Topicalization, Scrambling, and Argument Scope in German: Integrating Semantic and Syntactic Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Topicalization, Scrambling, and Argument Scope in German: Integrating Semantic and Syntactic Information Journal oj Semantics 11:311-363 © N.I.S. Foundation (1994) Topicalization, Scrambling, and Argument Scope in German: Integrating Semantic and Syntactic Information ANATOLI STRIGIN Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jos/article/11/4/311/1640111 by guest on 01 October 2021 Max-Planck Research Group 'Structural Grammar', Berlin Abstract The paper proposes an explanation of some argument scope phenomena in German in terms of interaction of syntactic and semantic information. On the assumption that lexical semantics of a verb induces a hierarchical ordering on its arguments, it is proposed that this hierarchy together with the mapping of the hierarchy to syntactic structure define a basic scope con- figuration. The mapping is controlled both by syntactic and by semantic information. Another hypothesis proposes that changes in the syntactic structure caused by topicalization and scrambling extend the mapping by assigning a specific role to the traces of the moved DPs. The traces can either have the semantic type of DPs or the type of individuals. This typing ambiguity yields two options: either the DP is semantically reconstructed into its original argument position, or the domain of the mapping of verbal arguments is extended. The options correspond to the narrow and the wide scopes of an argument, scope being expressed at the level of Discourse Representation Structures. This treatment of German facts is more restrictive than the ones based on Cooper storage, Logical Form, or Flexible Type Assignment, o INTRODUCTION: SCOPE ASSIGNMENT AT THE LEVEL OF SEMANTIC FORM o. 1 A brief review of the subject matter The phenomenon of scope in natural language as it is understood in this paper is due to dependencies between mental constructs—semantic representations. The dependencies which are of interest in this sense reflect dependencies of verifiability conditions for representations corresponding to propositional structures. In other words, they define what may be called truth-conditional scope. The main aim of the paper is to provide a technical outline of a theory of how argument scope is computed in this framework for a small fragment of German. An argument in the context of this paper is simply a determiner phrase (DP) which is assigned a 0-role by some syntactic constituent. The term argument scope refers to the dependencies in propositional representations introduced by arguments; that is to say, in the case, of some first order sentence of the form predicate (a, b) with two individual constants a and b, possible 312 Topicalizarion, Scrambling, and Argument Scope in German interpretations of b can be required to depend on those of a inasmuch as any mapping of [a, b) to a model which is allowed to vary in letting b denote different individuals must observe some fixed interpretation of a, but a can vary irrespective of b, e.g. if it is required that for every embedding/ of a into some model M there must be an embedding £ oft into M with the additional requirement that£ should agree with/wrt. a. I take this to be the core case of argument scope, and the question usually asked in this connection is which Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jos/article/11/4/311/1640111 by guest on 01 October 2021 factors determine it. There are a number of treatments of argument scope, both in model theoretic semantics, e.g. Cooper (1983), Hendriks (1990), and in representa- tional theories, e.g. May (1977, 1985). There is also a recent proposal in the framework of Discourse Representation Theory, DRT, by Reyle (1993); Frank & Reyle (1992). This introduction is devoted to motivating yet another attempt to formulate mechanisms and principles of argument scope assignment. Since both semantic means and syntactic factors of scope assignment are reasonably well understood, the emphasis of any such attempt should be on the ways these two aspects are interrelated. To explain where exactly the emphasis of the present proposal lies, I will start by briefly reviewing some theories, beginning with the representational theory which has the widest currency: May's theory of scope determination at the level of Logical Form with the rule of Quantifier Raising (May 1977, 1985, 1991). According to May (1991), any language has its logical form—the representa- tion of the form of the logical terms of a language. May characterizes logical terms as those expressions of the language which have, in some sense, invariant meanings. Their fixed meanings (i.e. those aspects of their meanings which are not lexical) arise from their being interpreted by general semantic rules. Thus, the rules for quantifiers have pattern-matching preconditions for their applica- tion which require the distinction between a sentence and a sentential function. This requires, in turn, that the mechanisms of interpretation be able to dis- tinguish free occurrences of variables from bound occurrences, hence the notion of binding. Binding requires the notion of scope, so scope in the sense of May is the domain of binding. A logical form is then a representation of those formal properties which are required to ensure proper application of the general semantic rules. A level of linguistic representation will be (a representa- tion of) logical form only if it manifests these properties. May argues that there is a syntactic level of representation, LF, and his central claim, an empirical discovery, is that the part of the grammar which deals with the syntax provides enough structure at LF for general semantic rules to use in the truth definition. This makes introduction of any other representational means for the purpose superfluous. Argument scope is defined at LF by the c-command configuration of syntactic representations of arguments arising after the application of the rule of Quantifier Raising (QR), which is a particular instance of the syntactic Anatoli Strigin 313 rule known as 'move a'. The configuration of c-command between arguments is claimed to provide enough information for the application of the recursive rules. Thus the sentence Everyone admires someone is claimed to be scope ambiguous due to the fact that (i) (1) [s someone; [s everyonej [s e-t admires ?;]]] is a structure of symmetrical c-command between the two quantified deter- Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jos/article/11/4/311/1640111 by guest on 01 October 2021 miner phrases someone and everyone which permits different orderings of the iterative application of the semantic quantifier clauses. Both DPs have been moved from their respective positions by the rule QR, and adjoined to an S node (bracketed expressions are used to denote uninterpreted syntactic structures). Note that binding here is effected by syntactic constituents. Similarly, domains of binding, as well as sentential functions and free variables, are syntactically defined. If, however, Logical Form is equipped with ^.-abstraction, and semantic types as in Williams (1977) (I am not quite sure about Williams 1986), I prefer to consider these proposals at a level of semantic representation rather than at a purely syntactic level which is subject to semantic constraints. In other words, I consider semantically motivated types of expression and the presence of a semantic binding operation (like ^.-abstraction or some equivalent of it) to be jointly characteristic of a semantic rather than a syntactic level of representation, though inasmuch as the word 'semantic' does not refer to any object of a non-representational character in this context, some researchers see it as more appropriate to consider any such representation level as syntax. There are arguments against the syntactic level of LF (see Berman & Hestvik 1991 for a recent critical survey of arguments for and against LF). In particular, it was claimed that the rule QR is not the right device to produce the relevant configurations. For example, QR presumably also predicts scope ambiguities in (2) many cellists played few variations which it does not seem to show. Such behaviour is typical of quantified DPs based on determiners which differ in their logical properties from someone or everyone. LF is too permissive here. Furthermore, some authors (e.g. Frey 1993) have argued that argument scope in German is implicitly represented at S-structure (see also Diesing 1992), and claimed that LF predictions for German are incorrect in a number of cases. The qualification 'implicitly' indicates that relative scope of quantifiers must be calculated from S-structure in German, and is not described by a simple pattern. Inasmuch as this claim is supported, the role of LF as a language-inde- pendent level of representation is dubious. The work of Frey will be reviewed in more detail later. 314 Topicalization, Scrambling, and Argument Scope in German Objections against QR, and against LF, in general stimulated the search for alternative means to represent relative scope of quantified DPs. One of the best known is the device of quantifier storage (Cooper 1983), which is a purely semantic means of dealing with the problem. Purely semantic here is meant to characterize any approach which assumes no special level of representation for scope, no syntactic ambiguity to reflect scope ambiguity, and in general no constraining influence of syntax on scope configuration over and above provid- Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jos/article/11/4/311/1640111 by guest on 01 October 2021 ing some constituent structure, but which tries to manipulate model theoretic constructs. The version developed in Cherchia (1988) makes provisions for some syntactic constraints. It should be noted that quantifier storage produces an impression of being not quite as explanatory as Logical Form. The following illustration is the one adapted from Chierchia (1988). The essence of Cooper's technique is a discontinuous operation of variable binding using a special information structure which stores interpretations of quantified phrases and their binding indices.
Recommended publications
  • Syncom.Sluicing
    SynCom Case 98 Sluicing Jason Merchant University of Chicago August 2003 Contents 1. Introduction 2. Movement vs. non-movement approaches 3. Theoretical consequences 3.1. Non-movement approaches 3.2. Movement approaches 4. Puzzles and prospects 4.1. Sluicing-COMP generalization puzzles 4.2. Sluicing in non-wh-in-specCP languages 4.3. Multiple sluicing 4.4. Swiping 5. Conclusion References Glossary 1. Introduction Sluicing is the ellipsis phenomenon illustrated in (1), in which the sentential portion of a constituent question is elided, leaving only a wh-phrase remnant. (1) a. Jack bought something, but I don’t know what. b. A: Someone called. B: Really? Who? c. Beth was there, but you’ll never guess who else. d. Jack called, but I don’t know {when/how/why/where from}. e. Sally’s out hunting — guess what! f. A car is parked on the lawn — find out whose. The sluices in (1) should be compared to their non-elliptical counterparts in (2), with which they are synonymous. (2) a. Jack bought something, but I don’t know what he bought. b. A: Someone called. B: Really? Who called? c. Beth was there, but you’ll never guess who else was there. d. Jack called, but I don’t know {when/how/why} he called. e. Sally’s out hunting — guess what she’s out hunting! f. A car is parked on the lawn — find out whose is parked on the lawn. Sluicing appears to be widespread cross-linguistically (unlike VP-ellipsis), and may in fact be found in some form or another in every language (like nominal ellipses, 1 gapping, stripping, and fragment answers).
    [Show full text]
  • Treatment of Multiword Expressions and Compounds in Bulgarian
    Treatment of Multiword Expressions and Compounds in Bulgarian Petya Osenova and Kiril Simov Linguistic Modelling Deparment, IICT-BAS Acad. G. Bonchev 25A, 1113 Sofia, Bulgaria [email protected] and [email protected] Abstract 2012)), we will adopt the Multiword Expressions The paper shows that catena represen- classification, presented in (Sag et al., 2001). They tation together with valence information divide them into two groups: lexicalized phrases can provide a good way of encoding and institutionalized phrases. The former are fur- Multiword Expressions (beyond idioms). ther subdivided into fixed-expressions, semi-fixed It also discusses a strategy for mapping expressions and syntactically-flexible expressions. noun/verb compounds with their counter- Fixed expressions are said to be fully lexicalized part syntactic phrases. The data on Mul- and undergoing neither morphosyntactic variation tiword Expression comes from BulTree- nor internal modification. Semi-fixed expressions Bank, while the data on compounds comes have a fixed word order, but “undergo some degree from a morphological dictionary of Bul- of lexical variation, e.g. in the form of inflection, garian. variation in reflexive form, and determiner selec- tion” (non-decomposable idioms, proper names). 1 Introduction Syntactically-flexible expressions show more vari- Our work is based on the annotation of Multi- ation in their word order (light verb constructions, word Expressions (MWE) in the Bulgarian tree- decomposable idioms). We follow the understand- bank — BulTreeBank (Simov et al., 2004). We ing of (O’Grady, 1998) that MWEs have their in- use this representation for parsing and analysis of ternal syntactic structure which needs to be rep- compounds. BulTreeBank exists in two formats: resented in the lexicon as well as in the sentence HPSG-based (original - constituent-based with analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Scrambling As Case-Driven Obligatory Movement
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons IRCS Technical Reports Series Institute for Research in Cognitive Science April 1993 Scrambling as Case-Driven Obligatory Movement Young-Suk Lee University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports Lee, Young-Suk, "Scrambling as Case-Driven Obligatory Movement" (1993). IRCS Technical Reports Series. 15. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/15 University of Pennsylvania Institute for Research in Cognitive Science Technical Report No. IRCS-93-06 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/ircs_reports/15 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Scrambling as Case-Driven Obligatory Movement Abstract In this thesis I explore the nature and properties of scrambling in Korean. Contrary to the widely accepted view that scrambling is truly optional, I propose that scrambling is a consequence of case-driven obligatory movement, a proposal consistent with the "last resort" condition on movement in [Chomsky 1991] and [Chomsky 1992]. I assume that scrambling is adjunction and defend this view in Ch. 5. In Ch. 2 and Ch. 3 based on binding facts and scope reconstruction, I claim that scrambling is best analyzed as A-movement. Scrambling either creates a binding relation which does not obtain in the base order, or destroys a binding relation which obtains in the base order. A scrambled element undergoes optional reconstruction for scope interpretation. All these properites are consistent with those of standard A-movement. In Ch. 4, I propose that scrambling is a consequence of case-driven movement. On the basis of case and word order possibilities in event nominal clauses, I first establish that in orK ean nominative case is licensed by INFL, and accusative case by a complex category formed by the head raising of VERB-to-INFL.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – a Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1
    Thomas Groß Some Observations on the Hebrew Desiderative Construction – A Dependency-Based Account in Terms of Catenae1 Abstract The Modern Hebrew (MH) desiderative construction must obey four conditions: 1. A subordinate clause headed by the clitic še= ‘that’ must be present. 2. The verb in the subordinate clause must be marked with future tense. 3. The grammatical properties genus, number, and person tend to be specified, i.e. if the future tense affix is underspecified, material tends to appear that aids specification, if contextual recovery is unavailable. 4. The units of form that make up the constructional meaning of the desiderative must qualify as a catena. A catena is a dependency-based unit of form, the parts of which are immediately continuous in the vertical dimension. The description of the individual parts of the desiderative must address trans-, pre-, and suffixes, and cliticization. Catena-based morphology is representational, monostratal, dependency-, construction-, and piece-based. 1. Purpose, means and claims The main purpose of this paper is to analyze the Hebrew desiderative construction. This construction is linguistically interesting and challenging for a number of reasons. 1. It is a periphrastic construction, with fairly transparent compositionality. 2. It is transclausal, i.e. some parts of the construction reside in the main clause, and others in the subordinated clause. The complementizer is also part of the construction. 3. The construction consists of more than one word, but it does not qualify as a constituent. Rather the construction cuts into words. 4. Two theoretically 1 I want to thank Outi Bat-El (Tel Aviv University) and three anonymous reviewers for their help and advice.
    [Show full text]
  • Malagasy Extraposition: Evidence for PF Movement
    Nat Lang Linguist Theory https://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-021-09505-2 Malagasy extraposition Evidence for PF movement Eric Potsdam1 Received: 28 August 2018 / Accepted: 23 January 2021 © The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature B.V. part of Springer Nature 2021 Abstract Extraposition is the non-canonical placement of dependents in a right- peripheral position in a clause. The Austronesian language Malagasy has basic VOXS word order, however, extraposition leads to VOSX. Extraposed constituents behave syntactically as though they were in their undisplaced position inside the predicate at both LF and Spell Out. This paper argues that extraposition is achieved via movement at Phonological Form (PF). I argue against alternatives that would derive extraposi- tion with syntactic A’ movement or stranding analyses. Within a Minimalist model of grammar, movement operations take place on the branch from Spell Out to PF and have only phonological consequences. Keywords Malagasy · Extraposition · Movement · Phonological Form · Word order 1 Introduction Extraposition—the non-canonical placement of certain constituents in a right- peripheral position—has been investigated in detail in only a small number of lan- guages. There is a considerable literature for English, SOV Germanic languages Ger- man and Dutch, and the SOV language Hindi-Urdu. The construction has not been widely explored in other, typologically distinct languages. This lacuna means that we have probably not seen the full range of options and have also not tested pro- posed analyses in the widest possible way. The goal of this paper is to investigate in some detail extraposition in Malagasy, an Austronesian language with basic VOXS word order spoken by approximately 17 million people on the island of Madagascar.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Scrambling Eljko Boškovi£ It Is Uncontroversial That Slavic
    Scrambling ¢ eljko Boškovi £ It is uncontroversial that Slavic languages have topicalization and focalization. It is less clear whether they also have the scrambling operation of the kind found in languages like Japanese and Korean. The goal of this chapter is to address the issue of whether Slavic languages have Japanese-style scrambling (JSS) in addition to topicalization/focalization. I will confine my attention to Russian and Serbo-Croatian (SC), focusing on three properties of JSS which differentiate it from topicalization/focalization, namely the undoing effect (i.e. semantic vacuity of long-distance scrambling), the impossibility of adjunct scrambling, and the absence of relativized minimality effects with scrambling.1 As discussed by a number of authors, long-distance scrambling in Japanese is semantically vacuous (see, e.g., Saito1992, Boškovi £ and Takahashi 1998, Saito and Fukui 1998, Tada 1993), which has led the above-mentioned authors to conclude that Japanese long-distance scrambling is completely undone in LF. Consider (1), involving long-distance scrambling of the embedded object daremo-ni.2 ¥ ¥ ¦ (1) Daremo-ni dareka-ga [Mary-ga e atta to] omotteiru. ¤ > ; * > DAT NOM NOM everyone- someone- Mary- met that thinks ‘Everyone, someone thinks that Mary met.’ (Boškovi § and Takahashi 1998) Daremo-ni in (1) must have narrow scope, i.e. it cannot scope over the matrix clause subject. This fact illustrates semantic vacuity of long-distance scrambling Japanese. In this respect, JSS clearly differs from topicalization and focalization, which do affect scope (see (5) below).3 Another property of Japanese scrambling that differentiates it from topicalization/focalization concerns inability of adjuncts to undergo scrambling, illustrated by Saito’s (1985) examples in (2).4 1A word of caution is in order regarding the term “scrambling”, one of the most abused items in the linguistic vocabulary.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Notes on Scrambling and Object Shift*
    Some Notes on Scrambling and Object Shift* Roland Hinterholz1 1 Introduction Though object shift in Scandinavian and one type of scrambling in West Ger- manic have the same information-structural trigger — discourse-given objects move across adverbs taken to mark the boundary of vP — they differ in a number of re- spects: First, object shift typically applies to weak pronouns and is widely taken to be obligatory (for an opposing view see Josefsson 2003), while scrambling in West Germanic can apply to pronominal DPs, nominai DPs and PP complements alike and is taken to be optional. Second, object shift in Scandinavian, including the shift of nominai DPs in Icelandic, is subject to a minimality condition, while scrambling of German DPs applies freely, thus allowing for any kind of order be- tween the arguments of the verb. Third, object shift may occur only in contexts where the main verb has moved out of the vP ("Holmberg's generalization," cf. Holmberg 1986). Since there is no verb movement in embedded clauses in Main- land Scandinavian, object shift is generally absent in these clauses, as it is missing in main clauses with periphrastic tenses. No such restriction holds for scrambling in West Germanic. Most accounts of these phenomena thus assume that object shift and scram- bling are different operations (e.g. Haider and Rosengren 1998). Such proposals also posit that scrambling and object shift are defined in purely syntactic terms which reflect language-specific restrictions. Hardly any approach argues that there is a unique universal operation of preposing discourse-given objects and relates the *This short contribution is intended to express my gratitude to Valéria Molnar for several won- derful stays in Lund during the last three years and for long and inspiring discussions of both theoretical issues and personal matters on these occasions.
    [Show full text]
  • A-Scrambling Exists!
    University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 6 Issue 1 Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Penn Article 20 Linguistics Colloquium 1999 A-Scrambling Exists! Martha McGinnis Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl Recommended Citation McGinnis, Martha (1999) "A-Scrambling Exists!," University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: Vol. 6 : Iss. 1 , Article 20. Available at: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol6/iss1/20 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol6/iss1/20 For more information, please contact [email protected]. A-Scrambling Exists! This working paper is available in University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol6/iss1/20 A-Scrambling Exists! Martha McGinnis 1 Preliminaries The nature of scrambling is a focus of recent debate in the syntactic literature. The term scrambling is used to describe apparently optional permutations of word order, found especially in languages with extensive case-marking. Saito (1989) argues that scrambling is A-bar movement (like wh-movement), rather than A-movement (like movement to the subject position). Webelhuth (1989) argues for scrambling to positions with mixed A- and A-bar proper- ties, while Mahajan (1990) counters that local (clause-internal) scrambling can be either to an A- or an A-bar position, while long-distance scrambling is A-bar movement. In a recently published paper, Frank, Lee & Rambow (FLR; 1996) take a careful look at different types of evidence for the kind of movement in- volved in scrambling in German and Korean. They conclude that there is no A-scrambling, and that scrambling is actually a special kind of A-bar move- ment that can affect binding relations in some languages.
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Generalized Pied-Piping Sayaka Funakoshi, Doctor Of
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: A Theory of Generalized Pied-Piping Sayaka Funakoshi, Doctor of Philosophy, 2015 Dissertation directed by: Professor Howard Lasnik Department of Linguistics The purpose of this thesis is to construct a theory to derive how pied-piping of formal features of a moved element takes place, by which some syntactic phenomena related to φ-features can be accounted for. Ura (2001) proposes that pied-piping of formal-features of a moved element is constrained by an economy condition like relativized minimality. On the basis of Ura’s (2001) proposal, I propose that how far an element that undergoes movement can carry its formal features, especially focusing on φ-features in this thesis, is determined by two conditions, a locality condition on the generalized pied-piping and an anti-locality condition onmovement. Given the proposed analysis, some patterns of so-called wh-agreement found in Bantu languages can be explained and with the assumption that φ-features play an role for binding, presence or absence of WCO effects in various languages can be derived without recourse to A/A-distinctions.¯ ATHEORYOFGENERALIZEDPIED-PIPING by Sayaka Funakoshi Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Maryland, College Park in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy 2015 Advisory Committee: Professor Howard Lasnik, Chair/Advisor Professor Norbert Hornstein Professor Omer Preminger Professor Steven Ross Professor Juan Uriagereka c Copyright by ! Sayaka Funakoshi 2015 Acknowledgments First and foremost, I would like to thank my advisor Howard Lasnik for his patience, support and encouragement.
    [Show full text]
  • Linearization at PF: Evidence from Malagasy Extraposition
    Linearization at PF: Evidence from Malagasy Extraposition Daniel Edmiston & Eric Potsdam University of Chicago, University of Florida 1. Introduction Within the Y-model of grammar (Chomsky 1995), (1), movement is widely believed to take place on two branches. OVERT MOVEMENT takes place before Spell Out and COVERT MOVEMENT takes place between Spell Out and LF: (1) Y-Model Lexicon overt movement ( Spell Out covert movement ( PF LF Given that movement occurs on two of the three branches, this paper addresses the question of whether movement ever takes places on the third branch, between Spell Out and PF. We will call such movement PHONOLOGICAL/PF MOVEMENT. Precedents in the literature include Japanese prosodic scrambling (Agbayani et al. 2015), extraposition from NP in English (Gobbel¨ 2007), and phenomena in Aoun & Benmamoun 1998 and Sauerland & Elbourne 2002. The goal of this paper is to argue for another instance of phonological movement, extraposition of CPs in the Austronesian language Malagasy.1 Basic word order in Malagasy is VOS, with direct objects obligatorily occurring be- fore the clause-final subject, (2). An exception to this generalization is clausal objects, which cannot appear before the subject but must extrapose and appear after the subject, (3) (Keenan 1976). We will use the label CP EXTRAPOSITION (CPEX) as a theory-neutral term to describe the right-peripheral placement of such clauses. 1Law 2007 first proposed that extraposition in Malagasy is PF movement. See Potsdam & Edmiston 2015 for further discussion. Edmiston & Potsdam (2) Nividy (fiara vaovao) Rabe (*fiara vaovao) PAST.buy car new Rabe car new ‘Rabe bought a new car.’ (3) Manantena (*fa hividy fiara aho) Rabe (fa hividy fiara aho) hope that FUT.buy car 1SG.NOM Rabe that FUT.buy car 1SG.NOM ‘Rabe hopes that I will buy a car.’ Our proposal is that CPEX is PF movement.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Scrambling Anti-Movement Movement *
    Against the Scrambling anti-Movement Movement* John Frederick Bailyn Stony Brook University 1. Introduction: Free Word Order and Scrambling This article argues against two recent non-movement accounts of free word order in Russian – van Gelderen (2003) (hereafter VG) and Bo!kovi" (2004) (hereafter B) and in favor of Scrambling-as- Movement. Both VG and B claim (a) that the (re)ordering of major constituents in Russian results from a process that is not movement, and (b) that (most) Russian (re)orderings result from a process distinct from that of Japanese. In sections 2 and 3 of this article I present the VG and B approaches and argue against them. In the final section, I argue that Japanese and Russian do not differ in the manner described by either author, and that a unified discourse- driven account of Scrambling as Last Resort movement is both theoretically more desirable and empirically more successful. The issue at hand is the proper account of alternative word orders for identical major constituents in so-called “free” word order languages. Typical cases are given in (1) (local) and (2) (long- distance) for Japanese and (3) for Russian (the bold element is the constituent separated from canonical (thematic) position): (1) a. Mary-ga sono hon-o yonda (Japanese) MaryNOM that bookACC read ‘Mary read that book.’ b. sono hon-o Mary-ga ___ yonda that bookACC MaryNOM read ‘That book Mary read ___ .’ (2) sono hon-o John-ga [ Mary-ga ___ katta to] itta] that book JohnNOM MaryNOM bought that thinks ‘That book John thinks that Mary bought ___ .’ *Ideas in this article have been presented at Utrecht, Tilburg and Yale Universities, and in seminars in St.
    [Show full text]
  • On Object Shift, Scrambling, and the PIC
    On Object Shift, Scrambling, and the PIC Peter Svenonius University of Tromsø and MIT* 1. A Class of Movements The displacements characterized in (1-2) have received a great deal of attention. (Boldface in the gloss here is simply to highlight the alternation.) (1) Scrambling (exx. from Bergsland 1997: 154) a. ... gan nagaan slukax igaaxtakum (Aleut) his.boat out.of seagull.ABS flew ‘... a seagull flew out of his boat’ b. ... quganax hlagan kugan husaqaa rock.ABS his.son on.top.of fell ‘... a rock fell on top of his son’1 (2) Object Shift (OS) a. Hann sendi sem betur fer bréfi ni ur. (Icelandic) he sent as better goes the.letter down2 b. Hann sendi bréfi sem betur fer ni ur. he sent the.letter as better goes down (Both:) ‘He fortunately sent the letter down’ * I am grateful to the University of Tromsø Faculty of Humanities for giving me leave to traipse the globe on the strength of the promise that I would write some papers, and to the MIT Department of Linguistics & Philosophy for welcoming me to breathe in their intellectually stimulating atmosphere. I would especially like to thank Noam Chomsky, Norvin Richards, and Juan Uriagereka for discussing parts of this work with me while it was underway, without implying their endorsement. Thanks also to Kleanthes Grohmann and Ora Matushansky for valuable feedback on earlier drafts, and to Ora Matushansky and Elena Guerzoni for their beneficient editorship. 1 According to Bergsland (pp. 151-153), a subject preceding an adjunct tends to be interpreted as definite (making (1b) unusual), and one following an adjunct tends to be indefinite; this is broadly consistent with the effects of scrambling cross-linguistically.
    [Show full text]