An Integrated Approach to Reference and Presupposition Resolution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Integrated Approach to Reference and Presupposition Resolution , O @ O O An Integrated Approach to Reference and Presupposition O Resolution O Robert T. Kasper, Paul C. Davis~ and Craige Roberts O Department of Linguistics @ Ohio State University 222 Oxley Hall O 1712 Neil Avenue O Columbus, OH 43210" O e-mail: (kasper~ pcdavis, croberts}@ling.ohio-state.edu O RecoL,nlzing the structure of the discourse will there- O Abstract fore play a crucial role in narrowing the search O We describe an approach to resolving definite de- for referents and other presupposed information. scriptious and pronominal anaphora as subcases of We will illustrate our approach with four example O a general strategy for presupposition satisfaction. human-computer dialogues, shown below. SYS in- O Generally, a presupposition is satisfied in a context dicates the utterances spoken by the computer sys- if the context contains a specific type of information tem. @ and is organized in such a way that this information Example I illustrates a case of pronominal can be retrieved by the interlocutors. The model anaphora resolution (it in (8)), in which recowniT.ing O of discourse context we develop assumes that dis- the hierarchical structure of the discourse is crucial O course structure is organized around a stack of ques- for identifying the antecedent, which was introduced tions under discussion, which plays a crucial role in many utterances earlier. The overall topic of the O narrowing the search for referents and other presup- conversation is the question of where the user @ posed information. The algerithmA for maintaining can find a hotel for June 15th in New York, and the discourse structures and retrieving presupposed th|8 snper-question both facilitates and constrains O information are presented and illustrated by several the intexpretafion of fl in (8). This example is example dialogues in which human users interact similar to the well-known examples of long-distance O with an agent tomake hotel reservatious. anaphora in task-oriented dialogues described by O Grosz (1981). Our approach is consistent with pre- I Introduction vious research that uses the intentional structure of O "Any theory of referring expressions must take into discourse to determine a set of potential antecedents O account the discourse context in which they ot~ur. for pronominal anaphora. The following examples Indeed, previous research has shown that the hier- will illustrate how a broader range of reference O archical organization of discourse is fundamentally and presuppositional constructions may also be O related to the rderence resolution process. In this addressed by using the discourse structure to guide paper, we show how a highly structured discourse the search for relevant information. @ model, in conjunction with a treatment of referring expressions as presuppmitional, enables us to de- Example L O velop a common strategy for z~olving a number of 1) USER: rm lookln~ for a hotel for June lSth in O reference resolution problems, such as pronominal New York. anaphora and definite descriptions. We also out- 2) SYS: What part of the city would you prefer? O line how this approach extends to a larger group of 3) USEI~ Manhattan, near Central Park. O phenomena which we take to be presuppositional,. 4) SYS: How many nights? including domain restriction, ellipsis, and lexically 5) USF~ Just 1. O and syntactically triggered presuppositions. All of 6) SYS: Will anyone be traveling with you? these constructions are presuppositional in a broad 7) USEI~ No. O sense, in that their use assumes that certain infor- 8) USEP~ Oh, I want it to have a swimming pool O marion can be retrieved from the discourse context. too. O O " Paul C. Davis is the recipient et~ a Motorola Partnemhipe O in Research Grant. Example II shows a definite description, the structure Of discourse and the related background hotel in (7), whose referent can only be uniquely literature. In section 3, we present algorithms which determined with respect to the indefinite hotel de- we have developed in a partially completed imple- scription ( a hotel close to Madison Square Garden) mentation of a natural language dialogue system in the question under discussion (1): where users interact with an automated hotel reser- vation booking system. In section 4, we discuss the Example II. use of the algorithms and discourse structures to 1) USER: I want to make a reservation at a hotel resolve the reference and presupposition problems close to Madison Square Garden. shown in the above examples. In the final section, @ 2) SYS: What dates will the reservation be for? we highlight the contributions of our approach and 3) USER: March 3rd and 4th. discuss future plans related to this research. 0 4) SYS: Wouldyou like a single room? 0 5) USER: Yes. 2 Background: Discourse Structure 6) USER: Also, I'll need a conference room on We assume the general theoretical framework of 0 the 4th. Roberts (1996), where discourse is formally charac- O 7) USER: I'd prefer it if the hotel had one. terized as a game of intentional inquiry. As in Grosz & Sidner (1986), discourse is organized by the in- 0 Example HI involves a contextually determined terlocutors' goals and intentions and the plans, or O domain restriction, with a quantificationai deter- strategies, which conversational participants develop miner every, innstrating that domain restriction to achieve them. Following Stalnaker (1979), the pri- 0 must be handled in a ~imilar way for a broader mary goal of the language game is communal inquiry, class of expressions than those which are normally i.e., interlocutors attempting to share information 0 regarded as rderring expr_~-_qjons or presupposition about their world, with the repository of that shared 0 triggers. information characterized as the interlocutors' com- Example HI." mon groun~ CG. The set of acceptable moves in the 0 I) USEI~ Does the Holiday Inn have any vacan- game are defined by the (conventional and conver- cies for sational) rules of the game, and are classified on the 0 a) Tuesday, 12/4- Friday 12/7? basis of their relatio_n~blp to the goals. Ignoring im- @ b) Thursday, 12/6 - Saturday 12/87 peratives, there are two main types of moves (see 2) SYS: Yes, several. also Carlson 1983): questions and assertions. If a 0 3) USER: Do they have a breakfast buffet question is accepted by the interlocutors, this com- @ every mor~;=g? mits them to a common dis(x)ur~ goal, l~lding a sat- 4) SYS: isfactory (asserted) answer; like the commitment to 0 a) Yes, Monday through Friday. a goal in Planning Theory, thiA strong commitment @ b) No. There's a breakfast buffet Monday persists until the goal is satJ'~ed or else shown to be through unsatisfi~le. The accepted question becomes the 0 Friday, but none on Saturday. immediate topic of discussion, the quest/on under discussion. An assertion is a move which proposes 0 Finally, in example IV we give a glimpse into an addition of information to the CG. 0 our larger research program, where an elliptical Roberts defines the structure of a discourse at @ question (3) must be resolved with respect to the a given point, its Information Structure, as a tu- question under discussion, in addition to estab- pie which includes (among other things) the ordered 0 lishing the reference of the deflm'te description the set of moves in the discourse (M), CG, and the set Marrio~ where the context might contain more of the questions currently under discussion at that 0 than one hotel with that name~ point (QUD). The QUD is ordered by order of ute • terance and is updated in a stack-!i!~ f~b!on, I with 0 E~-mple IV. questions popped when they are answered (or de- 0 I) USER: Which hotels near the airport have f.-mined to be practically unanswerable). The or- vacancies? dered set of questions under disc~-_~f~on corresponds O 2) SYS: The Holiday Inn and Sheraton have to the hierarchical intentional structure of the dis- 0 vacancies. course. The QUD in this structure constitutes the 3) USER: How about the Marriott7 set of d/sco,rse goa/s of the interlocutors; the dis. 0 4) SYS: No, the airport Marriott doesn't have any course goals are only a subset of the set of common vacancies. .goals of the interlocutors, their domain goals, and 0 1However, all elements of the QUD list are accessibledur. 0 The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. ing the interpretation of an utterance. Only the top element In section 2 we discuss our assumptions about the is wr/table, but any entry is readable. 0 0 2 0 0 0 the discourse goals ar e subordinate to, and subserve (2) Weak Familiarity: A discourse referent i is the domain goals. Hence, the requirement that in- weakly familiar in a context C (i E Domain(C) terlocutors stick to the question under discussion is and C encodes the information that i has prop- just an instance of the more general commitment erties Pi .... , Pk) iff the Common Ground of C to plans; and in turn, in a fully integrated theory entails the existence of an entity with properties we would expect that domain goals and plans would P~, . , Pk. influence interpretation as directly as the discourse goals represented by the questions under discussion. Informational uniqueness only requires that the Any move in a discourse game is interpreted with discourse referent which satisfies the defmite's famil- respect to the Information Structure of the discourse iarity presupposition be unique among the discourse at that point. There are two main aspects to the referents in the context in satisfying the definite's interpretation of any given move: its presupposed descriptive content.
Recommended publications
  • The Etienne Gilson Series 21
    The Etienne Gilson Series 21 Remapping Scholasticism by MARCIA L. COLISH 3 March 2000 Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies This lecture and its publication was made possible through the generous bequest of the late Charles J. Sullivan (1914-1999) Note: the author may be contacted at: Department of History Oberlin College Oberlin OH USA 44074 ISSN 0-708-319X ISBN 0-88844-721-3 © 2000 by Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies 59 Queen’s Park Crescent East Toronto, Ontario, Canada M5S 2C4 Printed in Canada nce upon a time there were two competing story-lines for medieval intellectual history, each writing a major role for scholasticism into its script. Although these story-lines were O created independently and reflected different concerns, they sometimes overlapped and gave each other aid and comfort. Both exerted considerable influence on the way historians of medieval speculative thought conceptualized their subject in the first half of the twentieth cen- tury. Both versions of the map drawn by these two sets of cartographers illustrated what Wallace K. Ferguson later described as “the revolt of the medievalists.”1 One was confined largely to the academy and appealed to a wide variety of medievalists, while the other had a somewhat narrower draw and reflected political and confessional, as well as academic, concerns. The first was the anti-Burckhardtian effort to push Renaissance humanism, understood as combining a knowledge and love of the classics with “the discovery of the world and of man,” back into the Middle Ages. The second was inspired by the neo-Thomist revival launched by Pope Leo XIII, and was inhabited almost exclusively by Roman Catholic scholars.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/kt2779p48t No online items Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Processed by David MacGill; machine-readable finding aid created by Caroline Cubé © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Finding Aid for the Gottfried 503 1 Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Finding Aid for the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Manuscripts Division Los Angeles, CA Processed by: David MacGill, November 1992 Encoded by: Caroline Cubé Online finding aid edited by: Josh Fiala, October 2003 © 2003 The Regents of the University of California. All rights reserved. Descriptive Summary Title: Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Papers, Date (inclusive): 1646-1716 Collection number: 503 Creator: Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von, 1646-1716 Extent: 6 oversize boxes Repository: University of California, Los Angeles. Library. Dept. of Special Collections. Los Angeles, California 90095-1575 Abstract: Leibniz (1646-1716) was a philosopher, mathematician, and political advisor. He invented differential and integral calculus. His major writings include New physical hypothesis (1671), Discourse on metaphysics (1686), On the ultimate origin of things (1697), and On nature itself (1698). The collection consists of 35 reels of positive microfilm of more than 100,000 handwritten pages of manuscripts and letters. Physical location: Stored off-site at SRLF. Advance notice is required for access to the collection. Please contact the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections Reference Desk for paging information. Language: English. Restrictions on Use and Reproduction Property rights to the physical object belong to the UCLA Library, Department of Special Collections.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition Failure and Intended Pronominal Reference: Person Is Not So Different from Gender After All* Isabelle Charnavel Harvard University
    Presupposition failure and intended pronominal reference: Person is not so different from gender after all* Isabelle Charnavel Harvard University Abstract This paper aims to show that (one of) the main argument(s) against the presuppositional account of person is not compelling if one makes appropriate assumptions about how the context fixes the assignment. It has been argued that unlike gender features, person features of free pronouns cannot yield presupposition failure (but only falsity) when they are not verified by the referent. The argument is however flawed because the way the referent is assigned is not made clear. If it is assumed to be the individual that the audience can recognize as the referent intended by the speaker, the argument is reversed. Keywords Person, gender, presupposition, assignment, reference, indexicals 1 Introduction Since Cooper (1983), gender features on pronouns are standardly analyzed as presuppositions (Heim and Kratzer 1998, Sauerland 2003, Heim 2008, Percus 2011, i.a.). Cooper’s analysis of gender features has not only been extended to number, but also to person features (Heim and Kratzer 1998, Schlenker 1999, 2003, Sauerland 2008, Heim 2008, i.a.), thus replacing the more traditional indexical analysis of first and second person pronouns (Kaplan 1977 and descendants of it). All pronouns are thereby interpreted as variables, and all phi-features are assigned uniform interpretive functions, that is, they introduce presuppositions that restrict of the value of the variables. However, empirical arguments have recently been provided that cast doubt on the presuppositional nature of person features (Stokke 2010, Sudo 2012, i.a.). In particular, it has been claimed that when the person information is not verified by the referent, the use of a first/second person pronoun does not give rise to a feeling of presupposition failure, as is the case when the gender information does not match the referent’s gender: a person mismatch, unlike a gender mismatch, yields a plain judgment of falsity.
    [Show full text]
  • Bearers of Truth and the Unsaid
    1 Bearers of Truth and the Unsaid Stephen Barker (University of Nottingham) Draft (Forthcoming in Making Semantics Pragmatic (ed) K. Turner. (CUP). The standard view about the bearers of truth–the entities that are the ultimate objects of predication of truth or falsity–is that they are propositions or sentences semantically correlated with propositions. Propositions are meant to be the contents of assertions, objects of thought or judgement, and so are ontologically distinct from assertions or acts of thought or judgement. So understood propositions are meant to be things like possible states of affairs or sets of possible worlds–entities that are clearly not acts of judgement. Let us say that a sentence S encodes a proposition «P» when linguistic rules (plus context) correlate «P» with S in a manner that does not depend upon whether S is asserted or appears embedded in a logical compound. The orthodox conception of truth-bearers then can be expressed in two forms: TB1 : The primary truth-bearers are propositions. TB2 : The primary truth-bearers are sentences that encode a proposition «P». I use the term primary truth-bearers , since orthodoxy allows that assertions or judgements, etc, can be truth-bearers, it is just that they are derivatively so; they being truth-apt depends on other things being truth-apt. Some orthodox theorists prefer TB1 –Stalnaker (1972)– some prefer TB2 –Richard (1990). We need not concern ourselves with the reasons for their preferences here. Rather, our concern shall be this: why accept orthodoxy at all in either form: TB1 or TB2 ? There is without doubt a strong general reason to accept the propositional view.
    [Show full text]
  • Role and Reference Grammar
    Work Papers of the Summer Institute of Linguistics, University of North Dakota Session Volume 37 Article 5 1993 Role and reference grammar Robert D. Van Valin Jr. Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.und.edu/sil-work-papers Part of the Linguistics Commons Recommended Citation Van Valin, Robert D. Jr. (1993) "Role and reference grammar," Work Papers of the Summer Institute of Linguistics, University of North Dakota Session: Vol. 37 , Article 5. DOI: 10.31356/silwp.vol37.05 Available at: https://commons.und.edu/sil-work-papers/vol37/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by UND Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Work Papers of the Summer Institute of Linguistics, University of North Dakota Session by an authorized editor of UND Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ROLE AND REFERENCE GRAMMAR Robert D. Van Valin, Jr. State University of New York at Buffalo 1 Introduction 2 Historical background 3 Central concepts of the theory 3. I Clause structure 3.2 Semantic structure 3 .3 FOCUS structure 3. 4 Grammatical relations and linking 4 Some implications of RRG 1 Introduction* Role and Reference Grammar [RRG] (Van Valin 1993a) may be termed a "structural-functionalist theory of grammar"; this locates it on a range of perspectives from extreme formalist at one end to radical functionalist at the other. RRG falls between these two extremes, differing markedly from each. In contrast to the extreme formalist view, RRG views language as a system of communicative social action, and consequently, analyzing the communicative functions of morphosyntactic structures has a vital role in grammatical description and theory from this perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • The Logic of Sense and Reference
    The Logic of Sense and Reference Reinhard Muskens Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS) ESSLLI 2009, Day 1 Reinhard Muskens (TiLPS) The Logic of Sense and Reference ESSLLI 2009, Day 1 1 / 37 The Logic of Sense and Reference In this course we look at the problem of the individuation of meaning. Many semantic theories do not individuate meanings finely enough and as a consequence make wrong predictions. We will discuss strategies to arrive at fine-grained theories of meaning. They will be illustrated mainly (though not exclusively) on the basis of my work. Strategies that can be implemented in standard higher order logic will be investigated, but generalisations of that logic that help deal with the problem will be considered too. Today I'll focus on explaining the problem itself and will mention some general strategies to deal with it. One of these (that of Thomason 1980) will be worked out in slightly more detail. Reinhard Muskens (TiLPS) The Logic of Sense and Reference ESSLLI 2009, Day 1 2 / 37 But we can form theories of meaning. Lewis (1972): In order to say what a meaning is, we may first ask what a meaning does, and then find something that does that. In today's talk I want to highlight some properties that meanings seem to have. If we want to find things that behave similarly they will need to have these properties too. In particular, I will look at the individuation of meaning. When are the meanings of two expressions identical? Or, in other words, what is synonymy? Introduction What is Meaning? And what is Synonymy? What is meaning? The question is not easy to answer.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Positivism, Operationalism, and Behaviorism
    This dissertation has been microfilmed exactly as received 70-6878 SHANAB, Robert E lias Abu, 1939- LOGICAL POSITIVISM, OPERATIONALISM, AND BEHAVIORISM. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1969 Philosophy University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan LOGICAL POSITIVISM, OPERATIONALISM, AND BEHAVIORISM DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Robert Elias Abu Shanab, B.A., A.M. ******** The Ohio State University 1969 Approved by / Adviser Department of Philosophy Dedicated to Professor Virgil Hinshaw, ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am especially indebted to my adviser, Professor Virgil Hinshaw, Jr. Several of his suggestions have been incorporated in the final manuscript. I wish also to express my thanks to Professor Charles F. Kielkopf. Finally I wish to extend affection and gratitude to my wife for encouragement, patience and for the hours spent typing and retyping manuscripts. ii VITA September 29, 1939 B o m - Jerusalem, Palestine 1962 ........ ........... B.A. , San Jose State College, San Jose, California 1964 ................... M.A., San Jose State College, San Jose, California 1965-1966 ............. Instructor, College of San Mateo, San Mateo, California 1967-1968 ....... Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 1969 ................... Lecturer, The Ohio State University, Newark, Ohio iii CONTENTS. Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ..... ....................... ii V I T A ..............................................iii
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Positivist Conception of Knowledge and the Verification Principle: a Reflection
    American International Journal of Social Science Vol. 3, No. 6; November 2014 Logical Positivist Conception of Knowledge and the Verification Principle: A Reflection Ade-Ali, Funmilayo A. Lecturer Department of Philosophy Olabisi Onabanjo University Ago-Iwoye, Ogun State Nigeria. Abstract The Logical positivist conception of knowledge holds that for any statement to be cognitively meaningful it should fall within the scope of the language of science. Thus meaningful statement of any sort can either be analytic or synthetic. By and large, the Vienna Circle of the logical positivists of the 1920s located its own world view of philosophy within the scientific world view with the establishment of the following theses viz: 1. The thesis of meaninglessness of Metaphysics 2. The Verification Principle 3. The Physicalist thesis. These theses therefore form the unifying factors among the continental logical positivists. And these theses by the language of the logical positivists are against the “traditional” and “metaphysical” conceptions of knowledge. The Logical analysis of Rudolf Carnap, one of the greatest members of logical positivism school makes several proclamations about these with a view to refining the language of philosophy in line with the physical and the scientific construction of language. It is in tune with this principle that the logical positivist conception of knowledge with its principle of verification is addressed and evaluated in this work. Keywords: Verification Principle, Logical Positivist, Knowledge, Analytic, Synthetic. Introduction This paper conceptually examines and evaluates the attack on metaphysics using the various theses of the logical positivists. Besides, an effort is made to point out the inherent inconsistencies involved in the logical positivist principles as to their unanimous rejection of metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • Misconceived Relationships Between Logical Positivism and Quantitative Research Chong Ho Yu, Ph.D., D
    Misconceived relationships between logical positivism and quantitative research Chong Ho Yu, Ph.D., D. Phil. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the 2001 American Educational Research Association, Seattle, WA Published in Research Method Forum, 2003 Included in the book Philosophical foundations of quantitative research methodology (2006, Laham, MD: University Press of America) Correspondence: Chong Ho Yu, Ph.D., D. Phil. Email: [email protected] Website: http://www.creative-wisdom.com/pub/pub.html Logical positivism and Quantitative Research 2 Abstract Although quantitative research methodology is widely applied by social scientists, there is a common misconception that quantitative research is based upon logical positivism. This misconception leads to misguided disputes between qualitative and quantitative researchers. This article points out that the polarities between the two are unnecessary, and the richness and continuity of “research traditions” is therefore proposed as a replacement for the incommensurability in the Kuhnian “paradigm.” Further, this article examines the relationship between quantitative research and eight major notions of logical positivism: (a) verification, (b) pro-observation, (c) anti-cause, (d) downplaying explanation, (e) anti- theoretical entities, (f) anti-metaphysics, (g) logical analysis and (h) frequentist probability. It is argued that the underlying philosophy of modern quantitative research does not subscribe to logical positivism. Associating an outdated philosophy with quantitative research
    [Show full text]
  • SAI and Autonomy of Syntax
    University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics Volume 6 University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics Volume 5 Article 6 1980 SAI and Autonomy of Syntax Michael Rochemont Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/umop Part of the Linguistics Commons Recommended Citation Rochemont, Michael (1980) "SAI and Autonomy of Syntax," University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics: Vol. 6 , Article 6. Available at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/umop/vol6/iss2/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Rochemont: SAI and Autonomy of Syntax .SAI AND AUTONOMY OF SYNTAX Michael Rochemont 0.0 In this paper we will critically examine the proposed analysis of Liberman (1975) of affective conditioned inversion constructions like that evidenced in the sentences which follow. Nowhere in the world can you find such beaches as these. At no time was John uncomfortable with Sue. Few men is David able to approach casually. The discussion assumes without subsequent argument the general validity of the framework of the. R.E.S.T., pa~ticularly as developed in Chomsky (1973) 1 (1977) and related work. Sections 1.1 and 1.2 review the pruning analysis Liberman proposes and in section l .3, some of the problems associated with such an analysis are noted; it will be argued here that the correlations Liberrnan 1 s pruning convention is designed to explain do not reflect true generalizations about English, and for this reason, the analysis will be seen to be without motivation .
    [Show full text]
  • Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives*
    (to appear in festschrift for David Kaplan, edited by Joseph Almog and Paolo Leonardi, Oxford: Oxford University Press) Reference, Inference and the Semantics of Pejoratives* Timothy Williamson 1. Introduction. Two opposing tendencies in the philosophy of language go by the names of ‘referentialism’ and ‘inferentialism’ respectively. In the crudest version of the contrast, the referentialist account of meaning gives centre stage to the referential semantics for a language, which is then used to explain the inference rules for the language, perhaps as those which preserve truth on that semantics (since a referential semantics for a language determines the truth-conditions of its sentences). By contrast, the inferentialist account of meaning gives centre stage to the inference rules for the language, which are then used to explain its referential semantics, perhaps as the semantics on which the rules preserve truth. On pain of circularity, we cannot combine both directions of explanation. Of course, this simple opposition may not survive more refined definitions of ‘referentialism’ and ‘inferentialism’. Not all of those willing to apply one or other term to their views would accept the crude characterizations just given. Nevertheless, the two styles of theorizing often function as rivals in practice. There is a corresponding contrast in the philosophy of thought, concerning the reference of concepts, rather than of 1 expressions of a public language, and inferential connections between thoughts, rather than between sentences. 2 If inferentialists appealed only to inference rules, they could not hope to explain how many words refer to extra-linguistic objects, or how language is used in interaction with the extra-linguistic environment.
    [Show full text]