– 1 – This Is a Post-Peer-Review, Pre-Copyedit Version of an Article

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

– 1 – This Is a Post-Peer-Review, Pre-Copyedit Version of an Article This is a post-peer-review, pre-copyedit version of an article published in History of Philosophy Quarterly 35 (2018), 371–387. Ethical Culture. Felix Adler and the Emergence of Applied Ethics from the Spirit of American Pragmatism Bert Heinrichs Abstract In this article, I seek to show that—contrary to the two prevailing views—applied ethics has neither existed “all along,” nor should it be regarded as an unforeseen philosophical response to new kinds of social challenges in the 1960s. In contrast, applied ethics is a genuine philosophical innovation whose origins can be traced back to the late nineteenth century. It is my central thesis that the key step in its development occurred in the intellectual environment around American Pragmatism. To be precise, I will claim that Felix Adler can be regarded as the founder of applied ethics in the modern sense. Consideration of the historical context allows for an understanding of applied ethics as an approach deeply rooted in the philosophical tradition and, at the same time, facilitates comprehension of important methodological characteristics that are still relevant for contemporary practice. Keywords Applied ethics, Felix Adler, pragmatism, Kantianism 1. The Notion of Applied Ethics In this article, I seek to show that—contrary to the two prevailing views—applied ethics has neither existed “all along,” nor should it be regarded as an unforeseen – 1 – philosophical response to new kinds of social challenges in the 1960s.1 In contrast, applied ethics is a genuine philosophical innovation whose origins can be traced back to the late nineteenth century. It is my central thesis that the key step in its development occurred in the intellectual environment around American Pragmatism. To be precise, I will claim that Felix Adler can be regarded as the founder of applied ethics in the modern sense. Consideration of the historical context allows for an understanding of applied ethics as an approach deeply rooted in the philosophical tradition and, at the same time, facilitates comprehension of important methodological characteristics that are still relevant for contemporary practice. (cf. Jamieson, “Constructing Practical Ethics,” 843-65) In a broad sense, the notion of applied ethics “refers to any use of philosophical methods to treat moral problems, practices, and policies in the professions, technology, government, and the like.” (Beauchamp, “The Nature of Applied Ethics,” 3) This broad understanding of applied ethics is prevailing in contemporary debates. In this view, the notion of applied ethics is synonymous to practical ethics—a notion that can be traced back at least to the seventeenth-century writer Charles Davenant (Beauchamp, “History and Theory in ‘Applied Ethics,’” 58-59)—and closely related to professional ethics. (Beauchamp, “The Nature of Applied Ethics,” 1-3) However, in a narrow sense applied ethics designates the application of abstract ethical principles to concrete moral problems. A clear case of this narrow understanding of applied ethics can, for example, be found in the influential Belmont Report that was published by the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research in reaction to the Tuskegee Syphilis Study in 1979. Part B of this report starts with the following clarification: The expression “basic ethical principles” refers to those general judgements that serve as a basic justification for the many particular ethical prescriptions and – 2 – evaluations of human action. (National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, The Belmont Report, Part B) Subsequently, three principles are stated (respect for persons, beneficence, and justice). Under the title “Applications”, Part C of the report is, then, dedicated to the application of these principles to the the conduct of research. According to the Commission, the three principles mentioned earlier lead to the requirements of informed consent, risk/benefit assessment, and the (fair) selection of subjects of research.2 It is important to note that, according to this second understanding, the notion of applied ethics implies a subdivision of normative ethics in (at least) two subbranches, namely pure or theoretical ethics on the one side and applied ethics on the other side. While applied ethics is concerned with the application of principles, pure or theoretical ethics deals with providing such principles. Applied ethics so conceived is, therefore, different from practical ethics which does not necessarily entail any systematic division. Critics of the narrow understanding claim that its commitment to abstract principles or—more generally speaking—to a certain form of ethical theory is too strong and excludes many other accepted methods and approaches. Such critics prefer a notion of applied ethics in the sense of practical ethics that allows for a wide variety of theories and methods. However, as the term “applied” suggests, applied ethics was originally committed to the idea of abstract principles and their applicability to concrete cases. Among others, Kantian ethics provided a basis for this concept of applied ethics. In fact, the division noticeable in Kant’s ethical writings between a Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and a subsequent Metaphysics of Morals presages the division of pure and applied ethics. (cf. Heinrichs, “Kants Angewandte Ethik,” 260-82) However, Kant himself was skeptical regarding the possibility of applied ethics as part of the system of ethics. The nineteeth century Neokantian – 3 – philosopher Hermann Cohen acknowledged in principle that pure ethics needs to be supplemented by applied ethics (see below). Yet, his specific interest was in the pure branch of ethics rather than in the application of principles to concrete moral problems. Moreover, his adherence to the idea of a philosophical system prevented him from elaborating an applied ethics. Nevertheless there is evidence that he presented the idea of a two-tier ethics—pure and applied (in the narrow sense)—to his students. In the early 1870s one of them was the German born American Felix Adler. 2. Felix Adler and his Intellectual Background The leading figure in the emergence of applied ethics has largely been forgotten today: Felix Adler.3 Among other places Adler worked at Columbia University, where for a time he was a contemporary of John Dewey in the Department of Philosophy.4 In 1924 he was even elected president of the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association. (Friess, Felix Adler, 220) Compared to his limited academic impact, Adler was more influential in his role as the founder of the Ethical Culture Society, (cf. Radest, Toward Common Ground, 14 ff.; Friess, Felix Adler, 47 ff.; MacKillop, The British Ethical Societies, 38-40) a humanistic movement that originated in New York in 1876 before spreading to several other US cities and later to Europe. (cf. Radest, Toward Common Grund) Lectures on ethical topics given by Adler made up a substantial part of the society’s weekly gatherings. Among the questions he addressed were family relationships, the role of women, child rearing, and social questions that had become increasingly explosive as a result of industrialization. (Friess, Felix Adler, 54) Prior to his work with the Ethical Culture Society, Adler had been influenced in important ways during a stay in Germany. From 1870 to 1873 he studied in Berlin, where among others he heard the Neokantian Hermann Cohen speak and participated – 4 – in a Kant reading group led by him. (Holzhey and Röd, Neukantianismus, Idealismus, Realismus, Phänomenonologie, 42) In the introduction to his book An Ethical Philosophy of Life Adler explicitly refers to Cohen as “my teacher in philosophy.” (Adler, An Ethical Philosophy of Life, 11) One can thus presume that Cohen influenced his thinking, specifically with respect to the idea of an applied ethics. In his 1877 book Kants Begründung der Ethik (Kant’s foundations of ethics) Cohen explicitly took up the systematic division of the field into pure and applied branches that had been inherent in Kant’s work. (Heinrichs, “Kants Angewandte Ethik,” 260-6) While committed to elaborating the foundations of ethics on the basis of reason alone, he also emphasized the “shaping of the human world” and specifically the “ethicization of culture” as “a principal task of ethics.” (Cohen, Kants Begründung der Ethik, 8 [translation by the author]) In this context Cohen speaks expressly of applied ethics: The problem of ethicizing the human world is a task for applied ethics […] And applied ethics will arise out of pure ethics and assert itself. (Ibid., 10 [translation by the author]) Not only in substance, then, but in explicit terms does Cohen’s work contain the idea of an independent branch of ethics that, under the heading of applied ethics, concerns itself with the moral shaping of society. Admittedly he goes no further than these few references, which he in fact significantly modifies in the second edition of Kants Begründung der Ethik from 1910.5 He himself sees his task as lying in the “description and discussion of Kant’s foundations of pure ethics.” (Ibid. [translation by the author]) It is said that on the whole Adler found Cohen’s philosophy “too intellectualist.” (Friess, Felix Adler, 32 and 209) Apparently he did not find any pertinent points of connection between the systems thinking of Neokantianism and his own theoretical reflections and practical initiatives. This would explain why he does not explicitly engage with Cohen anywhere in his work.6 Notwithstanding this reservation, Adler – 5 – may very well have been inspired by Cohen in relation to the notion of applied ethics. Meanwhile, the development of Pragmatism in the United States at this time offered more fertile intellectual ground for this new appraoch. 3. Some Elements of American Pragmatism The term “Pragmatism” has long been well established as a label for a particular current of philosophical thought,7 though it is used to subsume thinkers and theories that are thoroughly different from one another, and in some cases even contradictory.
Recommended publications
  • HUMANISM Religious Practices
    HUMANISM Religious Practices . Required Daily Observances . Required Weekly Observances . Required Occasional Observances/Holy Days Religious Items . Personal Religious Items . Congregate Religious Items . Searches Requirements for Membership . Requirements (Includes Rites of Conversion) . Total Membership Medical Prohibitions Dietary Standards Burial Rituals . Death . Autopsies . Mourning Practices Sacred Writings Organizational Structure . Headquarters Location . Contact Office/Person History Theology 1 Religious Practices Required Daily Observance No required daily observances. Required Weekly Observance No required weekly observances, but many Humanists find fulfillment in congregating with other Humanists on a weekly basis (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) or other regular basis for social and intellectual engagement, discussions, book talks, lectures, and similar activities. Required Occasional Observances No required occasional observances, but some Humanists (especially those who characterize themselves as Religious Humanists) celebrate life-cycle events with baby naming, coming of age, and marriage ceremonies as well as memorial services. Even though there are no required observances, there are several days throughout the calendar year that many Humanists consider holidays. They include (but are not limited to) the following: February 12. Darwin Day: This marks the birthday of Charles Darwin, whose research and findings in the field of biology, particularly his theory of evolution by natural selection, represent a breakthrough in human knowledge that Humanists celebrate. First Thursday in May. National Day of Reason: This day acknowledges the importance of reason, as opposed to blind faith, as the best method for determining valid conclusions. June 21 - Summer Solstice. This day is also known as World Humanist Day and is a celebration of the longest day of the year.
    [Show full text]
  • American Jewish History a Qijilrteriy P11bllcatlon of the Amerloan J.Ewlsh Hlstorloal Society
    American Jewish History A QIJilrteriY P11bllcatlon of the Amerloan J.ewlsh Hlstorloal SOciety Two Jewish Lawyers Named Lollis* JONATHAN D. SARNA The year r856 was a vintage year for brilliant Jewish lawyers named Louis. On November 13, r8s6, Louis Brandeis was born in Louisville, Kentucky. One month later, on December 14, r856, Louis Marshall was born in Syracuse, New York. Louis and Louis were both first-generation Americans, born of central European Jewish parents. They both compiled stellar academic records. They both went on to have a profound affect on American law. Both were considered for seats on the U.S. Supreme Court, although only one of them made it.' And both became eminent leaders in American Jewish life. Yet while both men earned enormous respect within the Jewish and general communities, they never became friends and rarely worked to­ gether. They differed religiously, philosophically, and politically. They approached Judaism, America, and even the law itself from sharply different perspectives. The parents of Louis Brandeis and Louis Marshall arrived in America at approximately the same time in the middle of the nineteenth century.' Brandeis' parents hailed from Prague, Marshall's father from Baden and his mother from Wiimemberg. The two fathers had experienced prejudice and privation in central Europe that precipitated their emigration. Adolph Brandeis, who grew up in an urban area and studied at the Technical ,. An earlier version of this paper was delivered as the 1006 B. G. Rudolph Lecture in Judaic Studies at Syracuse University, commemorating the rsorh anniversary of the birth of Louis Marshall. I am grateful to Syracuse University for permitting me to publish the lecture here.
    [Show full text]
  • What's It Going to Cost
    IS “THE ETHICIST” THE ANSWER? Gary B. Anderson, M.D. ETHICS ◼ The application of moral principles to everyday situations. A system to guide action based on judgement which respects the rights of others and that is separate from religious orthodoxy. “The Ethicist” ◼ A “New York Times” writer (Randy Cohen), who from 1999 to 2011 wrote a weekly column for the “Times Magazine”. ◼ His most famous achievement however was inventing David Letterman’s “Top Ten List.” Is it ethical? ◼ To submit the same report twice in two different situations? • Does it harm anyone? • Does this gain unfair advantage? • Does this garner an unjustified reward? ◼ Does this action violate any rules? • This is a pragmatic or legal, not ethical consideration. The ethicists answer: ◼ Yes. ◼ There is no harm to others. ◼ It is your own work to use as you choose. ◼ You may get expelled. Is it ethical? ◼ To move to a better seat at a Thunder game? • Does it harm anyone? • Does this gain unfair advantage? • Does this garner an unjustified reward? ◼ Does this action violate any rules? • This is a pragmatic or legal, not ethical consideration. The ethicists answer: ◼ Yes. ◼ There is no harm to other fans. ◼ It is wasteful to let the seats go unused. ◼ The team is a local monopoly, so you have no other alternative venue to choose. Is it ethical? ◼ To buy an obviously (accidently) mispriced item? • Does it harm anyone? • Does this gain unfair advantage? • Does this garner an unjustified reward? ◼ Does this action violate any rules? • This is a pragmatic or legal, not ethical consideration.
    [Show full text]
  • From Reform Judaism to Ethical Culture
    THE AMERICAN ISRAELITE November 15, 1979 ,.;; 'tiM SHe .' _. '. - ;- ~ . - ~ - ~.-i~{--~~,Af #~~'¥#~~!~~~r~a"D7" '!f!!~!: ~es~v~t~er ~S ·e~~~!~~~··. ~. }<::~~:t£ Benny Kraut,. "Fmm, Reform Any list .. of American Social FE!lix Adler's influefiOOnEMtr.h~· '.. Judaism toE.hicaIOulture: The Gospel thinkers should rank 1')1[11 less lQPrns.lar:9~JI:1.. {AtrteriCan ReUglous EvoluHQ'n of. Felix near the top .. He contr-ibuted to~ewiSh)ife.l.,8.t" . .... rabbis, Adler." An L Edward Kiev Library the movement which rejected theimbuedwHti a (Japtb... social Foundation Book. Hebrew· Union deterministic philosophy of SIJC- . COlliclousnessb8relyik~n in O.ollege Press; f979(285pp. ial Darwinism, and insisted In- earlier days, freel)L~mlttedthat . $16 ..50. '.. stead. that man could create a Adler was realty theIT.mentor-in better, highly ethical future. His 'ethics If not inJeligion; "He comes as near to being, a influence on. American religion ,"I turned to him for guidance, saint as iUs possible for a human was both indomitably powerful_ for spiritual guidance and for being to do. He is So good that a and durablyperrnanent. moral help, "Rabbi Stephen Wise ',.,c great many people regard him as In his' new book, "From Reform admittefl aft~rAdler died., Wise eccentric.... YolJ coulQhardly be-JudaismtoEthical Culture: The viewed Adledls the "one prop he-. lieve meifl were to repeat to you Religious Evolution of Felix tic Jewish VOice" in New York all the bad names he has . been Adler," Of. Benny Kraut, associ- City. , c~Uad. Crank, 'hypocrite,pharj- at~ professor and directorot'the In his later years,Adlerfrequen~ see, infidel-everything hisene- Jewish Studies Program at the :",tly denied that he was a Jew.
    [Show full text]
  • UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Previously Published Works
    UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Previously Published Works Title Secularism, Humanism, and Secular Humanism: Terms and Institutions Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5023z45w Author Blankholm, Joseph Publication Date 2016 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Joseph Blankholm Department of Religious Studies University of California, Santa Barbara Secularism, Humanism, and Secular Humanism: Terms and Institutions Abstract: This chapter considers recent American attempts to recognize secular humanism as a religion in light of more than a century of debates over the religiosity of secularism and humanism. It offers a history of these terms’ codependent evolution in the United States by focusing on the individuals, groups, and institutions that have adopted them and shaped their meanings. The chapter also argues that those who use these terms today bear forth a fraught and sometimes self-contradicting inheritance. In order to recognize the stakes of contemporary struggles over the meaning and purpose of secularism, one needs a deeper understanding of how the term has come to bear its traces and how it fits within a shifting constellation of labels and concepts. Keywords: Secularism, Humanism, Secular Humanism, Organized Nonbelievers, Secular Activism, Separation of Church and State In October of 2014, a federal district judge in the state of Oregon ruled that secular humanism is a religion, at least for legal purposes involving the Establishment Clause of the U.S. Constitution’s First Amendment. The judge sided with the lawsuits’ plaintiffs, who argued that a humanist inmate at a federal prison should receive certain rights reserved solely for religious groups.
    [Show full text]
  • The Jewish Advance
    of the loose dvr The Jewish Advance. animal hoax paper found light how little we have to rely on our eellence, has just published Catal-oy to in dvr something inquire about, but did not reformers. What the pen and the argu- Ihbrolschen Handschn/tvn 84 & 86 FIFTH AVENUE. zu (Ham- find the right person of whom to inquire, ment could not do, this event did, and, Stadthibliotlu'k Hambnnj 220 After and the absurd to the of a man to whom we burg, 1878, XX, and pages). Terms of Subscription: penitential day” theory, quote words at the Ham- of which Judaism is as as the Royal Library Munich, Per annum. $3.00 innocent eitil- indeed look up as to a master of Jewish contains the richest col- For .. burg Library six months. 1.30 er of the parties concerned in the mar- learning and principles: Single Copies.10 lection of Hebrew manuscripts in all riage, sprang into existence. The "de- Man weiß in der That nicht, worüber Kates of Advertisi.no : ) Germany. It enumerates and describes fection,” therefore, lies with neither of man über die One line Nompareil, one insertion,.$ .15 j mehr staune-n soll, gemeine 855 volumes. But almost every one of 1 month the prominent Jewish but (4 insert.).. .50 ministers, oder die große »Jgnoranz, die in these volumes contains four, five, and 3 months, (13 insert.) 1.00 wi th the HI m jBosheit -press. very private affair ust das some even ten and more various manu- 12 (52 insert.) 3.00 HAmerika so frech Haupt erhebt.
    [Show full text]
  • Felix Adler's Campaign for Social Justice in the Progressive
    “Let Our Little People Go Free:” Felix Adler’s Campaign for Social Justice in the Progressive Era Esther Lifshitz Senior Thesis HIST C4399 Department of History, Columbia University April 12, 2010 Lifshitz ii Acknowledgments This thesis benefited from the talent, wisdom, and dedication of many who merit mention. I would like to thank the wonderful librarians and staff at Columbia University’s libraries, particularly the archivists at the Rare Book and Manuscript Library for all their assistance. I am also sincerely grateful to the Leaders and affiliates of the New York Society for Ethical Culture, namely, Dr. Anne Klaeysen, Dr. Howard B. Radest, and Dr. Marc Bernstein, who were always gracious with their time and supportive of my research. The intelligence and passion of my history professors have inspired my outlook on history. While they did not contribute directly to this thesis, Professor Alan Brinkley and PhD student Alexander Kaye warrant mention for their influence on the development of my scholarship. This applies as well to professors Eric Foner and Casey Blake, who deserve special thanks for the generous time and advice they gave to this thesis. I must pay tribute to Professor Steven Mintz, my teacher for two semesters, advisor for the past two years, and second reader for this thesis. Professor Mintz was forever encouraging, considerate, and constructive; his patience and guidance were invaluable not only to this thesis but to my academic career. Among the many debts I owe to Professor Mintz, his classes shaped my approach to historical study. Professor Mintz is both an exceptional teacher and human being.
    [Show full text]
  • Fifty Years of History: the Ethical Humanist Society of Long Island
    Fifty Years of History: The Ethical Humanist Society of Long Island Introduction * In The Beginning: A brief retrospective of the Ethical Movement in the United States to the beginnings of the Ethical Humanist Society of Long Island. * 1950s – America Grows Up – Bricks And Ideas, The Ethical Culture Movement Comes To Long Island: We have built well. We have found that there is a strong need for an Ethical Society on Long Island, and we know that there is opportunity ahead of us. We see Long Island growing bigger and we want to help it grow better. We think we can do this by making our Meeting House that in spirit as well as name -- –a place where men meet to seek the highest together. -- –Sheldon Ackley, Leader 1950 -1959, Ethical Culture Society of Long Island * 1960s – Innocence Lost – Beginning The Battle: Today, when democracy is more aware how vast is its program of unfinished business, the call to increase the knowledge, the love, the practice of the best human relationships is still, we believe, the call to take part in the sublimest and most needed of [people's] endeavors. Responding to it by lives which add their gift, howsoever small, to the world's treasure of good and lovable living, lives which reanimate in others hope, trust, courage to keep moving ahead, can give people their most rewarding satisfaction and their truest title to the name human. -- –Henry Neumann, Leader, Brooklyn Society for Ethical Culture * 1970s – America At The Doorstep Of Self- DesctructionDesctructionDesctructionDestruction – A Light In The Dark: Nature is a source of strength.
    [Show full text]
  • „Modernity” in Education Around 1900*)
    1 Jürgen Oelkers „Modernity” in Education around 1900*) In 1876 Harper & Brothers of New York published an anthology entitled The First Century of the Republic. The subtitle read: „A Review of American Progress.” The editor was the publicist Theodore Dwight Woolsey,1 president of Yale University for many years and educated in Germany as a classical philologist. The publication’s title was also its agenda; it sought to review the first one hundred years of the first modern republic. This represented an opportunity that was too good for any publisher to miss, especially this one.2 James and John Harper established their publishing house in 1817 and their first book was John Locke’s Essay on Human Understanding. Not only is it a bold title, but many aspects of the book on the American progress are unusual. It does not open with a preface by the editor, but with a note entitled „publishers’ advertisement.” The note is not signed in the name of the Harper brothers, but with a reference to the publisher’s office, „Franklin Square, New York.” The editor, Woolsey, is not identified as such; his name simply appears as the first in the list of contributors on the frontispiece. His role as editor has thus been assumed.3 The individual pages of the book are printed in two columns of closely spaced lines; the volume appears very dense and contains 506 pages, which does not suggest an easy reading. In their introductory note, the Harper brothers wrote that the book was intended as a national „supplement” to the International Exhibition in Philadelphia.
    [Show full text]
  • Inside This Issue Negotiating Your Rights As an Author Research
    Vol. 14, No 2 October/November 2004 Negotiating Your Rights as an Author Research Impact of Open Access Articles Some publishers now offer author-friendly copyright A recent study found that articles freely available on the agreements that allow authors to retain rights to their Web have greater research impact as measured by the works to use in teaching or future scholarly efforts. degree to which they are cited. Kristin Antelman, North This easing of exclusive copyright transfer requirements Carolina State University, looked at articles from is due in large measure to the growing open access philosophy, political science, electrical and electronic movement, which is defined as free and unrestricted engineering, and mathematics. Each of these disciplines online availability to journal articles. was deemed to be in varying stages of adopting open access. Even the mega-publisher Elsevier has revised the Articles from ten high-impact journals in each field for a copyright agreement authors are asked to sign. two-year period formed the sample. The citedness of each Copyright information provided at their “Author article was determined using the ISI Citation Indexes. Each Gateway” (http://www.authors.elsevier.com/) indicates article was then searched on the Web using the Google that authors will maintain rights for personal use search engine, which now indexes the full-text of PDF files including teaching, posting pre-print and final versions and some PostScript files in addition to html pages. of articles on their personal or institutional websites For each of the disciplines, articles in the open access with a link to the journal home page, presenting the sample had higher citation counts than those only available work at meetings, and preparing derivative works.
    [Show full text]
  • An Ethical Philosophy of Life Presented in Its Main Outlines Books by Felix Adler
    This is a reproduction of a library book that was digitized by Google as part of an ongoing effort to preserve the information in books and make it universally accessible. http://books.google.com FROM THE BEQUEST OF JAMES WALKER (Class of 1814) President oj Harvard College "Preference being given to works in the Intellectual and Moral Sciences " nammammrf AN ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY OF LIFE PRESENTED IN ITS MAIN OUTLINES BOOKS BY FELIX ADLER An Ethical Philosophy of Life The World CrUU and Its Meaning Marriage and Divorce Life and Destiny The Religion of Duty The Moral Instruction of Children IM AN ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY OF LIFE PRESENTED IN ITS MAIN OUTLINES BY FELIX ADLER D. APPLETON AND COMPANY NEW YORK LONDON 1918 ( MAY 221910 ) COPTRIOBT, 1918, BT D. APPLETON AND COMPANY Printed in the United States of America PREFACE This book records a philosophy of life growing out of the experience of a lifetime. The convictions put in it are not dog matic, for dogma is the conviction of one man imposed author itatively upon others. The convictions herein expounded are submitted to those who search, as the writer has searched, for light on the problems of life, in order that they may compare their experience with his, and their interpretations of their ex perience with his interpretation.1 It is a great hope that some of the readers of this book may find the general world-view expounded congenial, and for them also real and true. It is believed that others may find the practical suggestions as to the conduct of life in which the theory issues helpful in part, if not in whole, as many of us accept from the teachings of the Stoics, or of other thinkers, practical precepts, without on that account adopting the philosophy from which these precepts are derived.
    [Show full text]
  • Oppenheimer, Bethe, and the Moral Against Unsupported Attacks (Attacks Responsibility of the Scientist
    Current Books essays. Had Singer reshaped some of the Study in Princeton, New Jersey, while essays and put a bit more effort into harmo- Bethe returned to Cornell University, his nizing the others, the result would have intellectual home since 1935 and a scholarly been a far better book. But one should still be community that would give him moral sup- grateful for the intelligence and judiciousness port. of the book we do have. One should “It is one of Bethe’s striking characteris- acknowledge, too, that writers who have the tics,” writes Schweber, a physicist and science temerity to write about Santayana are historian at Brandeis University, “that there doomed to be outshone by their subject. We is only one of him—in contrast to Oppen- can be grateful to Singer for showing just heimer.” When Cold War anticommunism such temerity, and thereby helping to keep struck American college campuses in the Santayana’s vision alive. 1940s and 1950s, a duplicitous Oppen- —Wilfred M. McClay heimer so feared his conservative critics that he could not bring himself to defend publicly a former student, University of IN THE SHADOW OF THE BOMB: Rochester physics professor Bernard Peters, Oppenheimer, Bethe, and the Moral against unsupported attacks (attacks Responsibility of the Scientist. prompted by Oppenheimer’s own casual By S. S. Schweber. Princeton Univ. remarks). By contrast, Bethe staunchly Press. 260 pp. $24.95 defended Cornell physicist Philip Morrison against biased accusations by the university’s o understand the overlapping but alumni and board members. President Tdivergent careers of nuclear physi- Dwight Eisenhower’s science adviser, cists J.
    [Show full text]