Descartes and Spinoza
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead
The Twilight of Determinism: At Least in Biophysical Novelties Amihud Gilead Department of Philosophy, Eshkol Tower, University of Haifa, Haifa 3498838 Email: [email protected] Abstract. In the 1990s, Richard Lewontin referred to what appeared to be the twilight of determinism in biology. He pointed out that DNA determines only a little part of life phenomena, which are very complex. In fact, organisms determine the environment and vice versa in a nonlinear way. Very recently, biophysicists, Shimon Marom and Erez Braun, have demonstrated that controlled biophysical systems have shown a relative autonomy and flexibility in response which could not be predicted. Within the boundaries of some restraints, most of them genetic, this freedom from determinism is well maintained. Marom and Braun have challenged not only biophysical determinism but also reverse-engineering, naive reductionism, mechanism, and systems biology. Metaphysically possibly, anything actual is contingent.1 Of course, such a possibility is entirely excluded in Spinoza’s philosophy as well as in many philosophical views at present. Kant believed that anything phenomenal, namely, anything that is experimental or empirical, is inescapably subject to space, time, and categories (such as causality) which entail the undeniable validity of determinism. Both Kant and Laplace assumed that modern science, such as Newton’s physics, must rely upon such a deterministic view. According to Kant, free will is possible not in the phenomenal world, the empirical world in which we 1 This is an assumption of a full-blown metaphysics—panenmentalism—whose author is Amihud Gilead. See Gilead 1999, 2003, 2009 and 2011, including literary, psychological, and natural applications and examples —especially in chemistry —in Gilead 2009, 2010, 2013, 2014a–c, and 2015a–d. -
Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (Ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016)
Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016) Leibniz’s metaphysical views were not known to most of his correspondents, let alone to the larger public, until 1695 when he published an article in Journal des savants, titled in English “A New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances, and of the Union of the Soul and Body” (henceforth New System).1 The article raised quite a stir. Perhaps the most interesting and cunning critique of Leibniz’s views was provided by a French refugee in Rotterdam, Pierre Bayle (1647−1706) who is most famous for his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (1697). The fascinating controversy on Leibniz’s idea of pre-established harmony and a number of other topics lasted for five years and ended only when Bayle died. In this paper I will give an overview of the communication, discuss in detail a central topic concerning spontaneity or a sudden change in the soul, and compare the views presented in the communication to Leibniz’s reflections in his partly concurrent New Essays on Human Understanding (1704) (henceforth NE). I will also reflect on whether the controversy could have ended in agreement if it would have continued longer. The New System Let us begin with the article that started the controversy, the New System. The article starts with Leibniz’s objection to the Cartesian doctrine of extension as a basic way of explaining motion. Instead, one should adopt a doctrine of force which belongs to the sphere of metaphysics (GP IV 478). -
1Jackson (1998) Gives This Necessary Condition on Physicalism. 2Two of the Reasons That Kim Gives for Holding That Supervenience
For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research The main conclusion of Jaegwon Kim’s admirable Mind and the Physical World is that the mind- body problem- Descartes problem of explaining how mental causation is possible- has not yet been solved. In particular, non reductive physicalism (NRP), a metaphysical account of the relationship between mental and physical entities that has become increasingly popular among philosophers of mind and that Kim himself once endorsed, is not a viable solution to the problem. I argue here that Kim’s arguments against non-reductive physicalism are unpersuasive and suggest that they involve assumptions about causation that are implausible in the light of contemporary physics. When these assumptions are rejected NRP lives. NRP is a family of views differing by how they understand “reduction” and “physicalism.” Following Kim I understand the non-reduction as holding that some events and properties are distinct from any physical events and properties. A necessary condition for physicalism is that mental properties, events, and laws supervene on physical ones. Kim allows various understandings of “supervenience” but I think that physicalism requires at least the claim that any minimal physical duplicate of the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter.1 Some complications aside this means that true mental propositions, e.g. Jaegwon is thinking about sailing, are metaphysically entailed by true physical propositions. Kim says that supervenience is too weak to capture the root idea of physicalism that mental property instantiations depend on physical property instantiations so he adds that the mental depends on the physical.2 One way (but not the only way) in which this dependance might be spelled out is that mental properties are higher order functional properties whose instantiations are realized by instantiations of physical properties. -
Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/Nml/023
AMS / MAA ANNELI LAX NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY VOL 23 Ingenuity in Mathematics Ross Honsberger 10.1090/nml/023 INGENUITY IN MATHEMAmCS NEW MATHEMATICAL LIBRARY PUBLISHED BY THEMATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Editorial Committee Basil Gordon, Chairman (1975-76) Anneli Lax, Editor University of California, L.A. New York University Ivan Niven (1 975-77) University of Oregon M. M. Schiffer (1975-77) Stanford University The New Mathematical Library (NML) was begun in 1961 by the School Mathematics Study Group to make available to high school students short expository books on various topics not usually covered in the high school syllabus. In a decade the NML matured into a steadily growing series of some twenty titles of interest not only to the originally intended audience, but to college students and teachers at all levels. Previously published by Random House and L. W. Singer, the NML became a publication series of the Mathematical Association of America (MAA) in 1975. Under the auspices of the MAA the NML will continue to grow and will remain dedicated to its original and expanded purposes. INGENUITY IN MATHEMATICS by Ross Honsberger University of Waterloo, Canada 23 MATHEMATICAL ASSOCIATION OF AMERICA Illustrated by George H. Buehler Sixth Printing © Copyright 1970, by the Mathematical Association of America A11 rights reserved under International and Pan-American Copyright Conventions. Published in Washington by The Mathematical Association of America Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 77-134351 Print ISBN 978-0-88385-623-9 Electronic ISBN 978-0-88385-938-4 Manufactured in the United States of America Note to the Reader his book is one of a series written by professional mathematicians Tin order to make some important mathematical ideas interesting and understandable to a large audience of high school students and laymen. -
Expressions of Mind/Body Dualism in Thinspiration
MIND OVER MATTER: EXPRESSIONS OF MIND/BODY DUALISM IN THINSPIRATION Annamarie O’Brien A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2013 Committee: Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Dr. Rebecca Kinney Dr. Jeremy Wallach © 2013 Annamarie O’Brien All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT Dr. Marilyn Motz, Advisor Thinspiration images, meant to inspire weight-loss, proliferate online through platforms that encourage the circulation of user-generated content. Despite numerous alarmist critiques in mass media about thinspiration and various academic studies investigating ‘pro-anorexia’ sites, surprisingly little attention has been given to the processes of creation and the symbolic potential of thinspiration. This thesis analyzes the formal hybridity of thinspiration, and its use as an expressive medium. The particularities of thinspiration (including its visual characteristics, creative processes, and exhibition) may be considered carefully constructed instances of self- representation, hinging on the expression of beliefs regarding the mind and body. While these beliefs are deeply entrenched in popular body management discourse, they also tend to rely on traditional dualist ideologies. Rather than simply emphasizing slenderness or reiterating standard assumptions about beauty, thinspiration often evokes pain and sadness, and employs truisms about the transcendence of flesh and rebellion against social constraints. By harnessing individualist discourse and the values of mind/body dualism, thinspiration becomes a space in which people struggling with disordered eating and body image issues may cast themselves as active agents—contrary to the image of eating disorders proffered by popular and medical discourse. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, I would like to thank my thesis committee chair, Dr. -
Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis the Aim of This Paper Is to Support Donald Davidson's Anomalous Monism1 As An
do E s An o m A l o u s mo n i s m hA v E proper construal of Davidson’s principle Ex p l A n A t o r y fo r ce ? of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis “Mental Events” reconciles the paradox which arises from three principles Davidson held ex hypothesi: (1) Mental events interact causally with physical events (Principle of Causal Interaction), (2) Where there is causality, there must be a law (Principle of the Nomological The aim of this paper is to support Donald Character of Causality), and (3) There are no 1 strict deterministic laws on the basis of which Davidson’s Anomalous Monism as an account mental events can be predicted and explained of law-governed mental causation in a world (Principle of the Anomalism of the Mental).4 unfettered by psychophysical laws. To this end, I will attempt to answer one principal objection Tension is apparent in that some mental to the theory: the claim that Anomalous events must interact causally with physical events Monism lacks sufficient “explanatory force.”2 and thereby feature in laws, and that this is an Though not quite the standard objection, I explicit contradiction of the Principle of the believe it to be the most formidable, and hence Anomalism of the Mental. Accepting three the most crucial to address.3 The argument’s further principles, in addition to the three strength is that it need not dispute Davidson’s above, will resolve the tension: (4) Each mental assumptions. -
Descartes (1596-1650) from I
René Descartes (1596-1650) from http://radicalacademy.com/phildescartes1.htm I. General Observations René Descartes is justly considered the father of modern philosophy and the founder of the rational method as applied to philosophical research. In fact, he is the first philosopher to begin with the impressions which are in our intellect (intellectual phenomenalism) and lay down the laws which reason must follow in order to arrive at reasonably certain philosophical data. This phenomenalism does not find its full development in Descartes. Indeed, Descartes reaches metaphysical conclusions which are no different from those of Scholastic philosophy. He maintains the transcendency of God, upholds human liberty and Christian morality. But pantheism is sown deep in every form of immanentism. The rationalism of Descartes was to be quickly and logically bent in this direction by Spinoza, while other Cartesians, such as Malebranche and Leibniz, tried -- with less logic -- middle-of-the-road solutions between pantheism and the transcendence of God. II. Life and Works Descartes was born in 1596 at La Haye in France of a noble family, and was educated in the celebrated Jesuit college of La Flèche, where he received a philosophical and scientific education according to the principles of the Scholasticism of his day. Not fully satisfied with this first education, and urged on by a desire to better himself, he went first to Paris, and then enlisted in the army during the Thirty Years' War. On the ninth of November, 1619, while still in the service in winter quarters, he gave himself up to meditating on how to apply the mathematical method of the sciences to philosophy. -
Laws in Metaphysics
LAWS IN METAPHYSICS BY TOBIAS WILSCH A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School—New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Philosophy Written under the direction of Jonathan Schaffer and approved by ___________________________________ ___________________________________ ___________________________________ ___________________________________ New Brunswick, New Jersey May, 2015 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Laws in Metaphysics By TOBIAS WILSCH Dissertation director: Jonathan Schaffer The first two chapters of this dissertation defend the Deductive-Nomological Account of metaphysical explanation. Chapter 1 develops the Nomological Account of ground, – p1, …, pn ground q if and only if the laws of metaphysics determine q on the basis of p1, …, pn, – and the constructional theory of the metaphysical laws, – the laws are general principles that characterize construction-operations. Chapter 2 offers an analysis of the notion of determination involved in the Nomological Account: the laws determine q based on p1, …, pn if and only if q follows from p1, …, pn and the laws in the grounding-calculus. The grounding-calculus is characterized in terms of two inference rules and a suitable notion of ‘proof’. The rules are designed to analyze the input- and output notions that are intuitively associated with laws: the laws take some facts as input and deliver some other facts as output. ii Chapters 1 and 2 also go beyond the development of the positive view. Chapter 1 shows how the Nomological Account explains general patterns among grounding-truths, the modal force of ground, and certain connections between ground and construction. Chapter 2 shows why the Deductive-Nomological Account of metaphysical explanation escapes the objections to the traditional DN-account of scientific explanation, and it also outlines two views on logical explanation that are available to the proponent of the Nomological Account. -
University of Groningen Spinoza's Theory of the Human Mind
University of Groningen Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason Marrama, Oberto IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 2019 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Marrama, O. (2019). Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason. University of Groningen. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 27-09-2021 SPINOZA’S THEORY OF THE HUMAN MIND: CONSCIOUSNESS, MEMORY, AND REASON 1A_BW_Marrama .job © Oberto Marrama, 2019. All rights reserved. ISBN 978-94-034-1568-0 (printed version) ISBN 978-94-034-1569-7 (electronic version) 1B_BW_Marrama .job Spinoza’s Theory of the Human Mind: Consciousness, Memory, and Reason PhD thesis to obtain the degree of PhD at the University of Groningen on the authority of the Rector Magnificus Prof. -
Machine Guessing – I
Machine Guessing { I David Miller Department of Philosophy University of Warwick COVENTRY CV4 7AL UK e-mail: [email protected] ⃝c copyright D. W. Miller 2011{2018 Abstract According to Karl Popper, the evolution of science, logically, methodologically, and even psy- chologically, is an involved interplay of acute conjectures and blunt refutations. Like biological evolution, it is an endless round of blind variation and selective retention. But unlike biological evolution, it incorporates, at the stage of selection, the use of reason. Part I of this two-part paper begins by repudiating the common beliefs that Hume's problem of induction, which com- pellingly confutes the thesis that science is rational in the way that most people think that it is rational, can be solved by assuming that science is rational, or by assuming that Hume was irrational (that is, by ignoring his argument). The problem of induction can be solved only by a non-authoritarian theory of rationality. It is shown also that because hypotheses cannot be distilled directly from experience, all knowledge is eventually dependent on blind conjecture, and therefore itself conjectural. In particular, the use of rules of inference, or of good or bad rules for generating conjectures, is conjectural. Part II of the paper expounds a form of Popper's critical rationalism that locates the rationality of science entirely in the deductive processes by which conjectures are criticized and improved. But extreme forms of deductivism are rejected. The paper concludes with a sharp dismissal of the view that work in artificial intelligence, including the JSM method cultivated extensively by Victor Finn, does anything to upset critical rationalism. -
Body, Mind and Spirit—Philosophical Reflections for Researching
education sciences Article Body, Mind and Spirit—Philosophical Reflections for Researching Education about the Holocaust Katalin Eszter Morgan Historisches Institut, Fakultät für Geisteswissenschaften, Universität Duisburg-Essen, Campus Essen, Universitätsstr, 12 45117 Essen, Germany; [email protected], Tel.: +49-201-183-7395 Received: 14 August 2017; Accepted: 14 September 2017; Published: 20 September 2017 Abstract: This reflective essay draws a sketch of the theoretical and philosophical foundations in preparation for conducting a research project that investigates how German school learners deal with the memories of Shoah survivors. The essay explores some communication challenges and opportunities presented by the use of the double linguistic medium—German and English. The central philosophical argument is that there is a conceptual conflation of and confusion around the word Geist (spirit/mind), and that the difference between the spirit and the mind needs to be explored and clarified. For this purpose Hegel’s thoughts on the spirit are considered and related to theories of memory. Also, Theodor Lessing’s reflections on the origins of hatred are touched upon, which he traces back to the splitting of the spirit from the mind. How the body, mind and spirit work together is highlighted with a biographical example of a descendant of a Nazi perpetrator. By way of conclusion, the philosophical and methodological implications for researching education about the Shoah are briefly discussed. Keywords: education about the holocaust; Hegel; spirit; mind; Geist; memory; language 1. Introduction This essay sketches out some theoretical and philosophical ideas in preparation for conducting a research project that investigates how learners deal with the memories of Holocaust survivors in German schools. -
The Virtues of Ingenuity: Reasoning and Arguing Without Bias
Topoi DOI 10.1007/s11245-013-9174-y The Virtues of Ingenuity: Reasoning and Arguing without Bias Olivier Morin Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013 Abstract This paper describes and defends the ‘‘virtues Ingenuity is the use of reasoning to gather information of ingenuity’’: detachment, lucidity, thoroughness. Philos- and to solve problems. This paper is about its virtues,in ophers traditionally praise these virtues for their role in the both senses of the term: the things that ingenuity is good practice of using reasoning to solve problems and gather for, and the qualities that it takes to be good at it. The information. Yet, reasoning has other, no less important philosophical tradition, particularly since Bacon and uses. Conviction is one of them. A recent revival of rhet- Descartes, has praised detachment, freedom from pre- oric and argumentative approaches to reasoning (in psy- judice, and objectivity, in terms that may sound quaintly chology, philosophy and science studies) has highlighted excessive today. The celebration of ingenuity often went the virtues of persuasiveness and cast a new light on some along with a demotion of other uses of reasoning. Con- of its apparent vices—bad faith, deluded confidence, con- viction, or persuasion—the use of reasoning to change firmation and myside biases. Those traits, it is often argued, other people’s minds—was one of them. Conviction and will no longer look so detrimental once we grasp their ingenuity arguably require different dispositions: a con- proper function: arguing in order to persuade, rather than vincing argumentation benefits from a sensitivity to other thinking in order to solve problems.