Aristotle on Truth

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle on Truth This page intentionally left blank ARISTOTLE ON TRUTH Aristotle’s theory of truth, which has been the most influential account of the concept of truth from Antiquity onwards, spans several areas of philosophy: philosophy of language, logic, ontology, and episte- mology. In this book, the first dedicated to this topic, Paolo Crivelli discusses all the main aspects of Aristotle’s views on truth and false- hood. He analyses in detail the main relevant passages, addresses some well-known problems of Aristotelian semantics, and assesses Aristotle’s theory from the point of view of modern analytic philosophy. In the process he discusses most of the literature on Aristotle’s semantic theory to have appeared in the last two centuries. His book vindi- cates and clarifies the often repeated claim that Aristotle’s is a corre- spondence theory of truth. It will be of interest to a wide range of readers working in both ancient philosophy and modern philosophy of language. paolo crivelli is Fellow and Tutor in Classical Philosophy at New College, Oxford. He has published articles on Plato’s logic and epistemology, Aristotle’s philosophical logic, and Stoic logic. ARISTOTLE ON TRUTH PAOLO CRIVELLI University of Oxford cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521823289 © Paolo Crivelli 2004 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provision of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published in print format 2004 isbn-13 978-0-511-23002-8 eBook (EBL) isbn-10 0-511-23002-8 eBook (EBL) isbn-13 978-0-521-82328-9 hardback isbn-10 0-521-82328-5 hardback Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. To the memory of my father Renzo Crivelli and to my mother Katherine Lester Crivelli Contents Acknowledgements page ix Notes on the text x List of abbreviations of titles of Aristotle’s works xi Introduction 1 1 An overview of Aristotle’s theory of truth 1 2 Methodology 39 part i bearers of truth or falsehood 1 States of affairs, thoughts, and sentences 45 1 States of affairs 46 2 Thoughts 62 3 Sentences 72 2 Tr uth conditions for predicative assertions 77 1 Universals 78 2 Truth and falsehood in de Interpretatione 182 3 Affirmative and negative predicative assertions 86 4 Assertions about individuals vs assertions about universals 89 5 Tr uth and the categories 95 3 Tr uth conditions for existential assertions 99 1 Existential assertions concerning simple items 100 2 Non-composite substances 116 3 Singular existential assertions concerning material substances 121 part ii ‘empty’ terms 4 Tr uth as correspondence 129 1 A correspondence theory of truth? 129 2 The Liar 139 vii viii Contents 5 ‘Vacuous’ terms and ‘empty’ terms 152 1 ‘Vacuous’ subjects or predicates 153 2 ‘Empty’ subjects or predicates 158 3 One assertion vs many assertions 163 part iii truth and time 6 Tr uth and change 183 1 Different truth-values at different times 183 2 Tr uth and relatives 189 3 How far is truth from change? 194 7 Tr uth and Determinism in de Interpretatione 9 198 1 The modal attributes and theses involved in Int. 9 199 2 Close textual analysis of Int. 9 200 3 Alternative interpretations 226 Appendix 1 Metaph. 10, 1051b1: the text 234 Appendix 2 Metaph. 10, 1051b2–3: the text 238 Appendix 3 Int. 7, 17b16–18: the text 239 Appendix 4 The two-place relations in Aristotle’s definition of truth 254 Appendix 5 Aristotle’s theory of truth for predicative assertions: formal presentation 258 Appendix 6 The failure of Bivalence for future-tense assertions: formal presentation 266 References 284 Index of names 313 Index of subjects 319 Index of passages 321 Acknowledgements Many friends and colleagues helped me to shape my views on many of the issues addressed by this study, and alerted me to points where improvement was desirable. Early drafts of parts of the book were presented in Cambridge, Clark, Edinburgh, Florence, Liverpool, Oxford, and Pisa. Among the indi- viduals who in various ways helped me to bring this project to completion, I should like to mention Francesco Ademollo, Francesco Adorno, Fab- rizio Amerini, Sylvia Berryman, Susanne Bobzien, Ettore Casari, Walter Cavini, David Charles, Francesco Del Punta, Paolo Fait, Michael Frede, Gabriele Galluzzo, Richard Gaskin, Katerina Ierodiakonou, Fred Miller, Peter Milne, Ben Morison, Massimo Mugnai, David Robinson, Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra, Theodore Scaltsas, Annamaria Schiaparelli, David Sed- ley, Bob Sharples, Robin Smith, Christopher Strachan, John Thorp, Tim Williamson, and an anonymous referee for Cambridge University Press. The responsibility for the remaining shortcomings is of course mine alone. ix Notes on the text ‘LSJ’ abbreviates the Liddell, Scott, Jones Greek–English lexicon. Irefer to Aristotelian passages by the line numbers as they are printed in Bekker’s original edition: these in some cases differ from the ‘Bekker lines’ of widespread editions (e.g., 101b38 of Ross’s edition of the Topics is 101b39 of Bekker’s original edition). Similarly, I follow Bekker’s numbering of the chapters within each book of the Nicomachean Ethics. ForGreek authors I use LSJ’s standard abbreviations. For authors other than Aristotle, I normally use the critical editions on which LSJ relies. For Latin authors, I employ abbreviations which are easy to decode and I use standard critical editions. ‘Cf.’ at the beginning of a footnote indicates that the passages subse- quently referred to express views close to those formulated in the portion of the main text to which the footnote pertains. If I disagree with an author, I say so explicitly (I never use ‘cf.’ to refer to one or more passages that for- mulate views with which I disagree). I use quotation marks for three purposes: (i) to mention linguistic expres- sions, e.g. the word ‘dog’ is a noun; (ii) to indicate that a certain linguistic expression is being used in some special or unusual sense, e.g. Homer is a ‘philosopher’; (iii) to quote a portion of text from some author, e.g. Aristo- tle says that ‘sentences are true in the same way as the objects’ (Int. 9, 19a33). I use double quotation marks (“and”) only when what would otherwise be occurrences of single quotation marks would be embedded within single quotation marks. x Abbreviations of titles of Aristotle’s works APo. Posterior Analytics APr. Prior Analytics Cael. de Caelo Cat. Categories de An. de Anima Div. Somn. de Divinatione per Somnia EE Eudemian Ethics EN Nicomachean Ethics GA de Generatione Animalium GC de Generatione et Corruptione HA Historia Animalium Insomn. de Insomniis Int. de Interpretatione Long. de Longaevitate MM Magna Moralia Mem. de Memoria Metaph. Metaphysics PA de Partibus Animalium Ph.Physics Po.Poetics Pol. Politics Pr.Problems Rh. Rhetoric SE Sophistici Elenchi Sens. de Sensu Somn. Vig. de Somno et Vigilia Top. Topics Xen. de Xenophane xi Introduction The study of truth is a central part of the philosophical tradition we have inherited from classical Greece. Aristotle played an important role in devel- oping and sharpening the debate in this area and on many issues that are connected with it. I have two primary goals: to offer a precise reconstruction of all of Aristotle’s most significant views on truth and falsehood and to gain a philosophical understanding of them. In this introduction I first offer an overview of Aristotle’s theory of truth and then discuss the methodology I adopt in pursuing my primary goals. 1anoverview of aristotle’s theory of truth Why an overview? Aristotle speaks about truth and falsehood in passages from several works, mainly the Categories (chapters 4, 5, 10, and 12), de Inter- pretatione (chapters 1–9), Sophistici Elenchi (chapter 25), de Anima (chapter 3.6), and the Metaphysics (chapters 7, 7, 29,E4, and 10). Truth and falsehood are not the main topic of these works: their discussions of truth and falsehood are asides. Reconstructing an Aristotelian theory of truth and falsehood on the basis of such asides poses complicated problems of various sorts. To help readers to keep their orientation through the many bifurcations of the arguments addressing these problems, I decided to offer a concise but precise map of the territory – an overview of Aristotle’s theory of truth. References to the passages from Aristotle’s works that substantiate the attribution of a certain view to him, and an examination of the rel- evant secondary literature, will be found in the chapters that follow this introduction. Universals.Toexpound Aristotle’s theory of truth, I need to present some of his views on universals and signification. I begin with universals. Luckily, it is not necessary to embark on the daunting task of a com- plete exposition of Aristotle’s views on universals. Aristotle is to this extent 1 2 Introduction arealist about universals: in his view, universals are objects whose nature is neither mental nor linguistic (they are neither concepts nor linguis- tic expressions). He believes that every universal exists when and only when1 it holds of some individual or other that at some time or other exists.2 Let me spend a few words explaining why the phrase ‘at some time or other’ is needed.
Recommended publications
  • Existentialism, Phenomenology, and Education James Magrini College of Dupage, [email protected]
    College of DuPage [email protected]. Philosophy Scholarship Philosophy 7-1-2012 Existentialism, Phenomenology, and Education James Magrini College of DuPage, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.cod.edu/philosophypub Part of the Education Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Magrini, James, "Existentialism, Phenomenology, and Education" (2012). Philosophy Scholarship. Paper 30. http://dc.cod.edu/philosophypub/30 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at [email protected].. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Scholarship by an authorized administrator of [email protected].. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Existentialism, Phenomenology, and Education James M. Magrini Existentialism, and specifically phenomenology, in qualitative educational research, tends to be misunderstood. There are many reasons for this, not the least of which is that scholars/researchers writing in the field often emulate and imitate the dense writing styles of philosophical forerunners in phenomenology such as Hegel, Brentano, Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty. Thus the writing is beyond the comprehension of many education professionals and practitioners. Existentialism and phenomenology need not be highly complex. Here I provide a summary of existentialism and phenomenology in accessible terms so that educators might see the potential this type of philosophy holds for enhancing our educational endeavors. 1. Existentialism is a modern philosophy emerging (existence-philosophy) from the 19th century, inspired by such thinkers as Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. Unlike traditional philosophy, which focuses on “objective” instances of truth, existentialism is concerned with the subjective, or personal, aspects of existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View
    R ené Descartes (1596-1650) is generally regarded as the “father of modern philosophy.” He stands as one of the most important figures in Western intellectual history. His work in mathematics and his writings on science proved to be foundational for further development in these fields. Our understanding of “scientific method” can be traced back to the work of Francis Bacon and to Descartes’ Discourse on Method. His groundbreaking approach to philosophy in his Meditations on First Philosophy determine the course of subsequent philosophy. The very problems with which much of modern philosophy has been primarily concerned arise only as a consequence of Descartes’thought. Descartes’ philosophy must be understood in the context of his times. The Medieval world was in the process of disintegration. The authoritarianism that had dominated the Medieval period was called into question by the rise of the Protestant revolt and advances in the development of science. Martin Luther’s emphasis that salvation was a matter of “faith” and not “works” undermined papal authority in asserting that each individual has a channel to God. The Copernican revolution undermined the authority of the Catholic Church in directly contradicting the established church doctrine of a geocentric universe. The rise of the sciences directly challenged the Church and seemed to put science and religion in opposition. A mathematician and scientist as well as a devout Catholic, Descartes was concerned primarily with establishing certain foundations for science and philosophy, and yet also with bridging the gap between the “new science” and religion. Descartes’ Influence in Shaping the Modern World-View 1) Descartes’ disbelief in authoritarianism: Descartes’ belief that all individuals possess the “natural light of reason,” the belief that each individual has the capacity for the discovery of truth, undermined Roman Catholic authoritarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • COPULAR CLAUSES in ENGLISH* Masatake Arimoto Nanzan University 1. Introduction English Has Copular Verb Be As Exemplified In
    COPULAR CLAUSES IN ENGLISH* Masatake Arimoto Nanzan University 1. Introduction English has copular verb be as exemplified in sentences like (1) and (2). (1) a. John is honest. b. John is a philosopher. (2) a. John is the Mayor of Cambridge. b. A picture of the wall was the cause of the riot. (Moro, 1997) Sentences in (1) and (2) appear to express that the pre-verbal elements are related to post-verbal elements in the same way. However, sentences in (1) and those in (2) behave differently. For example, if post-verbal elements are placed before be and pre-verbal elements are placed after be, the resultant sentences are unacceptable for (1) as in (3), but acceptable for (2) as in (4). (3) a. *Honest is John. b. *A philosopher is John. (4) a. The Mayor of Cambridge is John. b. The cause of the riot was a picture of the wall. Sentences like (2) and sentences like (4) again appear to express the same meanings, but there are some syntactic differences between them. Both of them appear in an ECM construction as in (5), but only sentences in (2) are possible in a Small Clause construction as in (6): sentences in (4) are impossible in a Small Clause construction as in (6b). (5) a. John considers a picture of the wall to be the cause of the riot. b. John considers the cause of the riot to be a picture of the wall. (6) a. John considers a picture of the wall the cause of the riot. b.
    [Show full text]
  • On ''Verbal Dps'
    From predication to reference: On ”verbal DPs” in Movima Katharina Haude To cite this version: Katharina Haude. From predication to reference: On ”verbal DPs” in Movima. Bonnot Christine; Outi Duvallon; Hélène de Penanros. Individuation et référence nominale à travers les langues, Lambert- Lucas, pp.53-77, 2019, 978-2-35935-294-8. hal-01971969v2 HAL Id: hal-01971969 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01971969v2 Submitted on 3 Jan 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. From predication to reference: On “verbal DPs” in Movima Katharina Haude (CNRS–SeDyL) Published as: Haude, Katharina. 2019. From predication to reference: On “verbal DPs” in Movima. In Individuation et référence nominale à travers les langues. Bonnot, Christine, Outi Duvallon et Hélène de Penanros (eds), 53-77. Paris: Editions Lambert-Lucas. Abstract In Movima (isolate, Bolivia), both verbs and nouns are basically predicates, but when preceded by an article, both nouns and verbs form part of a determiner phrase (DP). The article has an individuating function in that it specifies the referent for humanness/sex, number, and spatio- temporal location. When a DP contains a verb, it refers to an event participant, whose role in the event (single participant, agent, or patient) is identified by verbal morphology.
    [Show full text]
  • “Modern” Philosophy: Introduction
    “Modern” Philosophy: Introduction [from Debates in Modern Philosophy by Stewart Duncan and Antonia LoLordo (Routledge, 2013)] This course discusses the views of various European of his contemporaries (e.g. Thomas Hobbes) did see philosophers of the seventeenth century. Along with themselves as engaged in a new project in philosophy the thinkers of the eighteenth century, they are con- and the sciences, which somehow contained a new sidered “modern” philosophers. That might not seem way of explaining how the world worked. So, what terribly modern. René Descartes was writing in the was this new project? And what, if anything, did all 1630s and 1640s, and Immanuel Kant died in 1804. these modern philosophers have in common? By many standards, that was a long time ago. So, why is the work of Descartes, Kant, and their contempor- Two themes emerge when you read what Des- aries called modern philosophy? cartes and Hobbes say about their new philosophies. First, they think that earlier philosophers, particu- In one way this question has a trivial answer. larly so-called Scholastic Aristotelians—medieval “Modern” is being used here to describe a period of European philosophers who were influenced by time, and to contrast it with other periods of time. So, Aristotle—were mistaken about many issues, and modern philosophy is not the philosophy of today as that the new, modern way is better. (They say nicer contrasted with the philosophy of the 2020s or even things about Aristotle himself, and about some other the 1950s. Rather it’s the philosophy of the 1600s previous philosophers.) This view was shared by and onwards, as opposed to ancient and medieval many modern philosophers, but not all of them.
    [Show full text]
  • SPINOZA's ETHICS: FREEDOM and DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero
    SPINOZA’S ETHICS: FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM by Alfredo Lucero-Montaño 1. What remains alive of a philosopher's thought are the realities that concern him, the problems that he addresses, as well as the questions that he poses. The breath and depth of a philosopher's thought is what continues to excite and incite today. However, his answers are limited to his time and circumstances, and these are subject to the historical evolution of thought, yet his principal commitments are based on the problems and questions with which he is concerned. And this is what resounds of a philosopher's thought, which we can theoretically and practically adopt and adapt. Spinoza is immersed in a time of reforms, and he is a revolutionary and a reformer himself. The reforming trend in modern philosophy is expressed in an eminent way by Descartes' philosophy. Descartes, the great restorer of science and metaphysics, had left unfinished the task of a new foundation of ethics. Spinoza was thus faced with this enterprise. But he couldn't carry it out without the conviction of the importance of the ethical problems or that ethics is involved in a fundamental aspect of existence: the moral destiny of man. Spinoza's Ethics[1] is based on a theory of man or, more precisely, on an ontology of man. Ethics is, for him, ontology. He does not approach the problems of morality — the nature of good and evil, why and wherefore of human life — if it is not on the basis of a conception of man's being-in-itself, to wit, that the moral existence of man can only be explained by its own condition.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cross-Linguistic Study of Grammatical Organization
    Complement Clauses and Complementation Systems: A Cross-Linguistic Study of Grammatical Organization Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) vorgelegt dem Rat der Philosophischen Fakultät der Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena von Karsten Schmidtke-Bode, M.A. geb. am 26.06.1981 in Eisenach Gutachter: 1. Prof. Dr. Holger Diessel (Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena) 2. Prof. Dr. Volker Gast (Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena) 3. Prof. Dr. Martin Haspelmath (MPI für Evolutionäre Anthropologie Leipzig) Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 16.12.2014 Contents Abbreviations and notational conventions iii 1 Introduction 1 2 The phenomenon of complementation 7 2.1 Introduction 7 2.2 Argument status 9 2.2.1 Complement clauses and argument-structure typology 10 2.2.2 On the notion of ‘argument’ 21 2.3 On the notion of ‘clause’ 26 2.3.1 Complementation constructions as biclausal units 27 2.3.2 The internal structure of clauses 31 2.4 The semantic content of complement clauses 34 2.5 Environments of complementation 36 2.5.1 Predicate classes as environments of complementation 37 2.5.2 Environments studied in the present work 39 3 Data and methods 48 3.1 Sampling and sources of information 48 3.2 Selection and nature of the data points 53 3.3 Storage and analysis of the data 59 4 The internal structure of complementation patterns 62 4.1 Introduction 62 4.2 The morphological status of the predicate 64 4.2.1 Nominalization 65 4.2.2 Converbs 68 4.2.3 Participles 70 4.2.4 Bare verb stems 71 4.2.5 Other dependent
    [Show full text]
  • Michael of Ephesus' Comments on Aristotle's De Memoria
    NATIONAL AND KAPODISTRIAN UNIVERSITY OF ATHENS NATIONAL TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY OF ATHENS Michael of Ephesus’ comments on Aristotle’s De memoria Graduate Programme in the History and Philosophy of Science and Technology Daphne Argyri Advisor: Katerina Ierodiakonou Athens 2016 ΔΙΠΛΩΜΑΤΙΚΗ ΕΡΓΑΣΙΑ Ονοματεπώνυμο: Δάφνη Αργύρη Μεταπτυχιακό πρόγραμμα: Ιστορία και Φιλοσοφία των Επιστημών και της Τεχνολογίας (ΙΦΕΤ) Α.Μ.: 004/13 Υπεύθυνη καθηγήτρια: Κατερίνα Ιεροδιακόνου Αναγνώστες: Βασίλης Καρασμάνης Παύλος Καλλιγάς i Τα σχόλια του Μιχαήλ Εφέσιου στο Περί μνήμης του Αριστοτέλη Στην πραγματεία του Περί μνήμης και αναμνήσεως ο Αριστοτέλης παρουσιάζει τη μνήμη ως βασικό στοιχείο της γνωστικής διαδικασίας, πολύ συγγενές με την αντίληψη. Πρόκειται για μια παθητική κατάσταση (ἕξις/πάθος, 449b25), δηλαδή για μια αποθήκη της ψυχής γεμάτη με εικόνες του παρελθόντος, που σε αντίθεση και συνέχεια του Πλάτωνα διακρίνεται εμφατικά από την σαφώς ενεργητική διαδικασία της ανάμνησης. Η ανάμνηση συνίσταται στη δυνατότητα ανάκλησης στο παρόν, εκουσίως ή ακουσίως, των εικόνων του παρελθόντος και ανήκει, σαν συλλογισμός (οἷον συλλογισμός τις, 453a10), στο μέρος της ψυχής που συνδέεται με την λογική ικανότητα του ανθρώπου. Το υπόμνημα του Μιχαήλ Εφέσιου (12ος αι. μ.Χ.) στο παραπάνω έργο του Αριστοτέλη (Σχόλια εἰς τὸ Περὶ μνήμης καὶ ἀναμνήσεως, 1-41) είναι το μόνο υπόμνημα σε αυτό που σώζεται ως τις μέρες μας και αποτελεί πολύ σημαντική πηγή για την ιστορία των δύο αυτών εννοιών. Οι οξυδερκείς παρατηρήσεις και τα σχόλια του Μιχαήλ φαίνεται κατ΄αρχάς πως έχουν επηρεαστεί από τις διάφορες σχολές σκέψης με τις οποίες ήταν εξοικειωμένος, αλλά παράλληλα εκφράζουν ξεκάθαρα και τις προσωπικές του αντιλήψεις πάνω στο θέμα. Συγκεκριμένα, φανερώνεται μια συγκροτημένη θεώρηση της μνήμης και της ανάμνησης καθώς και του τρόπου με τον οποίο σχετίζονται και αλληλεπιδρούν στο πλαίσιο μιας συστηματικής γνωστικής θεωρίας.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY 27 Early Modern Philosophy in This Course We Will
    PHILOSOPHY 27 Early Modern Philosophy Michael Epperson CSUS Office: Mendocino Hall # 3036 Fall 2010 Telephone: 278-4535 T & TH 10:30 – 11:45, Amador 152 Email: [email protected] Office Hours: By Appointment Description In this course we will examine the ways in which the scientific and political innovations of 16th, 17th, and 18th century Europe both influenced and were influenced by the rationalist and empiricist philosophical traditions that competed and flourished during this period. We will study the works of several philosophers working within these two traditions as they struggled to make sense of the scientific and social revolutions sweeping through their world; and we will see how their work would, in turn, help shape these revolutions, even as they continue to evolve today. One focus of the course, then, will be to examine the ways in which these philosophical traditions have maintained their relevance and influence in our own millennium as 21st century science struggles with its most difficult questions yet. Our survey will entail a careful reading and critique of the metaphysical and epistemological schemes developed by key philosophers of the early modern period, beginning with the work of Bacon, Galileo, and Descartes and concluding with Kant and his revolutionary synthesis of the rationalist and empiricist worldviews. The course website can be found at: www.csus.edu/cpns/epperson. Requirements Our work will primarily be lecture and discussion, so both careful attention to the readings and class participation will be crucial for a lively course. Please bring your text to class. There will be two examinations--one take-home mid-term paper and one in-class final--as well as several homework assignments and unannounced short answer quizzes on the readings.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Al-Farabi's Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics
    Al-Farabi’s Short Commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Analytics Translated, with an Introduction and Notes, by Nicholas Rescher University of Pittsburgh Press AL-FARABI’S SHORT COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE’S PRIOR ANALYTICS AL-FARABI’S SHORT COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE’S PRIOR ANALYTICS Translated from the Original Arabic with Introduction and Notes BY NICHOLAS RESCHER Professor of Philosophy in the University of Pittsburgh UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH PRESS 1963 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 63-10581 Printed in Great Britain by Butler & ‘Tanner Ltd, Frome and London This book is dedicated, with gratitude and with love, to my mother and to the memory of my father. PREFACE This English version of al-Farabi’s “Short Commentary on Prior Analytics”, made from Mlle Mubahat Tirker’s recent edition of the Arabic text (Revue de la Faculté des Langues, d Histoire, et de Géographie de? Université d Ankara, vol. 16 [1958]), is the first appearanceof this treatise in a European language. It is hoped that this addition to the dozen or so Arabic logical texts now accessible to the non- Orientalist will contribute to a wider appreciation of the great mass of work constituting the Arabic contribution to logic, which remains so largely terra incognita. I wish to thank Mrs. Shukrieh Kassis and especially Mr. Seostoris Khalil for help with the translation. I am in- debted to Mr. Storrs McCall, Dr. J. Ackrill, and particu- larly to Professor D. M. Dunlop for reading my typescript and suggesting needed improvements. Although some strengths of this work owetheir existence to others, all of its weaknesses and errors must be laid at my own door.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and Aristotle on What Is Common to Soul and Body. Some Remarks on a Complicated Issue
    Chapter 8 Plato and Aristotle On What Is Common to Soul and Body. Some Remarks on a Complicated Issue Marcelo D. Boeri Abstract Aristotelian scholars tend to reject the Cartesian dualism as applied to Aristotelian model of the soul, and favor the view that denies that the soul is radically opposed to body. This is so due the fact that Aristotle takes the living being to be a unified whole (composed by form and matter). I start by reminding that both Plato and Aristotle argue that by their very nature soul and body are different, but at the same time they maintain that there are things that are ‘common’ to soul and body. The issue is how it is possible that two entities so different in nature have something in common. I argue that the key to the problem lies in the fact that both Plato and Aristotle regard the soul and the body as capacities, and that – in so far as they are able to act and to be acted upon – such is the ‘commonality’ shared both by soul and body. Given that capacities are relational entities, both of them turn out to be very plastic notions that should not necessarily be understood as entirely foreign to each other. 8.1 Introduction Both Plato and Aristotle famously argue that soul and body are two different kinds of entities: the soul is immaterial and the body material; the former is able to set in motion the body, and the latter is motionless.1 If this is so, one might assume that by their very nature soul and body are two profoundly disparate entities.
    [Show full text]