Weyl's `Das Kontinuum' — 100 Years Later

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Weyl's `Das Kontinuum' — 100 Years Later Arnon Avron Weyl's `Das Kontinuum' | 100 years later Orevkov'80 Conference St. Petersburg Days of Logic and Computability V April 2020 Prologue All platonists are alike; each anti-platonist is unhappy in her/his own way... My aim in this talk is first of all to present Weyl's views and system, at the time he wrote \Das Kontinuum" (exactly 100 years ago). Then I'll try to describe mine, which I believe are rather close to Weyl's original ideas (but still different). Weyl's Goals \I shall show that the house of analysis is to a large degree built on sand. I believe that I can replace this shifting foundation with pillars of enduring strength. They will not, however, support everything which today is generally considered to be securely grounded. I give up the rest, since I see no other possibility." \I would like to be understood . by all students who have become acquainted with the currently canonical and al- legedly `rigorous' foundations of analysis." \In spite of Dedekind, Cantor, and Weierstrass, the great task which has been facing us since the Pythagorean dis- covery of the irrationals remains today as unfinished as ever" Weyl and P´olya's Wager in 1918 Within 20 years P´olya and the majority of representative mathematicians will admit that the statements 1 Every bounded set of reals has a precise supremum 2 Every infinite set of numbers contains a denumerable subset contain totally vague concepts, such as \number," \set," and \denumerable," and therefore that their truth or fal- sity has the same status as that of the main propositions of Hegel's natural philosophy. However, under a natural interpretation, (1) and (2) will be seen to be false. What Has Weyl Rejected, and Why? He rejected the \completely vague concept of function which has become canonical in analysis since Dirichlet and, together with it, the prevailing concept of set." He believed that this \vague concept of set and function . finds itself caught in a vicious circle." The Ideal Calculus for Sets Extensionality: 8z(z 2 x $ z 2 y) ! x = y The Comprehension Schema: 8y(y 2f x j 'g$ '[y=x]) Ideal, but inconsistent! Predicativity, Impredicativity, and Poincar´eVCP The inconsistency of the ideal calculus implies that not every formula ' can be used for constructing legitimate set terms of the form fx j 'g. Poincar´eand Russel called a formula that (in their opinion) can be so used predicative, and a formula that cannot impredicative. They (and then Weyl) Usually characterized an impredicative definition as a definition that violates the Vicious Circle Principle (VCP): `Whatever involves all of a collection must not be one of the collection.' [Principia Mathematica 1910] Weyl and the VCP \It would be meaningless to include among these principles an assertion such as the following: If A is a property of properties, then one may form that property PA which belongs to an object x if and only if there is a property constructed by means of these principles which belongs to x and itself possesses the property A. That would be a blatant vicious circle; yet our current version of analysis commits this error and I consider this ground for censure". S PA = fx 2 S j 9X :X 2 2 ^ A(X ) ^ x 2 X g An Example: The LUB principle In analysis, the least upper bound (sup) of a bounded set A of reals is defined as the minimal element of the set of upper bounds of A. This is an impredicative definition. When real numbers are taken as Dedekind cuts, then the existence of the sup(A) is shown by defining (or characterizing it) as: sup(A) = fq 2 Q j 9X :X 2 2Q ^ X 2 A ^ q 2 X g Again, this involves an impredicative definition. When Should an Impredicative Definition Be Rejected? There are certainly impredicative definitions that are perfectly acceptable: The tallest man in the room The least prime number These definitions just select an object from a given fully-determined (or `closed') collection. An impredicative definition is illegitimate if it tries to \select" an object from an indeterminate (or `open') collection. In particular: if the definition is viewed as creating the object it defines. Weyl's Principles: Sets Sets (and functions) are created only by definitions. \No one can describe an infinite set other than by indi- cating properties which are characteristic of the elements of the set. The notion that an infinite set as a \gath- ering" brought together by infinitely many individual arbi- trary acts of selection, assembled and then surveyed as a whole by consciousness, is nonsensical;" Weyl's Principles: Predicativity Via Types Weyl allows only predicative definitions of sets. Like Russel, this predicativity is ensured using a combination of two independent means, one of which is the use of types (or \categories"). Each object and relation between objects has a specific type. Some of the types are basic. Each basic type is \a complete system of definite self-existent objects". In addition, in basic types also the basic accepted relations should be “definite”. The other types are types of sets and functions which are derived from the basic ones using the rules of definition. These types are incomplete systems of objects. Weyl's Principles: Predicativity Via Safe Formulas The other measure Weyl took in order to ensure predicativity is to allow only the use of safe (or \delimited") formulas in the definitions of sets and functions. For Weyl safe formulas are those in which the use of quantification and equality is confined only to basic types. Weyl's Principles: The Natural Numbers The natural numbers sequence is a basic well-understood, mathematical concept, and should be taken as a basic type. \[T]he idea of iteration, i.e., of the sequence of the natural numbers, is an ultimate foundation of mathematical thought" \Our grasp of the basic concepts of set theory depends on a prior intuition of iteration and of the sequence of natural numbers." [P. 24] \A single basic relation, whose meaning is immediately exhibited, underlies this category | namely, the relation Succ(x; y) which holds between two natural numbers x; y when y is the immediate successor of x." [P. 25] Weyl's Principles: Real numbers [T]he real numbers are certain four-dimensional sets of natural numbers. The collection of real numbers is open: \If we regard the principles of definition as an \open" sys- tem, i.e., if we reserve the right to extend them when necessary by making additions, then in general the ques- tion of whether a given function is continuous must also remain open. For a function which, within our current sys- tem, is continuous can lose this property if our principles of definition are expanded and, accordingly, the real numbers \presently" available are joined by others." [P. 87] Weyl's Notion of Function The only sort of functions as objects which are allowed by Weyl are those which have explicit definitions of the form: λy1;:::; yk :fhx1;:::; xni j 'g The domain of such a function is some product of types, and its range is a type of sets. Thus operations on N (like addition) are officially defined as relations, not as functions. Functions are always defined on their full domain. Thus a function from R to R is a function from Set(N4) to Set(N4) with the property that for every x 2 R its value is in R. (The collection of such functions is neither a set nor a type.) Weyl writes: \once we become aware of this concept of function, we also immediately grasp its significance". Some Examples of Weyl's Idea Procedures for solving equations and inequalities (with parameters). E.g. Asin(nx) + Bcos(nx) = C. Constructions of locies in Euclidean geometry. Queries in logic programming. Queries in relational databases. Weyl's Formal System: Types 1 N is a (basic) type. 2 If τ1; : : : ; τn are types (n > 0), then so is Set(τ1 × · · · × τn). 3 If σ1; : : : ; σk and τ1; : : : ; τn are types, where k > 0 and n > 0, then( σ1 × · · · × σk ) ! Set(τ1 × · · · × τn) is a type. Weyl's Formal System: Terms Notation: σ = σ1 × · · · × σk , τ = τ1 × · · · × τn. 1 xσ : σ 2 Let n > 0, and let be a safe formula such that Fv[ ] ⊇ fx1;:::; xng, where xi : τi (1 ≤ i ≤ n). Then fhx1;:::; xni j g : Set(τ) 3 Let k > 0, and let t : Set(τ) be a term such that Fv[t] ⊇ fy1;:::; yk g, where yj : σj (1 ≤ j ≤ k). Then λy1;:::; yk :t : σ !Set(τ) 4 If s : σ ! Set(τ) and ti : σi (i = 1;:::; k), then s(t1;:::; tk ): Set(τ). 5 If t : Set(τ) ! Set(τ) then IT [t]: N × Set(τ) ! Set(τ). A Natural Extension of Weyl's System Types:3 If σ1; : : : ; σk and τ are types, where k ≥ 1, then (σ1 × · · · × σk ) ! τ is a type. Terms:3 Let k ≥ 1, and let t : τ be a term such that Fv[t] ⊇ fy1;:::; yk g, where yj : σj (1 ≤ j ≤ k). Then λy1;:::; yk :t : σ ! τ. 4 If s : σ ! τ and ti : σi (i = 1;:::; k), then s(t1;:::; tk ): τ. 5 If t : τ ! τ then IT [t]: N × τ ! τ. Weyl's Formal System: Safe Formulas The set of terms and the set of safe formulas are simultaneously defined using a mutual recursion. 1 If t : N and s : N then SUCC(t; s) is a safe formulas. 2 If t and s are terms of type N then t = s is a safe formula.
Recommended publications
  • Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic
    Ling 310, adapted from UMass Ling 409, Partee lecture notes March 1, 2006 p. 1 Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory........................................................................................................................1 1.1. Sets and elements ...................................................................................................................................1 1.2. Specification of sets ...............................................................................................................................2 1.3. Identity and cardinality ..........................................................................................................................3 1.4. Subsets ...................................................................................................................................................4 1.5. Power sets .............................................................................................................................................4 1.6. Operations on sets: union, intersection...................................................................................................4 1.7 More operations on sets: difference, complement...................................................................................5 1.8. Set-theoretic equalities ...........................................................................................................................5 Chapter 2. Relations and Functions ..................................................................................................................6
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • THE 1910 PRINCIPIA's THEORY of FUNCTIONS and CLASSES and the THEORY of DESCRIPTIONS*
    EUJAP VOL. 3 No. 2 2007 ORIGinal SCienTifiC papeR UDK: 165 THE 1910 PRINCIPIA’S THEORY OF FUNCTIONS AND CLASSES AND THE THEORY OF DESCRIPTIONS* WILLIAM DEMOPOULOS** The University of Western Ontario ABSTRACT 1. Introduction It is generally acknowledged that the 1910 Prin- The 19101 Principia’s theory of proposi- cipia does not deny the existence of classes, but tional functions and classes is officially claims only that the theory it advances can be developed so that any apparent commitment to a “no-classes theory of classes,” a theory them is eliminable by the method of contextual according to which classes are eliminable. analysis. The application of contextual analysis But it is clear from Principia’s solution to ontological questions is widely viewed as the to the class paradoxes that although the central philosophical innovation of Russell’s theory of descriptions. Principia’s “no-classes theory it advances holds that classes are theory of classes” is a striking example of such eliminable, it does not deny their exis- an application. The present paper develops a re- tence. Whitehead and Russell argue from construction of Principia’s theory of functions the supposition that classes involve or and classes that is based on Russell’s epistemo- logical applications of the method of contextual presuppose propositional functions to the analysis. Such a reconstruction is not eliminativ- conclusion that the paradoxical classes ist—indeed, it explicitly assumes the existence of are excluded by the nature of such func- classes—and possesses certain advantages over tions. This supposition rests on the repre- the no–classes theory advocated by Whitehead and Russell.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Mathematics
    Foundations of Mathematics. Does mathematics need foundations? (Not until 1900.) Mathematical approach: Work towards an axiom system of mathematics with purely mathematical means. ( Hilbert’s Programme ). In its naïve interpretation crushed by Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem. Extra-mathematical approach: Use external arguments for axioms and rules: pragmatic, philosophical, sociological, (theological ?). Foundations of number theory: test case. Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 2/36 Sets are everything (1). Different areas of mathematics use different primitive notions: ordered pair, function, natural number, real number, transformation, etc. Set theory is able to incorporate all of these in one framework: Ordered Pair. We define hx, y i := {{ x}, {x, y }} . (Kuratowski pair ) Function. A set f is called a function if there are sets X and Y such that f ⊆ X × Y and ′ ′ ′ ∀x, y, y hx, y i ∈ f&hx, y i ∈ f → y = y . Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 3/36 Sets are everything (2). Set theory incorporates basic notions of mathematics: Natural Numbers. We call a set X inductive if it contains ∅ and for each x ∈ X, we have x ∪ { x} ∈ X. Assume that there is an inductive set. Then define N to be the intersection of all inductive sets. Rational Numbers. We define P := {0, 1} × N × N\{ 0}, then hi, n, m i ∼ h j, k, ℓ i : ⇐⇒ i = j & n · ℓ = m · k, and Q := P/∼. Core Logic – 2007/08-1ab – p. 4/36 Sets are everything (3). Set theory incorporates basic notions of mathematics: Real Numbers. Define an order on Q by hi, n, m i ≤ h j, k, ℓ i : ⇐⇒ i < j ∨ (i = j & n · ℓ ≤ k · m).
    [Show full text]
  • Russell's Paradox: Let a Be the Set of All Sets Which Do Not Contain
    Russell’s paradox: Let A be the set of all sets which do not contain themselves = {S | S 6∈ S} Ex: {1} ∈ {{1}, {1, 2}}, but {1} 6∈ {1} Is A∈A? Suppose A∈A. Then by definition of A, A 6∈ A. Suppose A 6∈ A. Then by definition of A, A∈A. Thus we need axioms in order to create mathematical objects. Principia Mathematica by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell From: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/principia-mathematica/ Logicism is the view that (some or all of) mathematics can be reduced to (formal) logic. It is often explained as a two-part thesis. First, it consists of the claim that all mathematical truths can be translated into logical truths or, in other words, that the vocabulary of mathematics constitutes a proper subset of the vocabulary of logic. Second, it consists of the claim that all mathematical proofs can be recast as logical proofs or, in other words, that the theorems of mathematics constitute a proper subset of the theorems of logic. In Bertrand Russell’s words, it is the logicist’s goal ”to show that all pure mathematics follows from purely logical premises and uses only concepts definable in logical terms.”[1] From: http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/∼schectex/ccc/choice.html Axiom of Choice. Let C be a collection of nonempty sets. Then we can choose a member from each set in that collection. In other words, there exists a function f defined on C with the property that, for each set S in the collection, f(S) is a member of S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Substitutional Paradox in Russell's 1907 Letter to Hawtrey
    THE SUBSTITUTIONAL PARADOX IN RUSSELL’S 1907 LETTER TO HAWTREY B L Philosophy / U. of Alberta Edmonton, , Canada .@. This note presents a transcription of Russell’s letter to Hawtrey of January accompanied by some proposed emendations. In that letter Russell describes the paradox that he says “pilled” the “substitutional theory” devel- oped just before he turned to the theory of types. A close paraphrase of the deri- vation of the paradox in a contemporary Lemmon-style natural deduction system shows which axioms the theory must assume to govern its characteristic notion of substituting individuals and propositions for each other in other propositions. Other discussions of this paradox in the literature are mentioned. I conclude with remarks about the significance of the paradox for Russell. n the years to Bertrand Russell worked on what is now called the “substitutional theory” with its primitive notion of substi- Ituting one entity for another in a proposition, as a foundation for logic and source of a solution to the paradoxes. Russell abandoned that approach quite abruptly and returned to a logic based on propositional functions, eventually to appear as Principia Mathematica. Almost all of the material on the substitutional theory has remained unpublished; however, much will appear in print as the subject matter of Volume of the Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell. In recent years there has been some discussion of the substitutional theory, most prominently by Including, one may hope, a transcription of the letter which is the topic of this note. russell: the Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies n.s. (winter –): – The Bertrand Russell Research Centre, McMaster U.
    [Show full text]
  • On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems KURT GÖDEL
    On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica And Related Systems KURT GÖDEL Translated by B. MELTZER Introduction by R. B. BRAITHWAITE TO CHRISTOPHER FERNAU in gratitude FL: Page 1 11/10/00 PREFACE Kurt Gödel’s astonishing discovery and proof, published in 1931, that even in elementary parts of arithmetic there exist propositions which cannot be proved or disproved within the system, is one of the most important contributions to logic since Aristotle. Any formal logical system which disposes of sufficient means to compass the addition and multiplication of positive integers and zero is subject to this limitation, so that one must consider this kind of incompleteness an inherent characteristic of formal mathematics as a whole, which was before this customarily considered the unequivocal intellectual discipline par excellence. No English translation of Gödel’s paper, which occupied twenty-five pages of the Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, has been generally available, and even the original German text is not everywhere easily accessible. The argument, which used a notation adapted from that of Whitehead and Russell’s Principia Mathematica, is a closely reasoned one and the present translation—besides being a long overdue act of piety—should make it more easily intelligible and much more widely read. In the former respect the reader will be greatly aided by the Introduction contributed by the Knightbridge Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Cambridge; for this is an excellent work of scholarship in its own right, not only pointing out the significance of Gödel’s work, but illuminating it by a paraphrase of the major part of the whole great argument.
    [Show full text]
  • The Propositional Logic of Principia Mathematica and Some of Its
    The propositional logic ofPM 93 2. Before and after Principia Mathematica One source which would have answered all questions is, of course, Russell. I imagine that he worked out all the demonstrations in detail and then condensed them to the current abbreviated form. At the least he must have had a sketch for The propositional logic of the complete demonstration. Presumably the next step would be to send them to Whitehead for comments. For a discussion of this process see Douglas Lackey's "The Whitehead Correspondence" [10]. In any case neither Russell's working Principia Mathematica and papers nor the letters to and responses from Whitehead concerning Part I, Section A are in the Russell Archives. There is however a letter from Whitehead to Russell some of its forerunners which indicates that, in an early draft of Part I, Section A, the demonstrations had not been written out in sufficient detail. Whitehead says, "Everything, even the object of the book, has been sacrificed to making the proofs look short and neat. It by Daniel J. O'Leary is essential, especially in the early parts that the proofs be written out fully-" (emphasis in original). This letter [31] had been later dated by Russell and a types­ cript [32]"prepared. On the bottom of the letter Russell has written, "Whitehead's criticism of *1-*5 ofPrincipia Mathematica". On the bottom of the typescript Rus­ sell wrote, "A criticism of my first draft of the Logic of Propositions for the begin­ ning of Principia Mathematica. Whitehead was entirely right." Russell assigned a I.
    [Show full text]
  • Kurt Gödel 1931
    Kurt Godel,¨ ‘Uber¨ formal unentscheidbare Satze¨ der Principia mathematica und verwandter Systeme I’ (1931) Richard Zach First publication: Monatshefte fur¨ Mathematik und Physik, 37, 173–198 Reprints: S. Feferman et al., eds., Kurt Godel.¨ Collected Works. Volume I: Publi- cations 1929–1936. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986, pp. 116–195. Translations: English translations: ‘On formally undecidable propositions of Prin- cipia mathematica and related systems I.’ Translation by B. Meltzer, On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems, Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1962. Translation by E. Mendelsohn in M. Davis, The Undecidable, Hewlett, N.Y.: Raven Press, 1965, pp. 4–38. Translation and introduction by J. van Heijenoort in J. van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Godel.¨ A Source Book in Mathe- matical Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, pp. 592–617. Van Heijenoort’s translation was approved by Godel¨ and is reprinted with an introduction by S. C. Kleene in S. Feferman et al., eds., Kurt Godel.¨ Collected Works. Volume I: Publications 1929–1936. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986, pp. 126– 195 (also contains several related pieces). Also reprinted in S. G. Shanker, Godel’s¨ Theorem in Focus, London: Routledge, 1988, pp. 17–47. Spanish translations: ‘So- bre proposiciones formalmente indecidibles de los Principia Mathematica y sistemas afines.’ Cuadernos Teorema 8. Valencia (Spain): Revista Teorema, 1980, by M. Gar- rido, A. Garc´ıa Suarez, and L. Ml. Valdes.;´ ‘Sobre sentencias formalmente inde- cidibles de Principa Matematica y sistemas afines,’ In: K. Godel,¨ Obras Completas, J. Moster´ın (ed.), Madrid: Alianza Editorial,1981, pp. 45–90.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications in Mathematics
    Treball final de grau GRAU DE MATEMATIQUES` Facultat de Matem`atiquesi Inform`atica Universitat de Barcelona The Axiom of Choice and its implications in mathematics Autor: Gina Garcia Tarrach Director: Dr. Joan Bagaria Realitzat a: Departament de Matem`atiques i Inform`atica Barcelona, 29 de juny de 2017 Abstract The Axiom of Choice is an axiom of set theory which states that, given a collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to choose an element out of each set of the collection. The implications of the acceptance of the Axiom are many, some of them essential to the de- velopment of contemporary mathematics. In this work, we give a basic presentation of the Axiom and its consequences: we study the Axiom of Choice as well as some of its equivalent forms such as the Well Ordering Theorem and Zorn's Lemma, some weaker choice principles, the implications of the Axiom in different fields of mathematics, so- me paradoxical results implied by it, and its role within the Zermelo-Fraenkel axiomatic theory. i Contents Introduction 1 0 Some preliminary notes on well-orders, ordinal and cardinal numbers 3 1 Historical background 6 2 The Axiom of Choice and its Equivalent Forms 9 2.1 The Axiom of Choice . 9 2.2 The Well Ordering Theorem . 10 2.3 Zorn's Lemma . 12 2.4 Other equivalent forms . 13 3 Weaker Forms of the Axiom of Choice 14 3.1 The Axiom of Dependent Choice . 14 3.2 The Axiom of Countable Choice . 15 3.3 The Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem .
    [Show full text]
  • Extension to Geometry of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems II
    The geometry of Principia 141 Due to the two editions of Principia, criticisms of them, changes in Whitehead and Russell's opinions in geometry, and relevant post-Principia developments, a word about perspective is in order. Another logician has asked me what is meant by "geometry" in the title of this paper and which edition of Principia is used. By Extension to geometry of the former I mean Principia geometry according to the cited sources. The perspec­ tive relies upon the second edition. Published, extra-Principia s.ources ofits authors' views are used as the primary foundation of speculative construction and are care­ Principia Mathematica and fully related to the primary sources. Influential criticisms ofPrincipia and significant post-Principia developments must be reserved for other occasions. Finally, although this work was prompted by questions about the effective applicability of Principia related systems III logic to its geometry in the projected Volume IV, this paper postpones a direct logical view of geometry. This paper is concerned with the preliminary work of demar­ by· Martha Harrell cating the field of geometry and with providing the discipline with some specifi­ cation adequate.to Principia purposes. In Se~. I, Principia references to geometry are studied. In Sec. 2, the major views of Whitehead and Russell regarding geometry are cited with reference to Sec. I. Whitehead's letters to Russell concerning Volume IV, the only primary sources of this work known extant, are studied here. In Sec. 3, related systems are considered. CONSIDERING THE LACK of attention paid to this subject, it should be said that The conclusion is given in Sec.
    [Show full text]