<<

Quednow, B B (2010). Ethics of neuroenhancement: a phantom debate. [Book review of: Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Davinia Talbot, Uwe Opolka and Johann S Ach (eds.), Neuro-Enhancement. Ethik vor neuen Herausforderungen, Paderborn: mentis, 2009]. BioSocieties, 5(1):153-156. Postprint available at: http://www.zora.uzh.ch

University of Zurich Posted at the Zurich Open Repository and Archive, University of Zurich. Zurich Open Repository and Archive http://www.zora.uzh.ch

Originally published at: BioSocieties 2010, 5(1):153-156. Winterthurerstr. 190 CH-8057 Zurich http://www.zora.uzh.ch

Year: 2010

Ethics of neuroenhancement: a phantom debate. [Book review of: Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Davinia Talbot, Uwe Opolka and Johann S Ach (eds.), Neuro-Enhancement. Ethik vor neuen Herausforderungen, Paderborn: mentis, 2009]

Quednow, B B

Quednow, B B (2010). Ethics of neuroenhancement: a phantom debate. [Book review of: Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Davinia Talbot, Uwe Opolka and Johann S Ach (eds.), Neuro-Enhancement. Ethik vor neuen Herausforderungen, Paderborn: mentis, 2009]. BioSocieties, 5(1):153-156. Postprint available at: http://www.zora.uzh.ch

Posted at the Zurich Open Repository and Archive, University of Zurich. http://www.zora.uzh.ch

Originally published at: BioSocieties 2010, 5(1):153-156. Review of Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Davinia Talbot, Uwe Opolka, and Johann S. Ach (eds.), Neuro-Enhancement. Ethik vor neuen Herausforderungen, Paderborn: mentis, 2009.

Ethics of neuroenhancement: a phantom debate

Boris B. Quednow

University Hospital of Psychiatry, Division of Experimental and Clinical Pharmacopsychology, Lenggstr. 31, CH-8032 Zürich, Switzerland E-mail: [email protected]

With their book Neuro-Enhancement: Ethik vor neuen Herausforderungen, the editors Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Davinia Talbot, Uwe Opolka, and Johann S. Ach have delivered a collection of articles providing a cross-section of the ongoing debate over cognitive and mood enhancement in Germany. As a pharmacopsychologist working on the neurochemistry of cognition and emotion I have followed this debate for several years now and I have felt uneasy about it from the start. What follows might rather be a perspectival response to the presented volume than a classical book review. But considering the current proliferation of publications on the ethics of neuroenhancement it seems about time to call into question some of the pharmacological and epidemiological presumptions on which this emergent body of literature – including the book at hand – is based. The volume Neuro-Enhancement was developed from papers presented at a one-week conference organized by the editors at the Hanse-Wissenschaftskolleg in Delmenhorst, Germany in 2005. All contributors are established experts in the field of medical ethics, but they come from different disciplines such as philosophy, political science, and medicine. The chapters are divided into four thematic sections. The first provides a conceptual framework distinguishing neuroenhancement of healthy subjects from the medical treatment of patients. Here, Saskia Nagel and Achim Stephan, for example, draw a normative map of conceivable enhancement options. And Joel Anderson discusses whether the use of imaginable future neuroprotheses providing music lovers with super hearing would be ethically legitimate. The second section illustrates the problems and chances of cognitive enhancement in particular. For instance, Sabine Müller poses the question whether, from idealist and utilitarian perspectives respectively, the enhancement of intelligence would be morally obligatory – if it

1 became possible. The third section reviews issues of emotional enhancement addressing the challenge posed by drugs such as Prozac to authenticity. And the final section discusses the ethical implications of neuroenhancement for society at large. As most of the preceding contributions, Bernward Gesang’s consideration of the social risks and benefits of different kinds of enhancement or Petra Schaper-Rinkel’s discussion of the political consequences of thinkable further developments of neuroimplants connecting people in new ways presuppose that, as the editors put it, neuroenhancement “will actually turn out to be efficient, agreeable and therefore, from an individual perspective, attractive.” From a pharmacological point of view, however, this presupposition is questionable. In my discussion, I will focus on what the book has to say about the enhancement of cognitive performance (although similar critiques could be developed with respect to emotional enhancement, biological and technical brain implants, and genetic manipulations). I will not engage with the ethical, social, and political consequences of enhancement discussed by the authors (as one could usually expect from a book review) as I believe that already their pharmacological and epidemiological premises are unrealistic. Almost all contributions to the volume Neuro-Enhancement are based on the assumption that, in the near future, we will have access to compounds that are not only effective cognitive enhancers, but also safe and well-tolerated and therefore suitable to be taken by everybody (see, for example, the essays of Schaper-Rinkel and Synofzik). This, however, is not likely to happen in the foreseeable future. It seems that many medical ethicists have been led astray by exaggerated promises of neuroscientists who are either collaborators of the pharmaceutical industry or forced to overstate their own results to get increasingly competitive research funding. As a matter of fact, we are currently even unable to fully restore disturbed intellectual functioning in psychiatric or neurological diseases and we still do not know how to achieve this goal in the future. Let me briefly sum up where we currently stand with respect to cognitive enhancement. In the discussed book, two drugs are repeatedly referred to as supposedly effective cognitive enhancers: (Ritalin©, Concerta©), and (Provigil ©, Vigil©). Together with amphetamine and the illegal drug cocaine, these substances share some neurochemical mechanisms and psychotropic effects which justify calling all of them . These drugs are affecting the dopamine and noradrenaline systems and their main effects are an increase of vigilance, arousal, and motivation. But, as far as we currently know, they have no direct effect on specific cognitive domains such as memory or (de Jongh et al., 2008). Thus, stimulants are rather second-

2 order cognitive enhancers. For the sake of clarity, they would better be called vigilance or motivation enhancers. Interestingly, for all of these substances it has been shown that they increase cognitive performance only in subjects with low baseline capacities whereas in subjects with higher baseline performance often deteriorates (Mattay et al., 2000; Mattay et al., 2003; Mehta et al., 2000; Muller et al., 2004; Randall et al., 2005). This points to a principle brain mechanism that can be found in several neuronal systems and circuits: the inverse U-function. According to this principle, enhancement is only possible as long as we do not have an optimal level of arousal, vigilance, or neurotransmitter concentration (Arnsten & Li, 2005; Kahneman, 1973; Mattay et al., 2003). Hence, an already optimally tuned brain can hardly be enhanced. Given that usually our brains already perform to the best of their ability and that the homeostasis of this organ is very sensitive, general enhancement for everyone seems strictly limited. Against this background, it is not surprising that stimulants – and here in particular modafinil – are effective to counter cognitive decline caused by . It was shown that caffeine – a well-known and effective vigilance enhancer with tolerable side effects – was about as effective as modafinil to antagonize sleep deprivation- induced impairments, for example, of reaction time (Killgore et al., 2008; Wesensten et al., 2002). However, cognitive effects in well-rested healthy subjects are small and hard to detect (for review see Kumar, 2008). Moreover, several studies have shown that an increased performance in one cognitive domain often goes along with a decrease in performance in another domain. For example, we could enhance our working memory but simultaneously decrease our long-term memory or vice versa but we will never be able enhance both simultaneously (de Jongh et al., 2008). The same is true regarding focusing vs. shifting attention and several other cognitive functions. These phenomena are further complicated by the fact that effects vary between individuals (a drug may enhance domain X and impair domain Y in individual A, whereas in subject B domain X is impaired and domain Y is enhanced) (Clatworthy et al., 2009). Because of the vast complexity of the brain, it seems likely that we will not be able to overcome trade-offs between enhancement and simultaneous impairment by drugs. Apart from the collateral adverse effects on cognitive functions, the available substances have many psychiatric and somatic side effects which make them not well suited for use in healthy humans only for the purpose of enhancing vigilance or motivation. For example, all stimulants bear a risk of addiction, which can be explained by their specific mechanism of action (Berridge, 2007). Thus, I trust in the old pharmacological principle that there is no effect without a side effect, which is essentially true for all drugs acting on the brain. Our

3 brain is of such complexity and its neurotransmitter systems are so strongly interlaced that turning a small screw in one system generates unpredictable effects in all other systems with corresponding consequences for behavior. has just scratched the surface of a still undiscovered universe. As we have seen there is no genuine cognitive enhancer available to date. There are several current attempts to develop more specifically acting compounds such as memory enhancers. However, none of the drugs tested so far have shown replicable and significant effects in healthy human volunteers (de Jongh et al., 2008; Lanni et al., 2008). Thus, we are still waiting for an effective drug that enhances cognition at least in patients suffering from mental dysfunctions. But it seems dubitable whether we will ever see the arrival of drugs significantly improving cognition in healthy subjects as presupposed in many contributions to Neuro-Enhancement. Certainly not in the near future. However, the topicality of the book is not only based on such futurology, but also on an – equally questionable – diagnosis of the present. In their introduction, Schöne-Seifert and Talbot argue that already available cognitive enhancers such as methylphenidate and modafinil are increasingly prescribed beyond their actual indications. They convey a sense of urgency: “More and more students, professors, and managers are already taking drugs for neuroenhancement purposes.“ Schaper-Rinkel believes that a market for neuroenhancement is developing and that its commercial significance will strongly increase in the near future (p. 299). There is nothing new about such recreational and off-label use of stimulants. From the 1940s to the 1960s, there was an epidemic abuse of amphetamines in countries like the USA, Great Britain, or Sweden with millions of users. In 1969, shortly before the distribution of amphetamines was legally restricted, the estimated prevalence of misuse in the US was comparable to 2002 (Rasmussen, 2008). Although, at the time, most amphetamines were sold as mild antidepressants they were also advertised for the enhancement of “mental alertness” (Rasmussen, 2008). Thus, the supposed urgency of the situation is not due to the fact that we are facing an unprecedented epidemic. In fact, the extent of cognitive enhancer abuse today has often been exaggerated (see the essay of Talbot, p. 325). A frequently cited study reported that up to 13% of high school students and up to 20% of college students in the US tried methylphenidate (Kapner, 2003). However, a more recent meta-analysis has shown that the one-year prevalence of experiences with stimulant cognitive enhancers is only 4% while the lifetime prevalence is 7% (Sussman et al., 2006). Moreover, the misuse was most prevalent among white male college students

4 struggling with their grades and living in larger urban areas (McCabe et al., 2005). These youth also tend to use illegal drugs such as , alcohol, MDMA, and cocaine (Sussman et al., 2006). Interestingly, more than 40% of the students reported that they use methylphenidate and amphetamine not only for performance enhancement but also to improve their mood, to get “high”, or for going clubbing (Sussman et al., 2006; Teter et al., 2005). The misuse of prescription stimulants is highest between 19 and 24 years and then decreases with increasing age (Johnston et al., 2005). And, finally, the lifetime prevalence of methylphenidate use in US college students seems to be decreasing rather than increasing, dropping from 5.7% in 2002 to 3.9% in 2006 (Kapner, 2008). In Germany, in a recent survey of a big insurance program, less than 1% of the employees reported that they had used stimulants at least once in their lives against tiredness and sleepiness (0.93%) or for better concentration (0.63%) (DAK, 2009). These numbers show that the diagnosed epidemic of cognitive enhancer abuse is inexistent. A further result of several surveys was that women prefer the use of antidepressants or sedative drugs whereas men are more inclined toward the use of stimulants to enhance their work performance (e.g., DAK, 2009). This phenomenon points to the fact that not everyone is equally interested in enhancement of his or her intellectual performance. Apart from gender differences, I suppose that personality exerts a strong effect on the felt need to enhance cognitive performance. I would predict that narcissistic and ambitious personalities are especially prone to the use of cognitive enhancers. Unfortunately, to my knowledge, there is no study that has investigated the influence of personality on the preference of cognitive enhancers. Thus, there is no increasing or epidemic use of cognitive enhancers to date, and it is unlikely that such a trend will develop given that seemingly only a minority of the population is interested in regular use. Moreover, as stated above, a large number of potential users will experience somatic side effects or negative effects on cognition that will result in discontinuation of use. If the epidemiological account that I am providing is correct, then the question is whether we are actually facing a problematic serious enough to warrant the large- scale debate over neuroenhancement to which the discussed volume contributes. In summary, the book Neuro-Enhancement provides a comprehensive compilation of articles giving a good overview of the current debate over the ethics of cognitive enhancement. Let me emphasize that I do not take issue with the philosophical quality of the contributions. But, from my perspective as a neuroscientist, the debate which is so well represented by the book is based on dubious assumptions. The participants of this discussion

5 often claim that their speculative approach provides us with the unique opportunity to discuss the ethical consequences of new technologies before they are fully developed. At least this one time, ethics could be ahead of technology. However, do we really need a debate on a technology that will probably never materialize?

Boris B. Quednow is assistant professor of Experimental and Clinical Pharmacopsychology at the University Hospital of Psychiatry in Zurich. His main research interests are the neurotoxicology of illegal drug use as well as the neurochemistry of cognition and disturbed information processing in psychiatric diseases.

References Arnsten, A. F., & Li, B. M. (2005). Neurobiology of executive functions: catecholamine influences on prefrontal cortical functions. Biol Psychiatry, 57(11), 1377-1384. Berridge, K. C. (2007). The debate over dopamine's role in reward: the case for incentive salience. Psychopharmacology (Berl), 191(3), 391-431. Clatworthy, P. L., Lewis, S. J., Brichard, L., Hong, Y. T., Izquierdo, D., Clark, L., et al. (2009). Dopamine release in dissociable striatal subregions predicts the different effects of oral methylphenidate on reversal learning and spatial working memory. J Neurosci, 29(15), 4690-4696. DAK. (2009). Gesundheitsreport 2009: Analyse der Arbeitsunfähigkeitsdaten. Schwerpunktthema Doping am Arbeitsplatz. Hamburg: DAK Forschung. de Jongh, R., Bolt, I., Schermer, M., & Olivier, B. (2008). Botox for the brain: enhancement of cognition, mood and pro-social behavior and blunting of unwanted memories. Neurosci Biobehav Rev, 32(4), 760-776. Johnston, L. D., O'Malley, P. M., Bachman, J. G., & Schulenberg, J. E. (2005). Monitoring the Future national survey results on drug use, 1975-2004. Volume I and II: Secondary school students and College students and adults ages 19-45. Bethesda, MD: National Institute on Drug Abuse (NIH Publication Nos. 05-5727 and 05-5728). Kahneman, D. (1973). Attention and effort. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Kapner, D. A. (2003). Recreational use of ritalin on college campuses. Newton, Massachusetts: The Higher Education Center for Alcohol and Other Drug Prevention. Kapner, D. A. (2008). Recreational use of ritalin on college campuses. Newton, Massachusetts: The Higher Education Center for Alcohol and Other Drug Prevention. Killgore, W. D., Rupp, T. L., Grugle, N. L., Reichardt, R. M., Lipizzi, E. L., & Balkin, T. J. (2008). Effects of dextroamphetamine, caffeine and modafinil on psychomotor vigilance test performance after 44 h of continuous wakefulness. J Sleep Res, 17(3), 309-321. Kumar, R. (2008). Approved and investigational uses of modafinil : an evidence-based review. Drugs, 68(13), 1803-1839. Lanni, C., Lenzken, S. C., Pascale, A., Del Vecchio, I., Racchi, M., Pistoia, F., et al. (2008). Cognition enhancers between treating and doping the mind. Pharmacol Res, 57(3), 196-213. Mattay, V. S., Callicott, J. H., Bertolino, A., Heaton, I., Frank, J. A., Coppola, R., et al. (2000). Effects of dextroamphetamine on cognitive performance and cortical activation. Neuroimage, 12(3), 268-275. Mattay, V. S., Goldberg, T. E., Fera, F., Hariri, A. R., Tessitore, A., Egan, M. F., et al. (2003). Catechol O- methyltransferase val158-met genotype and individual variation in the brain response to amphetamine. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A, 100(10), 6186-6191. McCabe, S. E., Knight, J. R., Teter, C. J., & Wechsler, H. (2005). Non-medical use of prescription stimulants among US college students: prevalence and correlates from a national survey. Addiction, 100(1), 96- 106. 6 Mehta, M. A., Owen, A. M., Sahakian, B. J., Mavaddat, N., Pickard, J. D., & Robbins, T. W. (2000). Methylphenidate enhances working memory by modulating discrete frontal and parietal lobe regions in the human brain. J Neurosci, 20(6), RC65. Muller, U., Steffenhagen, N., Regenthal, R., & Bublak, P. (2004). Effects of modafinil on working memory processes in humans. Psychopharmacology (Berl), 177(1-2), 161-169. Randall, D. C., Shneerson, J. M., & File, S. E. (2005). Cognitive effects of modafinil in student volunteers may depend on IQ. Pharmacol Biochem Behav, 82(1), 133-139. Rasmussen, N. (2008). America's first amphetamine epidemic 1929-1971: a quantitative and qualitative retrospective with implications for the present. Am J Public Health, 98(6), 974-985. Sussman, S., Pentz, M. A., Spruijt-Metz, D., & Miller, T. (2006). Misuse of "study drugs:" prevalence, consequences, and implications for policy. Subst Abuse Treat Prev Policy, 1, 15. Teter, C. J., McCabe, S. E., Cranford, J. A., Boyd, C. J., & Guthrie, S. K. (2005). Prevalence and motives for illicit use of prescription stimulants in an undergraduate student sample. J Am Coll Health, 53(6), 253- 262. Wesensten, N. J., Belenky, G., Kautz, M. A., Thorne, D. R., Reichardt, R. M., & Balkin, T. J. (2002). Maintaining alertness and performance during sleep deprivation: modafinil versus caffeine. Psychopharmacology (Berl), 159(3), 238-247.

7