The Metatheory of First-Order Logic: a Contribution to a Defence Of

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Metatheory of First-Order Logic: a Contribution to a Defence Of The metatheory of first-order logic: a contribution to a defence of Principia Mathematica Stephen Boyce University of Sydney 29 November 2010 Abstract This paper presents an account of the first-order logic of Principia Mathematica and evidence that the system is superior to currently accepted classical rivals. A widely accepted view that Whitehead and Russell’s presentation of logic in Principia is essentially defective in departing from contemporary standards is considered. It is shown that the judgement is based on a number of arguments that do not withstand critical scrutiny. For example, the assumption that the metatheory of contemporary first-order logic may be made precise in the expected way (using a first-order set theory equivalent to NBG) is shown to be false; on pain of contradiction, there cannot exist any such domain of interpretation of NBG. An alternative view of first- order logic, derived from Principia, is then presented. It is shown that Principia avoids the problem just discussed, as the first-order fragment may be made precise under an interpretation of the full sys- tem. arXiv:1003.4483v5 [math.LO] 28 Nov 2010 1 Is there a logic of Principia? My primary aim in the following is to sketch an account of the first-order logic of Principia Mathematica. I begin by considering the claim that the Whitehead-Russell presentation is flawed in so far as modern standards for the characterisation of a system of logic are not adhered to; hence to recover a system of logic from Principia it is essential to consider a revised system that adheres to contemporary standards must be developed. I challenge this claim 1 below (§2.1) by sketching a proof that the metatheory of modern first-order logic cannot be made precise in the generally expected way; more precisely, I show that (Proposition 2.1) there is no interpretation of NBG set theory that expresses the metatheory of Mendelson’s pure predicate calculus PP ([23]) . In §2.1 I focus on a standard presentation of a contemporary first-order logic, rather than a modern reconstruction of the first-order fragment of Principia, in order to support the claim that the Whitehead-Russell account of first-order logic ought to be considered on its merit. As the Whitehead- Russell account has been dismissed by many highly regarded authors (§2) it is necessary to present evidence in support of this claim. Having presented such evidence, I then (§3) examine the Whitehead-Russell version of first- order logic. I focus on the question of how to make Principia’s notions of a proposition / propositional functions precise - as a widely accepted objection to Principia holds that some confusion (perhaps involving sloppiness about the use/mention distinction) is intrinsic to the Whitehead-Russell account (cf [26], [3]: 56, [18]: 259). The slogan version of my account is that the logic of Principia is a logic of propositional functions, the latter being neither open sentences nor the ’meanings’ attached to these under some interpretation(s) but rather a combination of the two. In §5 I sketch an extension of this account to the full system of Principia. For brevity throughout the following various well-known distinctions con- cerning formal systems are blurred where no confusion should result. For example, it is convenient in many contexts to speak of the symbols of a for- mal system when it is really instances of the symbols that are mentioned; similarly, it is often convenient to refer to the meaning of a sentence and so on, when it is really the meaning of the sentence in a specific context that is referred to. As such distinctions are well-known in the literature and noth- ing essential rides on them in what follows I will make no further mention of them herein. 2 The formalist drive-by In this section I wish to consider the following claim (hereon ’the formalist drive-by’): to recover a system of logic from Principia it is essential to aban- don the Whitehead-Russell presentation and construct an alternative system that adheres to contemporary standards. Urquhart, in describing the type theory of Principia, explicitly asserts this claim: ... it is better to abandon the original Whitehead-Russell pre- sentation of the ramified theory of types and to follow a modern 2 presentation. The original presentation in Principia Mathemat- ica is both imprecise and notationally clumsy. Above all, the original formulation is unsatisfactory because there is no precise presentation of the syntax of the system. [29]: 295 The formalist drive-by is asserted implicitly by some authors. G¨odel, for example, to establish his famous incompleteness theorems concerning systems such as Principia, explicitly examines the formalist system P rather than the system of logic that Whitehead and Russell actually present in Principia. G¨odel is keen in [11] to establish that the exhibited proof catches the system of Principia itself; not surprisingly therefore the differences between the two systems are asserted to be of no essential import: P is essentially the system obtained when the logic of PM is superposed upon the Peano axioms ... The introduction of the Peano axioms, as well as all other modifications introduced in the system PM, merely serves to simplify the proof and is dispensable in principle. [11]: 599 That G¨odel actually judged the formalist reconstruction of, for example, Principia’s inference rules to be an essential correction to the Whitehead- Russell presentation is however made clear elsewhere. In characterising Prin- cipia’s place within the development of logic more generally G¨odel states: It is to be regretted that this first comprehensive and thorough- going presentation of a mathematical logic and the derivation of mathematics from it [is] so greatly lacking in formal precision in the foundations (contained in *1 - *21 of Principia) that it presents in this respect a considerable step backwards as com- pared with Frege. What is missing, above all, is a precise state- ment of the syntax of the formalism. ([12]: 120, modified through interpolation ’[]’) G¨odel’s considered position is thus that to extract a system of logic from Principia the Whitehead-Russell presentation must be modified so that a sys- tem with a precisely characterised, formal syntax (and so on) is described. When implicit and explicit assertions of the formalist drive-by are grouped together, it is clear that this claim is widely endorsed by many highly re- garded commentators: [4], [6], [8], [13], [14], [15], [16], [19] [20], [21], [22], [24], [26]. In examining the formalist drive-by it is useful to consider the claim that Whitehead and Russell ought to provide a precise presentation of the 3 syntax of the system. That is, they ought to have provided a ’purely formal’ description of the system of Principia ’in abstraction from’ any interpretation of the system ([4]: 58); minimally, they should have characterised the ’syntax’ of Principia in the narrower sense of specifying the formation and inference rules of the system in such terms. To illustrate what is at issue, Whitehead and Russell state the principle of inference generally known as modus ponens (for the propositional fragment of Principia) thus: ’∗1·1. Anything implied by a true elementary proposition is true.’ ([31]: 98). Jung amongst others takes Whitehead and Russell’s primitive proposition ∗1·1 to reflect a failure to distinguish an object language under discussion (namely the ideal language of Principia Mathematica) from a metalanguage in which this object language is being described ([16]: 137-140). On this view, the inference rule in question should be formulated in the metalanguage in a form such as the following: ’for any formulae φ and ψ, from φ and pψ → ψq infer ψ,’ ([16]: 140, using corners for quasi-quotation and syntactical variables ranging over the well- formed formulas of the object language). I note for future reference that Jung’s objection to ∗1·1 assumes that propositions are, in an appropriate sense, Principia formulas. It will be seen below that if Principia propositions are not formulas but other kinds of entities then the formalists have not demonstrated an error in the Whitehead- Russell presentation, but rather have failed to address the system under dis- cussion. Before considering what Principia’s propositions might be however I consider two arguments in favour of the claim that the Whitehead-Russell presentation of Principia is defective in so far as it departs from the the the formalists approach. These arguments may be summarised thus: Effectiveness requirement The Whitehead-Russell presentation, to the extent that it departs from the formalist approach, fails to provide a notion of proof that is effective, and hence the ideal language of Principia is not adequate for the purpose of communication (c.f. [4]: 50-52; [11]: 616 ’Note added 28 August 1963’); Appropriate metatheory requirement A formalist reconstruction of the logic of Principia is to be preferred to the original Whitehead-Russell presentation since the metatheoretical properties of the former system may be precisely characterised for at least the first-order fragment, and moreover for this fragment the properties are well-known and appropri- ate - in brief, the theory is sound, complete, consistent and undecidable. Consider firstly the effectiveness requirement. This claim is not essential to the formalists’ position, as the idea of a ’formal system’ may be defined more broadly so as to avoid this requirement (e.g. [23]: 25). That is as 4 well for the formalist perspective, as the routine communication of working mathematicians presents strong prima facie evidence against this claim. To illustrate this point in various ways I will assume that the currently accepted metatheory of (classical) first-order logic and so on is essentially correct.
Recommended publications
  • Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic
    Ling 310, adapted from UMass Ling 409, Partee lecture notes March 1, 2006 p. 1 Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory........................................................................................................................1 1.1. Sets and elements ...................................................................................................................................1 1.2. Specification of sets ...............................................................................................................................2 1.3. Identity and cardinality ..........................................................................................................................3 1.4. Subsets ...................................................................................................................................................4 1.5. Power sets .............................................................................................................................................4 1.6. Operations on sets: union, intersection...................................................................................................4 1.7 More operations on sets: difference, complement...................................................................................5 1.8. Set-theoretic equalities ...........................................................................................................................5 Chapter 2. Relations and Functions ..................................................................................................................6
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • THE 1910 PRINCIPIA's THEORY of FUNCTIONS and CLASSES and the THEORY of DESCRIPTIONS*
    EUJAP VOL. 3 No. 2 2007 ORIGinal SCienTifiC papeR UDK: 165 THE 1910 PRINCIPIA’S THEORY OF FUNCTIONS AND CLASSES AND THE THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS* WILLIAM DEMOPOULOS** The University of Western Ontario ABSTRACT 1. Introduction It is generally acknowledged that the 1910 Prin- The 19101 Principia’s theory of proposi- cipia does not deny the existence of classes, but tional functions and classes is officially claims only that the theory it advances can be developed so that any apparent commitment to a “no-classes theory of classes,” a theory them is eliminable by the method of contextual according to which classes are eliminable. analysis. The application of contextual analysis But it is clear from Principia’s solution to ontological questions is widely viewed as the to the class paradoxes that although the central philosophical innovation of Russell’s theory of descriptions. Principia’s “no-classes theory it advances holds that classes are theory of classes” is a striking example of such eliminable, it does not deny their exis- an application. The present paper develops a re- tence. Whitehead and Russell argue from construction of Principia’s theory of functions the supposition that classes involve or and classes that is based on Russell’s epistemo- logical applications of the method of contextual presuppose propositional functions to the analysis. Such a reconstruction is not eliminativ- conclusion that the paradoxical classes ist—indeed, it explicitly assumes the existence of are excluded by the nature of such func- classes—and possesses certain advantages over tions. This supposition rests on the repre- the no–classes theory advocated by Whitehead and Russell.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Mathematics
    Foundations of Mathematics. Does mathematics need foundations? (Not until 1900.) Mathematical approach: Work towards an axiom system of mathematics with purely mathematical means. ( Hilbert’s Programme ). In its naïve interpretation crushed by Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem. Extra-mathematical approach: Use external arguments for axioms and rules: pragmatic, philosophical, sociological, (theological ?). Foundations of number theory: test case. Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 2/36 Sets are everything (1). Different areas of mathematics use different primitive notions: ordered pair, function, natural number, real number, transformation, etc. Set theory is able to incorporate all of these in one framework: Ordered Pair. We define hx, y i := {{ x}, {x, y }} . (Kuratowski pair ) Function. A set f is called a function if there are sets X and Y such that f ⊆ X × Y and ′ ′ ′ ∀x, y, y hx, y i ∈ f&hx, y i ∈ f → y = y . Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 3/36 Sets are everything (2). Set theory incorporates basic notions of mathematics: Natural Numbers. We call a set X inductive if it contains ∅ and for each x ∈ X, we have x ∪ { x} ∈ X. Assume that there is an inductive set. Then define N to be the intersection of all inductive sets. Rational Numbers. We define P := {0, 1} × N × N\{ 0}, then hi, n, m i ∼ h j, k, ℓ i : ⇐⇒ i = j & n · ℓ = m · k, and Q := P/∼. Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 4/36 Sets are everything (3). Set theory incorporates basic notions of mathematics: Real Numbers. Define an order on Q by hi, n, m i ≤ h j, k, ℓ i : ⇐⇒ i < j ∨ (i = j & n · ℓ ≤ k · m).
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Paradox: Let a Be the Set of All Sets Which Do Not Contain
    Russell’s paradox: Let A be the set of all sets which do not contain themselves = {S | S 6∈ S} Ex: {1} ∈ {{1}, {1, 2}}, but {1} 6∈ {1} Is A∈A? Suppose A∈A. Then by definition of A, A 6∈ A. Suppose A 6∈ A. Then by definition of A, A∈A. Thus we need axioms in order to create mathematical objects. Principia Mathematica by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell From: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/principia-mathematica/ Logicism is the view that (some or all of) mathematics can be reduced to (formal) logic. It is often explained as a two-part thesis. First, it consists of the claim that all mathematical truths can be translated into logical truths or, in other words, that the vocabulary of mathematics constitutes a proper subset of the vocabulary of logic. Second, it consists of the claim that all mathematical proofs can be recast as logical proofs or, in other words, that the theorems of mathematics constitute a proper subset of the theorems of logic. In Bertrand Russell’s words, it is the logicist’s goal ”to show that all pure mathematics follows from purely logical premises and uses only concepts definable in logical terms.”[1] From: http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/∼schectex/ccc/choice.html Axiom of Choice. Let C be a collection of nonempty sets. Then we can choose a member from each set in that collection. In other words, there exists a function f defined on C with the property that, for each set S in the collection, f(S) is a member of S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Substitutional Paradox in Russell's 1907 Letter to Hawtrey
    THE SUBSTITUTIONAL PARADOX IN RUSSELL’S 1907 LETTER TO HAWTREY B L Philosophy / U. of Alberta Edmonton, , Canada .@. This note presents a transcription of Russell’s letter to Hawtrey of January accompanied by some proposed emendations. In that letter Russell describes the paradox that he says “pilled” the “substitutional theory” devel- oped just before he turned to the theory of types. A close paraphrase of the deri- vation of the paradox in a contemporary Lemmon-style natural deduction system shows which axioms the theory must assume to govern its characteristic notion of substituting individuals and propositions for each other in other propositions. Other discussions of this paradox in the literature are mentioned. I conclude with remarks about the significance of the paradox for Russell. n the years to Bertrand Russell worked on what is now called the “substitutional theory” with its primitive notion of substi- Ituting one entity for another in a proposition, as a foundation for logic and source of a solution to the paradoxes. Russell abandoned that approach quite abruptly and returned to a logic based on propositional functions, eventually to appear as Principia Mathematica. Almost all of the material on the substitutional theory has remained unpublished; however, much will appear in print as the subject matter of Volume of the Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell. In recent years there has been some discussion of the substitutional theory, most prominently by Including, one may hope, a transcription of the letter which is the topic of this note. russell: the Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies n.s. (winter –): – The Bertrand Russell Research Centre, McMaster U.
    [Show full text]
  • Weyl's `Das Kontinuum' — 100 Years Later
    Arnon Avron Weyl's `Das Kontinuum' | 100 years later Orevkov'80 Conference St. Petersburg Days of Logic and Computability V April 2020 Prologue All platonists are alike; each anti-platonist is unhappy in her/his own way... My aim in this talk is first of all to present Weyl's views and system, at the time he wrote \Das Kontinuum" (exactly 100 years ago). Then I'll try to describe mine, which I believe are rather close to Weyl's original ideas (but still different). Weyl's Goals \I shall show that the house of analysis is to a large degree built on sand. I believe that I can replace this shifting foundation with pillars of enduring strength. They will not, however, support everything which today is generally considered to be securely grounded. I give up the rest, since I see no other possibility." \I would like to be understood . by all students who have become acquainted with the currently canonical and al- legedly `rigorous' foundations of analysis." \In spite of Dedekind, Cantor, and Weierstrass, the great task which has been facing us since the Pythagorean dis- covery of the irrationals remains today as unfinished as ever" Weyl and P´olya's Wager in 1918 Within 20 years P´olya and the majority of representative mathematicians will admit that the statements 1 Every bounded set of reals has a precise supremum 2 Every infinite set of numbers contains a denumerable subset contain totally vague concepts, such as \number," \set," and \denumerable," and therefore that their truth or fal- sity has the same status as that of the main propositions of Hegel's natural philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems KURT GÖDEL
    On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica And Related Systems KURT GÖDEL Translated by B. MELTZER Introduction by R. B. BRAITHWAITE TO CHRISTOPHER FERNAU in gratitude FL: Page 1 11/10/00 PREFACE Kurt Gödel’s astonishing discovery and proof, published in 1931, that even in elementary parts of arithmetic there exist propositions which cannot be proved or disproved within the system, is one of the most important contributions to logic since Aristotle. Any formal logical system which disposes of sufficient means to compass the addition and multiplication of positive integers and zero is subject to this limitation, so that one must consider this kind of incompleteness an inherent characteristic of formal mathematics as a whole, which was before this customarily considered the unequivocal intellectual discipline par excellence. No English translation of Gödel’s paper, which occupied twenty-five pages of the Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, has been generally available, and even the original German text is not everywhere easily accessible. The argument, which used a notation adapted from that of Whitehead and Russell’s Principia Mathematica, is a closely reasoned one and the present translation—besides being a long overdue act of piety—should make it more easily intelligible and much more widely read. In the former respect the reader will be greatly aided by the Introduction contributed by the Knightbridge Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Cambridge; for this is an excellent work of scholarship in its own right, not only pointing out the significance of Gödel’s work, but illuminating it by a paraphrase of the major part of the whole great argument.
    [Show full text]
  • The Propositional Logic of Principia Mathematica and Some of Its
    The propositional logic ofPM 93 2. Before and after Principia Mathematica One source which would have answered all questions is, of course, Russell. I imagine that he worked out all the demonstrations in detail and then condensed them to the current abbreviated form. At the least he must have had a sketch for The propositional logic of the complete demonstration. Presumably the next step would be to send them to Whitehead for comments. For a discussion of this process see Douglas Lackey's "The Whitehead Correspondence" [10]. In any case neither Russell's working Principia Mathematica and papers nor the letters to and responses from Whitehead concerning Part I, Section A are in the Russell Archives. There is however a letter from Whitehead to Russell some of its forerunners which indicates that, in an early draft of Part I, Section A, the demonstrations had not been written out in sufficient detail. Whitehead says, "Everything, even the object of the book, has been sacrificed to making the proofs look short and neat. It by Daniel J. O'Leary is essential, especially in the early parts that the proofs be written out fully-" (emphasis in original). This letter [31] had been later dated by Russell and a types­ cript [32]"prepared. On the bottom of the letter Russell has written, "Whitehead's criticism of *1-*5 ofPrincipia Mathematica". On the bottom of the typescript Rus­ sell wrote, "A criticism of my first draft of the Logic of Propositions for the begin­ ning of Principia Mathematica. Whitehead was entirely right." Russell assigned a I.
    [Show full text]
  • Kurt Gödel 1931
    Kurt Godel,¨ ‘Uber¨ formal unentscheidbare Satze¨ der Principia mathematica und verwandter Systeme I’ (1931) Richard Zach First publication: Monatshefte fur¨ Mathematik und Physik, 37, 173–198 Reprints: S. Feferman et al., eds., Kurt Godel.¨ Collected Works. Volume I: Publi- cations 1929–1936. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986, pp. 116–195. Translations: English translations: ‘On formally undecidable propositions of Prin- cipia mathematica and related systems I.’ Translation by B. Meltzer, On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems, Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1962. Translation by E. Mendelsohn in M. Davis, The Undecidable, Hewlett, N.Y.: Raven Press, 1965, pp. 4–38. Translation and introduction by J. van Heijenoort in J. van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Godel.¨ A Source Book in Mathe- matical Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, pp. 592–617. Van Heijenoort’s translation was approved by Godel¨ and is reprinted with an introduction by S. C. Kleene in S. Feferman et al., eds., Kurt Godel.¨ Collected Works. Volume I: Publications 1929–1936. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986, pp. 126– 195 (also contains several related pieces). Also reprinted in S. G. Shanker, Godel’s¨ Theorem in Focus, London: Routledge, 1988, pp. 17–47. Spanish translations: ‘So- bre proposiciones formalmente indecidibles de los Principia Mathematica y sistemas afines.’ Cuadernos Teorema 8. Valencia (Spain): Revista Teorema, 1980, by M. Gar- rido, A. Garc´ıa Suarez, and L. Ml. Valdes.;´ ‘Sobre sentencias formalmente inde- cidibles de Principa Matematica y sistemas afines,’ In: K. Godel,¨ Obras Completas, J. Moster´ın (ed.), Madrid: Alianza Editorial,1981, pp. 45–90.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications in Mathematics
    Treball final de grau GRAU DE MATEMATIQUES` Facultat de Matem`atiquesi Inform`atica Universitat de Barcelona The Axiom of Choice and its implications in mathematics Autor: Gina Garcia Tarrach Director: Dr. Joan Bagaria Realitzat a: Departament de Matem`atiques i Inform`atica Barcelona, 29 de juny de 2017 Abstract The Axiom of Choice is an axiom of set theory which states that, given a collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to choose an element out of each set of the collection. The implications of the acceptance of the Axiom are many, some of them essential to the de- velopment of contemporary mathematics. In this work, we give a basic presentation of the Axiom and its consequences: we study the Axiom of Choice as well as some of its equivalent forms such as the Well Ordering Theorem and Zorn's Lemma, some weaker choice principles, the implications of the Axiom in different fields of mathematics, so- me paradoxical results implied by it, and its role within the Zermelo-Fraenkel axiomatic theory. i Contents Introduction 1 0 Some preliminary notes on well-orders, ordinal and cardinal numbers 3 1 Historical background 6 2 The Axiom of Choice and its Equivalent Forms 9 2.1 The Axiom of Choice . 9 2.2 The Well Ordering Theorem . 10 2.3 Zorn's Lemma . 12 2.4 Other equivalent forms . 13 3 Weaker Forms of the Axiom of Choice 14 3.1 The Axiom of Dependent Choice . 14 3.2 The Axiom of Countable Choice . 15 3.3 The Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem .
    [Show full text]