Kremer University of Notre Dame

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Kremer University of Notre Dame NOÛS 35:1 ~2001! 39–73 The Purpose of Tractarian Nonsense* Michael Kremer University of Notre Dame “To use a word without a justification does not mean to use it without right.” ~Wittgenstein, 1958, §289! I. Wittgenstein’s closing remarks in the Tractatus have long puzzled his readers. His propositions, he tells us, are nonsense, and to understand him is to recog- nize this. Yet how can recognizing his pronouncements as nonsense count as a kind of understanding? Of what value could this understanding be? We can rec- ognize Jabberwocky as nonsense, and in doing so we can perhaps achieve some sort of understanding of Lewis Carroll. However, Jabberwocky does not open with a claim to deal with the problems of philosophy and to bring them to a definitive resolution. Moreover, Jabberwocky wears its nonsensicality on its sleeve; it is obvious nonsense and we recognize it as such from its first sen- tence. The typical reader of the Tractatus, on the other hand, will begin by sup- posing herself to be reading a book of philosophy, intended as a straightforward communication of intelligible thought. This thought may appear difficult and its expression highly compressed; the reader may struggle to come to an under- standing of the author’s point of view; but if the reader persists and makes it to the end of the book, it may surprise her to learn that she is to dismiss as non- sense what she had taken herself to understand. She may infer that she has un- derstood nothing at all, and throw the book away—yet not in the way seemingly intended by Wittgenstein’s image of the ladder which one throws away after climbing it—for this reader will not have been transformed in any interesting way by the experience, except perhaps in acquiring a distaste for certain kinds of philosophy. I recently encountered an example of such a reaction in a “read- er’s review” of the Tractatus posted by the Internet bookseller Amazon.com. The reviewer1 writes, under the heading “A lot of bloated nonsense”: © 2001 Blackwell Publishers Inc., 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA, and 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK. 39 40 NOÛS Wittgenstein must be the most over rated philosopher who has ever lived. Because of the work ~and marketing! of a few devoted students, the rest of us have been led to believe that he is one of the great ones. The truth is nothing of the sort. He couldn’t write clearly. The result is much undeserved attention has been given to some very ambiguous epigrammatic statements of his. Much of his work is unreadable and of no use or interest to anyone but a few hard core positivist philosophy professors. If you really want to read some good philosophy, do not be unjustifiably taken in by the weird mystique of the Wittgenstein name. It is all P.R. work by some ivy league philosophers who do not even care anymore if philsophy @sic# has anything useful to say to people who live in the real world. As long as they can continue to collect their salaries and analyze their little language puzzles in the privacy of their faculty offices, they are happy-and irrelevant to the lives of anyone who actually works outside of a university. Save yourself the bother of trying to decipher this guy; It isn’t worth your trouble. A more determined reader may, however, wish to hold onto the thought that he has understood something in reading the earlier sections of the Tractatus. He may discern there a theory of metaphysics, or of language, or of the mind, which attracts or repels him. He may see in the work arguments for and against important positions, which can be elaborated, defended or refuted. He may ex- pend great energy on these tasks. He may even conclude that Wittgenstein has shown, through important arguments, that certain views or theories are founded on nonsense and irredeemably confused. Yet in thus concluding, he will take Wittgenstein himself to have presented a philosophical view, which may itself be mistaken in whole or in part, and may even involve various confusions, but is not simply nonsense. Most commentators have implicitly taken this approach to reading the Trac- tatus, in attempting to explain Wittgenstein’s doctrine on this or that philosoph- ical issue. Peter Carruthers is more explicit, claiming that “the doctrine of philosophy as nonsense may simply be excised from @the Tractatus#, without damage to the remainder,” attributing this “doctrine” to Wittgenstein’s having over-generalized a “theory of semantic content...adequate...for factual ~broadly scientific! discourse...to cover discourse of all kinds, including...philosophy.” ~Carruthers 1990, 5!. To read the Tractatus in this way is to take Wittgenstein to have made at least one major error in classifying his own propositions as non- sense, and to suggest that at a certain fundamental level Wittgenstein did not properly understand his own activity or accomplishment. For interpreters such as Carruthers, we can best appreciate Wittgenstein’s achievement by simply dis- missing the self-destructive climax of the Tractatus. In contrast, the “resolute” interpretation of the Tractatus, so-called by War- ren Goldfarb and Thomas Ricketts, forcefully developed by Cora Diamond and James Conant, insists that we take seriously Wittgenstein’s claim that his prop- ositions are nonsense, that they constitute a ladder that we are to throw away.2 Diamond suggests, following Wittgenstein’s advice to Ficker ~Wittgenstein 1979a, 95!, that we look to the Preface and closing sections of the book, which The Purpose of Tractarian Nonsense 41 she calls its “frame,” for indications as to how to read the work. ~Diamond 1991, 55!. The Preface tells us that the book will draw a limit not to thought, but to the expression of thought, in language. What lies on the other side of the limit will be “einfach Unsinn”—simply nonsense. ~Wittgenstein 1933, p. 27!.3 The penultimate section of the work itself tells us that to understand Wittgenstein, we must recognize his propositions to be nonsense, so that we can climb through them, on them, over them, in the end discarding them entirely. ~6.54!. The book is not a textbook, according to the Preface ~p. 27!; the philosophy that it teaches us is not a doctrine, but an activity of clarification in which we make explicit the content that is already completely present and in order in the propositions of ordinary language. ~4.112, 5.5563!. At the same time, this activity of clari- fication can help us to see how ordinary language makes possible various am- biguities and confusions, ~3.323! which allow, through what Wittgenstein calls “the misunderstanding of the logic of our language” the formulation of the ap- parent but unreal “problems of philosophy.” ~p. 27, 3.324, 4.003!. In becoming aware of these confusions and the illusions they generate, we unmask the prob- lems of philosophy as consisting not of errors but nonsense. Thus we “solve” them in a way more definitive than any philosophical argument could provide. Diamond initially introduces the idea of the “frame” of the book, in accor- dance with the implicit spatial metaphor, as comprising the Preface and final propositions of the Tractatus. However, as the above summary makes clear, the resolute interpretation also takes its cue from propositions occurring in the rest of the work. Conant explains that “the distinction between what is part of the frame and what is part of the body of the work is not, as some commentators have thought, simply a function of where in the work a remark occurs ~say, in the beginning or near the end of the book!. Rather, it is a function of how it occurs.” The place of a proposition in the frame or the body is determined by “its role in the work.” ~Conant forthcoming, 151, fn. 195!. Thus Conant counts several passages from the middle of the work as parts of the frame rather than the body.4 While such “framing” propositions are not among those proclaimed in the end to be nonsense, they are also not part of an elaborate philosophical theory that the book sets forward. They are instructions for reading the book. Our abil- ity to understand these instructions does not depend on our grasp of a complex theoretical reconstruction of such notions as sense and nonsense, thought and truth. Rather, it is based on our ordinary understanding of these notions, our ordinary use of these words. On the resolute reading, as I understand it, Wittgenstein’s view of meaning, sense and nonsense in the Tractatus is simply this: meaningful linguistic expressions are those that have a use in the lan- guage.5 The most basic use which we make of language is to say something; expressions that have the same use, or can be used to say the same things, have the same meaning, while expressions that have no use in saying things are mean- ingless. ~3.328, 5.47321!. Nonsense arises when we construct apparent sen- tences containing meaningless words—words for which we have failed to make 42 NOÛS a determination of meaning. ~5.473!. When we come to recognize the proposi- tions of the Tractatus as nonsense, we realize that these propositions have not been given a use in which they say anything, because they contain words that have not been given a determinate meaning, a use in combinations of signs that say something. This realization is not the conclusion of an elaborate argument based on a theory of meaning. It is the result of the attempt to grasp the mean- ing that the sentences purport to have, and of the disintegration of any sense that there is such a meaning, in the process of trying to think through what that would involve.
Recommended publications
  • Rethinking Fideism Through the Lens of Wittgenstein's Engineering Outlook
    University of Dayton eCommons Religious Studies Faculty Publications Department of Religious Studies 2012 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad Kallenberg University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other Religion Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons eCommons Citation Kallenberg, Brad, "Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook" (2012). Religious Studies Faculty Publications. 82. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/rel_fac_pub/82 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Religious Studies at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Note: This is the accepted manuscript for the following article: Kallenberg, Brad J. “Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, no. 1 (2012): 55-73. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11153-011-9327-0 Rethinking Fideism through the Lens of Wittgenstein’s Engineering Outlook Brad J. Kallenberg University of Dayton, 2011 In an otherwise superbly edited compilation of student notes from Wittgenstein’s 1939 Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cora Diamond makes an false step that reveals to us our own tendencies to misread Wittgenstein. The student notes she collated attributed the following remark to a student named Watson: “The point is that these [data] tables do not by themselves determine that one builds the bridge in this way: only the tables together with certain scientific theory determine that.”1 But Diamond thinks this a mistake, presuming instead to change the manuscript and put these words into the mouth of Wittgenstein.
    [Show full text]
  • The Method of Wittgenstein's Tractatus
    The Method of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus: Toward a New Interpretation Nikolay Milkov, University of Paderborn, Germany Abstract This paper introduces a novel interpretation of Wittgenstein‘s Tractatus, a work widely held to be one of the most intricate in the philosophical canon. It maintains that the Tractatus does not develop a theory but rather advances an original logical symbolism, a new instrument that enables one to ―recognize the formal properties of propositions by mere inspection of propositions themselves‖ (6.122). Moreover, the Tractarian conceptual notation offers to instruct us on how better to follow the logic of language, and by that token stands to enhance our ability to think. Upon acquiring the thinking skills that one can develop by working with the new symbolism, one may move on and discard the notation—―throw away the ladder‖ (6.54), as Wittgenstein put it. 1. The New Wittgensteinians This paper introduces a novel interpretation of Wittgenstein‘s Tractatus. In the process, it takes issue with the New Wittgensteinians, in particular Cora Diamond and James Conant,1 who some twenty-five years ago fielded a comprehensive, essentially skeptical interpretation of the entire body of the Tractatus. Diamond and Conant argued that the core propositions of the Tractatus are literally nonsense, gibberish equivalent to phrases like ―piggly wiggle tiggle‖ (Diamond, 2000, p. 151). To be more explicit, Diamond and Conant defended their view that the book‘s core content is philosophically vacuous by arguing (i) that the Tractatus is divided into a body and a frame; (ii) that the Preface, 3.32–3.326, 4–4.003, 4.111–2 and 6.53–6.54 compose the frame (Conant 2001, p.
    [Show full text]
  • A REDUCTIVE READING of the TRACTATUS Interpretation of the Book Being About How to Defeat Skepticism
    2015 Umeå University, Department of Historical, Philosophical and Religious Studies Stefan Karlsson Supervisor: Andreas Stokke Examinor: Peter Melander Level: Bachelor’s thesis A REDUCTIVE READING OF THE TRACTATUS Interpretation of the book being about how to defeat skepticism. Content Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 4 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................. 5 Contents .................................................................................................................................................. 6 Traditional readings ................................................................................................................................. 7 Meta-physical interpretations ............................................................................................................. 7 Traditional readings of the nonsense concept in the Tractatus ......................................................... 8 The ineffable truth interpretation ................................................................................................... 8 What can be said and what can be shown ...................................................................................... 9 Modern readings ..................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • "Utter Nonsense?" : an Examination of the Linguisitic Theories of F
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 1988 Did you say "utter nonsense?" : an examination of the linguisitic theories of F. de Saussure and Noam Chomsky R.G. Herndon Jr. College of William and Mary Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Recommended Citation Herndon, R.G. Jr., "Did you say "utter nonsense?" : an examination of the linguisitic theories of F. de Saussure and Noam Chomsky" (1988). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 655. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/655 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Did you say "utter Nonsense?" An Examination of the Lingusi tic 'Iheories of F. de Saussure and NoamChomsky A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Bachelor of Arts with Honors in Linguistics and Philosophy fram the College of William and Mary in Virginia By R. G. Her'ndon, Jr. t{\ay 1'183 Accepted for: HOi\O ,S "Youwill observe the Rules of Battle, of course? the ~rute Knight remarked, putting on his helIoot too. "I always do," said the Red Knight, and they began banging awayat each other with such a fury that Alice got behirrl a tree to be out of the \vay of the blows. "I wonder, what the Rules of Battle are;." she said to herself, as she watched the fight, timidly peeping out from her hiding place.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Wayward Student: the Unauthorized Autobiography
    Wittgenstein’s wayward student: the unauthorized autobiography1 Annotated by Curtis Franks2 Note: Our hero has been confined until now to the space allotted him by other writers who only want to bounce their own ideas off of him because of their interest in the re- sulting trajectories. Quite reasonably he feels that he’s never been given a fair shake. His efforts to understand his critics turn up points where their arguments strike him as unconvincing or altogether absent. He delights in these discoveries, but his readers will see them instead as evidence of his own confusion and as clues to the sort of positions his critics adopt. When he meets another idealized character in Penelope Maddy’s Sec- ond Philosopher, he is intrigued by the difference in the treatment he receives. She raises many of the same questions that haunt him, the very considerations that others dismissed. But the answers she provides alienate him even more profoundly. Now that the impasse pervades everything from elementary logic to the higher infinite, new questions are met with a cool nonchalance. Struggling to fathom how she can carry on without the answers he seeks, he unwittingly reveals what sets the Second Philosopher’s position apart from related naturalistic accounts by chronicling how it leads him to confront the idleness of his demands. 1. First things I think the first thing you ought to know about me, if you’re going to appreciate much of what I have to say later on about my main scientific and philosophical agenda—the nature of logic and mathematics as it happens to be—is that I’m a lot older than I’m often made out to be.
    [Show full text]
  • Death and Nonsense in the Poetry of George Macdonaldâ•Žs at the Back of the North Wind and Lewis Carrollâ•Žs Alice Books
    North Wind: A Journal of George MacDonald Studies Volume 30 Article 4 1-1-2011 Death and Nonsense in the Poetry of George MacDonald’s At the Back of the North Wind and Lewis Carroll’s Alice Books Melody Green Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.snc.edu/northwind Recommended Citation Green, Melody (2011) "Death and Nonsense in the Poetry of George MacDonald’s At the Back of the North Wind and Lewis Carroll’s Alice Books," North Wind: A Journal of George MacDonald Studies: Vol. 30 , Article 4. Available at: http://digitalcommons.snc.edu/northwind/vol30/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the English at Digital Commons @ St. Norbert College. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Wind: A Journal of George MacDonald Studies by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ St. Norbert College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Death and Nonsense in the Poetry of George MacDonald’s At the Back of the North Wind and Lewis Carroll’s Alice Books Melody Green n The Literary Products of the George MacDonald-Lewis Carroll FriendshipI, John Docherty explains not only that MacDonald and Carroll were friends for more than 40 years, but also that they explored some of the same ideas in their texts. In “Some Linguistic Moves in the Carroll- MacDonald ‘Literary Game,’” Fernando Soto takes this even further by arguing that these two writers played linguistic games with each other, based on their understanding of the Scottish and Cheshire dialects. Meanwhile, R.
    [Show full text]
  • “Nothing Is Shown”: a 'Resolute' Response
    Philosophical Investigations 26:3 July 2003 ISSN 0190-0536 “Nothing is Shown”: A ‘Resolute’ Response to Mounce, Emiliani, Koethe and Vilhauer Rupert Read and Rob Deans, University of East Anglia Part 1: On Mounce on Wittgenstein (Early and Late) on ‘Saying and Showing’ H. O. Mounce published in this journal two years ago now a Criti- cal Notice of the The New Wittgenstein,1 an anthology (edited by Alice Crary and Rupert Read) which is evenly divided between work on Wittgenstein’s early and later writings. The bulk of Mounce’s article was devoted to those contributions primarily con- cerned with the Tractatus.2 There is a straightforward sense in which this selective focus is natural. The pertinent contributions – most conspicuously those by Cora Diamond and James Conant – describe a strikingly un- orthodox interpretation of Wittgenstein’s early book on which it is depicted as having an anti-metaphysical aim. Mounce takes an inter- est in this interpretation because he believes that, in characterizing the Tractatus in anti-metaphysical terms, it misrepresents the central Tractarian doctrine of ‘saying and showing’ – a doctrine which he understands in terms of the idea that “metaphysical truths, though they cannot be stated, may nevertheless be shown”(186). Mounce argues that Diamond and Conant et al. fail to treat this doctrine as “one that Wittgenstein himself advances,” and he claims that they therefore make Wittgenstein’s thought “less original than one might otherwise suppose” (186) by implying that it is “indistinguishable from positivism” in the sense of “not even attempt[ing] to provide positive knowledge [and] confin[ing] itself to removing the confu- 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein in Exile
    Wittgenstein in Exile “My thoughts are one hundred per cent Hebraic.” -Wittgenstein to Drury, 19491 Wittgenstein was born in 1889 into one of the richest families in Central Europe. He lived and learned at home, in Vienna, until 1903, when he was 14. We have no record of his thoughts about the turn of the last century, but it is unlikely that it seemed very significant to him. The Viennese of the time had little inclination to consider the possibilities of change, and the over-ripe era in which Wittgenstein grew up did not really end until Austria-Hungary’s defeat, in World War I, and subsequent dismantling. But the family in which Wittgenstein grew up apparently felt that European culture had already come to an end in the 1840’s. And Wittgenstein himself felt he belonged to an era that had vanished with the death of the composer Robert Schumann (1810-1856).2 Somewhere in the middle of the Nineteenth Century there was an important change into the contemporary era, of which Wittgenstein did not feel a part. Wittgenstein’s understanding of history, and his consequent self-understanding in relation to his times, was deeply influenced by Oswald Spengler, who in 1918 published The Decline of the West [Der Untergang des Abenlandes]. This book, expanded to a second volume in 1922, and revised in 1923, became a best-seller in post-war Europe. Wittgenstein made numerous references to it in 1930-1931, and acknowledged Spengler as one of his ten noteworthy influences.3 According to Spengler, cultures grow, flower, and deteriorate naturally, according to their own internal form, much as a human being does.
    [Show full text]
  • No Nonsense Grammar Conference Thursday 2Nd February 2017 | Crosby Lakeside Adventure Centre, L22 1RR | 9:30 - 15:30
    No Nonsense Grammar Conference Thursday 2nd February 2017 | Crosby Lakeside Adventure Centre, L22 1RR | 9:30 - 15:30 Conference Overview Key Reasons to Attend Without doubt, the expectations of grammar knowledge Hear from nationally renowned primary literacy and understanding in the National Curriculum are experts presenting schools with enormous challenges. Secure, Expand your subject knowledge about a key confident teacher subject knowledge needs to underpin aspect of the curriculum high expectations of children’s understanding resulting in: Learn how to get the best out of No Nonsense “Grammar teaching that draws attention to the linguistic Grammar possibilities available to children, and has at its heart the creative shaping of text.” Reflect on current practice Myhill et al (2016) Grammar for Creative Teachers Develop ideas for the classroom and for developing grammar in school Hear nationally renowned expert Debra Myhill outline how grammar is a key tool in exploring how texts work, both the texts children read and the texts they write. Followed Who should attend? by two sessions with Rebecca Cosgrave, co-author of No Nonsense Grammar. Rebecca will highlight the importance Primary Teachers and Literacy Coordinators of teachers’ grammatical subject knowledge and detail how No Nonsense Grammar can support outstanding teaching and learning. In association with: www.babcock-education.co.uk/ldp © Babcock International Group PLC Our Speakers About No Nonsense Grammar Debra Myhill, Pro-Vice-Chancellor: College of Social Sciences and International Studies Debra Myhill’s interests are in the teaching and research of language and literacy. Debra is Director of the Centre for Research in Writing and her commitment is to the bringing together of teaching, teacher education and research so that children and young people’s experience of learning to be literate enables them to be confident, articulate citizens of the future, able to use language and literature for personal fulfilment and economic well-being.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein on the Nature of British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Philosophy J Wittgenstein and His Times
    @Basil Blackwdl Publisher Limitcd 1982 Contents Fiesr published 1982 Basil BlackwelJ Publisher Limited 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 IJF, England All rights rcserved. No part ofthis publicarion may bc reproduccd, stored in a retricval system, or trammitted. in an y form or hy any means. clcctronic, mcchanicaJ, photocopying. recording or otherwisc. withollt the prior permission of Basil Blackwell Publisher Limited. Editor's Preface v Anthony Kenny Wittgenstein on the Nature of British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Philosophy J Wittgenstein and his times. Brian McGuinness Freud and Wittgenstein 27 I. Wittgenstein, Ludwig I. McGuinness, Brian J. C. NYlri Wittgenstein's Later Work in '92 B)376.W)64 reiation co Conservatism 44 ISBN 0-63'-11161-1 Rush Rhees Wittgenstein on Language and Ritual 69 G. H von Wright Wittgenstein in relation to his Times 108 Index 121 Printe<! in Great Britain at Thc Blackwell Press Limitcd, Guildford, Landon, Oxford, Worcester. LATER WORK IN RELATION 1'0 CONSERVATISM 45 since Wittgenstein 's position in respect to the body ofconserva­ Wittgenstein 's Later Work in relation tive literature cannot be satisfactorily dctcrmined in the absence to Conservatism * ofa thorough analysis ofhis unpublished manuscripts. I Still, the interpretation here presented, cven ifmerely an approximation, C. Nyiri seems to me to constitute a necessary step towards a more J. complere pieture of Wittgenstcin's philosophy. Wittgenstein's later philosophy emerged at a time when conservatism - in tbe form of neo-conservatism - was one of the dominant spiritual currents in Germany and Austria; and Wittgenstein received decisive impulses both from authors who deeply influenced this The well-kno"vn fact that in Wittgenstein's later philosophy current and trom representatives ofthe I1ew conservatism itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositions, Functions, and Analysis This Page Intentionally Left Blank Propositions, Functions, and Analysis Selected Essays on Russell’S Philosophy
    Propositions, Functions, and Analysis This page intentionally left blank Propositions, Functions, and Analysis Selected Essays on Russell’s Philosophy PETER HYLTON CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Peter Hylton 2005 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems (P) Ltd., Chennai, India Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by Biddles Ltd., King’s Lynn, Norfolk ISBN 0–19–928635–3 978–0–19–928635–5 13579108642 To the memory of Burton S.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason, Causation and Compatibility with the Phenomena
    Reason, causation and compatibility with the phenomena Basil Evangelidis Series in Philosophy Copyright © 2020 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States Series in Philosophy Library of Congress Control Number: 2019942259 ISBN: 978-1-62273-755-0 Cover design by Vernon Press. Cover image by Garik Barseghyan from Pixabay. Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it. Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been inadvertently overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition. Table of contents Abbreviations vii Preface ix Introduction xi Chapter 1 Causation, determinism and the universe 1 1. Natural principles and the rise of free-will 1 1.1. “The most exact of the sciences” 2 1.2.
    [Show full text]