converts a macho sixty-year old tycoon, facing financial ruin, to Stoicism.2 The young man, Conrad, has miraculously escaped from the Santa Rita gaol as a result of an earthquake. Shortly before, he had discovered Epictetus in a book called The Stoics, a book he had been sent mistakenly in place of a riveting thriller by his favourite author with the title, The Stoics' Game. He rapidly comes across this passage: T [Zeus] gave you a portion of our divinity, a spark from our own fire, the power to act and not to act, the will to get and the will to avoid. If you pay heed to this, you will not groan, you will blame no man, you will flatter none' (p. 398). Conrad is hooked. An innocent among a bunch of hideous felons, he asks himself: 'What would Epictetus have done with this bunch? What could he have done? How could you apply his lessons two thousand years later, in this grimy gray pod, this pigsty full of beasts who grunted about mother-fuckin this and mother-fuckin that?' (p. 410). Conrad memorises chunks of Epictetus. He refers a series of challenges to Zeus, overcomes a thug twice his size, and radiates Stoic strength. At the end, hired as a male nurse in Atlanta for the massive but now ailing Croker, the about-to-be ruined tycoon, Conrad tells Croker about the Stoic Zeus and Epictetus.
    [Show full text]
  • Index of Passages General Index
    BmLIOGRAPHY INDEX OF PASSAGES GENERAL INDEX BmLIOGRAPHY Allen, Reginald E., ed. 1965. Studies in Plato's Metaphysics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. --- 1970. Plato's HEuthyphro' and the Earlier Theory ofForms. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. --- 1971. "Plato's Earlier Theory of Forms." In Vlastos (1971: 329-334). 1980. Socrates and Legal Obligation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. --- 1983. Plato's Parmenides. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. --- 1984. Euthyphro; Apology; Crito; Meno; Gorgias; Menexe1Uls. The Dialogues of Plato I. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. --- 1991. The Symposium. The Dialogues ofPlato II. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Annas, Julia 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. -- 1992. "Plato the Sceptic." In Klagge and Smith (1992: 43-72). Arnim, H. von 1896. De Platonis Dialogis Quaestiones Chronologicae, Vorlesungsver- zeichnis der Universitiit Rostock fUr das W.-Semester 1896. Barnes, Jonathan 1991. "Socrates the Hedonist." In Boudouris (1991: 22-32). Beck, Robert H. 1985. "Plato's Views on Teaching." Educational Theory 35:2, 119-134. Benardete, S. 1991. The Rhetoric of Morality and Philosophy: Plato's Gorgias and Phaedrus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Benson, Hugh H. 1987. "The Problem of the Elenchus Reconsidered." Ancient Philosophy 7,67-85. ---, ed. 1992. Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates. New York: Oxford University Press. Bernal, Martin 1987. Black Athena: The Afroasiatic Roots ofClassical Civilization. Vol. I: The Fabrication ofAncient Greece 1785-1985. London: Free Association Books. Beversluis, John 1993. "Vlastos's Quest for the Historical Socrates." Ancient Philosophy 13,293-312. Boudouris, K. 1., ed. 1991. The Philosophy ofSocrates. Athens: International Center for Greek Philosophy and Culture.
    [Show full text]
  • DL Socrates Handout
    ISSS Virtual Socrates Colloquium 2021 Afterlives of an Eminent Philosopher: Socrates in Diogenes Laertius Stephen White, University of Texas at Austin, 9 June 2021 I. Socrates in the Lives: philosophy’s genealogy and a founder’s legacy 1. Plan of the Lives B1. Origins: Thales, sages, Pherecydes Ionic branch from Thales in Books 2-7 B2. Anaximander, Anaximenes, Anaxagoras, Archelaus B2. Socrates: Socratics Xenophon, Aeschines Aristippus: Cyrenaics; Phaedo (Eretriacs); Euclides: Megarics Crito (4 sons), Simon, Glaucon, Simmias, Cebes B3. Plato: Academics & Peripatetics B4. Academics B5. Aristotle: Peripatetics B6. Antisthenes: Cynics B7. Zeno: Stoics Italic branch from Pherecydes in Books 8-10 B8. Pythagoras: Pythagoreans B9. Heraclitus; Eleatics, Atomists, Protagoras … Pyrrho: Pyrrhonists B10. Epicurus: Epicureans 2. Preview of Lives organized by teacher-student succession: Lives 1.13-15 φιλοσοφίας δὲ δύο γεγόνασιν ἀρχαί, (B2) ἥ τε ἀπὸ Ἀναξιµάνδρου καὶ (B8) ἡ ἀπὸ Πυθαγόρου· τοῦ µὲν Θαλοῦ διακηκοότος, Πυθαγόρου δὲ Φερεκύδης καθηγήσατο. καὶ ἐκαλεῖτο ἡ µὲν Ἰωνική, ὅτι Θαλῆς Ἴων ὤν, Μιλήσιος γάρ, καθηγήσατο Ἀναξιµάνδρου· ἡ δὲ Ἰταλικὴ ἀπὸ Πυθαγόρου, ὅτι τὰ πλεῖστα κατὰ τὴν Ἰταλίαν ἐφιλοσόφησε. [14] καταλήγει δὲ ἡ µὲν εἰς (B4) Κλειτόµαχον καὶ (B7) Χρύσιππον καὶ (B5) Θεόφραστον ἡ Ἰωνική· ἡ δὲ Ἰταλικὴ εἰς (B10) Ἐπίκουρον. (B2) Θαλοῦ µὲν γὰρ Ἀναξίµανδρος, οὗ Ἀναξιµένης, οὗ Ἀναξαγόρας, οὗ Ἀρχέλαος, οὗ Σωκράτης ὁ τὴν ἠθικὴν εἰσαγαγών· οὗ οἵ τε ἄλλοι Σωκρατικοὶ καὶ (B3) Πλάτων ὁ τὴν ἀρχαίαν Ἀκαδηµίαν συστησάµενος· (B4) οὗ Σπεύσιππος καὶ Ξενοκράτης, οὗ Πολέµων, οὗ Κράντωρ καὶ Κράτης, οὗ Ἀρκεσίλαος ὁ τὴν µέσην Ἀκαδηµίαν εἰσηγησάµενος· οὗ Λακύδης ὁ τὴν νέαν Ἀκαδηµίαν φιλοσοφήσας· οὗ Καρνεάδης, οὗ Κλειτόµαχος. καὶ ὧδε µὲν εἰς Κλειτόµαχον.
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. Paper 641. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]