Bacon's Allegory of Science: <I>The Theater of the New Atlantis</I>

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bacon's Allegory of Science: <I>The Theater of the New Atlantis</I> Quidditas Volume 4 Article 11 1983 Bacon's Allegory of Science: The Theater of the New Atlantis Patricia Demers University of Alberta Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/rmmra Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Renaissance Studies Commons Recommended Citation Demers, Patricia (1983) "Bacon's Allegory of Science: The Theater of the New Atlantis," Quidditas: Vol. 4 , Article 11. Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/rmmra/vol4/iss1/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Quidditas by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Bacon's Allegory of Science: The Theater of the New Atlantis by Patricia Demers University of Alberto I conceive that I perform the office of a true priest of the sense (from which all knowledge in nature must be sought, unless men mean to go mad) and a not unskilful interpreter of its ora­ cles. ("The Plan of the Work," The Great h1stau­ ratio11) Dramatic poesy among the ancients . bas been regarded by learned men and great philosophers as a kind of musician's bow by which men's minds may be played upon. (Tra11slatio11 of the 'Ve Augmentis," The Sec­ ond Book)' The ass ssment of Bacon's New Atlantis has long been a vexing critical problem-and with good reason. An incomplete work probably begun in 1623, when Bacon's hopes of shoring up his disgraced reputation by being appointed Provost of Eton and establishing a research institute there were high, New Atlantis is cited by various commentators as the final corrobora­ tive testimony in their views of the man. lf Bacon is merely the pragmatic materialist, censorious statesman or technocratic spokesman, then critical observations on NewAtlallfis may be seen to be tailored to suit an instruc• tive fable about scientilk advances which can, however, reveal Verulam's legalistic reliance on the world-as-it-is,• his divorce of science from po-- 'The Work8 ofFrancis Baco11, In Fifteen Volumes, ed. J. Spedding, .R. L. Ells, D. D . Heath (London: Longman and Company, 1857-74), VDI, 44; vm. 441. Subsequent guotalforu from Bacon'• works will be based on this edition. 'Sidney Warhaft, "Bacon and the Renaissance Ideal of Self-Knowledge." Pemma/1,14 44 (1964), 451-71. 136 The Theater of the ew Atlantis etry,• his addiction to superstitious habits of mind and his lack of foresight about the social responsibilities of scientific autonomy.• On the whole these views categorize Bacon either as an ambitious but prosaic litcralist or as a skilful logician who unfortunately missed the crucial point. Two critical comments might summarize neatly. For Marjorie Hope icolson, studying "The EIFect of the • ew Science' pon venteenth-Century Poetry," Francis Bacon shows "his usual prosaic common sense: ·• she examine and generally commends Bacon's "Art of Discour e," Li a Jar­ dine regrets that this gifted writer treated "systematic experimenting as sub idiary" and thereby dismissed "as secondary and provisional much of what we now regard as science."• Another and, in most instances, more recent view of Bacon insists on his primacy as a prophet and poet of hitherto neglected or maligned talents. An inspiring model for The Royal Society,' Francis Bacon has been hailed as a reformer8 who, in elevating the pursuit of continuing experiment, contributed to "a new ideal of man."• ot only was Bacon prescient in eparating science from politics, but he was also \villing to o!Fer his "idealist poetics . in the ervice of science." 10 he was prized by Shelley, Lord Bacon was a poet; although this statesman clung to peculiar, sometimes erron ou theories, he a.Isa distinguished his voluminous labour with reHective, though not always consistent, utterance . 11 Mary He e has recogniz d that, despite the nu­ merous 0aws in Bacon's thinking, he did visualize the structure of scien­ 1 tific laws and support "a method of systematic analogy." 1 Jonathan Cohen 'LC. Knights, "Bacon and the Seventeenth-Century Dissociation of Sensibility," Exp/om­ /ions: Essa11s m Criticism Mainly on the Llterotum of the Seventeenth Centu'JI (Middlesex: Penguin, I 946). 'Robert P. Adarru, '"!'he Social Responsibilities or Science in Utopia, New At/011/1$ and After,"/H/, 10 (1949), 393;Judah Bierman,·· ew Atlantis Revisited," Studiu/11 theLIIBm'JI lmoginotlon, 4 (1971 ), 137; Loren Eiseley, Fmnc/s Bacon and thtJ Mod11m Dllsmmo (Un­ coln: Uruversity or ebraslca Pr-, 1962), p. 67 'The Brmklng of the Clrr:le: Studio In the Efft!Ct oftl,s "New SclcnCI!" Upon Sswmtstmth­ Century P«try, Revised Edition 'ew York: Columbia University Pr , 1960), p. 8. 'Francis Bacon Dlxooery and the Art of Discount! (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974), p. 149. 'Margery Purver, ThtJ Royal Socielfl· Concept and Crmtlon (London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967). 'Marie Boos Hall, ··tn Defense of Bacon"s Views on the Reform of Science," Penono/ist, 44 (1964), 436-53. 'Moody E. Prior, "Bacon's Man of Science," /HI, 15 (1954), 365. 0 ' E. P. McCreary, "Bacon's Theory or the Imagination Reconsidered," HLQ, 36 (1973), 328. "John L Harrison, "Bacon's View or Rhetoric, Poelry, and the Imagination," HLQ, 20 (1957), 107-25; Walter R. Davis, '"!'he Imagery or Bacon's Late Work," MLQ, 27 (1966), 162-73. ""Francu Bacon's Philosophy or Science" in Esser1t10/ Articles for thtJ Study of Fmncls Bacon, ed. B. Vickers (Hamden, Connecticut: Archon Books, 1968), p. 138. Patricia Demers 137 has gone as far as to claim that laws established by Baconian induction can indeed .. constitute a pyramid of increasing probability."" Especially as a schematic, assertive writer, Bacon was a consummate artist who, as Brian Vickers describes him, was "incapable of writing on any topic for long without using metaphor." 14 Moreover, Vickers has hown very convinc­ ingly how this metaphorical penchant enabled Bacon to write with ·•no animus towards the theatre."" One of the best of the modem readers of Bacon is Michael Hattaway who defends "the interpenetration of the physical and the metaphysical in Bacon's method."'" For Hattaway Bacon is a genuine composite: a modem synthesizer who shows traces of a medi­ eval encyclopaedist, the delineator of an ordered universe who is also given to probing, non-mechanical aphorisms. Bacon's chaplain was the 6rst editor of New Atlantis: William Rawley called it a .. fable" which instructed by means of the .. model or description of a college." Later analysts have called it a "mythic parable,"" a "speculative myth,"18 or a "utopia of science."'" Without wishing to add to taxonomic confusion this reading focusses on the poetic expressiveness and dramatic capacitie which Bacon used in designing ew Atlantis. His imaginative Janus was forever active. While the forthright prophet­ prie t interpreted the oracle of the future, the eulogist of classical drama bemoaned the "toys" of the present in favour of the educating mu ician­ ship of the past. ln fact, such a priest would likely balk at the musician's role about to be sugge ted for him in ew Atlantis. Idle and light wits usually corrupt allegory, he charged, and drama is more effective in open• ing men's minds "to impressions and affections when many are gathered together than when they are alone."20 Where does this leave the solitary reader of ew Atlantis who sees in it a theater for the presentation of an allegory of science? Bacon would no doubt remind his reader that '"all the received systems are but so many stageplays, representing the worlds of their own creation after an unreal and scenic fashion,"21 and dismiss the per istent allegorist into a limbo with other victims of the idols of the Theatre. Yet because Bacon was enough of an artist and a potential musi­ cian, he might also linger awhile to hear hi own reviews. ""'Som Historical Remarks on the Baconian Conception or Probability,'" JIii, 41 (1980), 220. "Franc,s Bacon and Re,1a,ssan~ Prose (Cambridge: At the University Press, 1968), p. 50. ""'Bacon's Use or Theatrical Imagery," Studies In Ilia Lilero'IJ lmaglnallan, 4 (1971), 226. ""Bacon and 'Knowledge Broken': Limits for Scienti&c Method,'" /HI, 39 (1978), 192. "McCreary, "Bacon's Theory or Imagination Reconsidered,'" 325. "Bierman, ·· cw Atlantis Re,isitcd,"" 131. ,.Judah Bierman, "The Nt!w Allan/ls, Bacon's Utopia or Science,'" Papen 011 Language and Literotu~. 3 (1967), 99-110. ' 0 Tron m/1011 af 11,e "O,, Augmenlis," Book 11 , Chapter xiii, Ill. 441-2. "Trans/al/an of !he Nocum Organum, Aphorism XLJV, VIII. 78 . • 138 The Theater of the New Atlantis Bacon has constructed NewAtlo11tis with remarkable dramatic artistry. After painting in the backdrop and scene with words, this schematic interpreter frequently proceeds to shape his scene into an icon, fabulous and allusive at once, and then reanimates this crystalline moment by lifting yet another veil and beginning anew. In this way New Atlo11tis mirrors the very approach of ordering, axiomizing and recreating that Bacon hoped to introduce to science. Like the industrious but transform­ ing bee,•• he is never content, ant-like, to collect mere scenes, or to spread spidery webs of reason about them to Batter himself. With each scene or movement he is always passing beyond and moving ahead. While the arrangement of the e scenes often suggests a "superficially ordered" argu­ ment, their connection with one another is, as Angus Fletcher has ob­ served, "to a high degree magical." .. In addition, there are many advantages to examining magical relation­ ships over totting up the depressingly impersonal features of a scientific utopia Tracing the ••figurative geometry"24 of allegory in the scenes of the work provides a more constructive way of assessing Bacon's matter than listing the differences between the Bensalemites and us, which viewing the narrative as an arid utopia of science encourages the reader to do.
Recommended publications
  • Utopian Science and Empire. Notes on the Iberian Background of Francis Bacon's Project Ştiinłă Utopică Şi Imperiu
    Studii de ştiinŃă şi cultură Anul VI, Nr. 4 (23), decembrie 2010 UTOPIAN SCIENCE AND EMPIRE. NOTES ON THE IBERIAN BACKGROUND OF FRANCIS BACON’S PROJECT ŞTIINłĂ UTOPICĂ ŞI IMPERIU: NOTE ASUPRA CONTEXTULUI IBERIC AL PROIECTULUI BACONIAN Silvia MANZO Universidad Nacional de La Plata, Argentina [email protected] Abstract This paper will explore Bacon’s perceptions of the scientific connotations of the Spanish empire and his reception of early modern Iberian science. Its aim is to analyze the extent to which the Iberian background played a role in the making of Bacon’s project of a utopian imperial science, by drawing attention to some particular cases: the reception of the Jesuits, the natural histories, the chronicles of discovery, and the evaluation of Columbus’ voyages. It is shown that Bacon’s relationship with Iberian themes and sources was explicit in a few cases (Acosta, Columbus, Inca Garcilaso, the Jesuit order), while at other times the relationship is more indirect and implicit (Fernández de Oviedo, López de Gomara, Martire, Ramusio, Benzoni, Fernández de Quirós). It is argued that early modern imperial Spain seems to have been assessed by Bacon as a model of a growing empire, an empire whose greatness relied heavily on the Jesuit order and the colonization of America. The paper concludes that the attentive observation of the Spanish empire as well as the acquaintance with the Jesuits and the Iberian chronicles must have inspired Bacon’s project of science and his ideas on the articulation of science with empire. At the same time, other past and contemporary authors and traditions found their place in Bacon’s program for the reform of learning.
    [Show full text]
  • Unmasking Utopia
    Faculteit Letteren & Wijsbegeerte Hannah Lingier Unmasking utopia Civil conditioning in early-modern utopian literature Promotor: Prof. dr. Eric Schliesser Vakgroep Wijsbegeerte Masterproef voorgelegd tot het behalen van de graad van Master in de Wijsbegeerte Academiejaar 2015-2016 … and continually we met with many things right worthy of observation and relation, as indeed, if there be a mirror in the world worthy to hold men’s eyes, it is that country. Francis Bacon, New Atlantis 3 4 Acknowledgements Although it took me a while to realize it, the subject of this thesis now seems the logical endpoint of my years as a student. Looking back, it is hard to see how I only decided on the topic of utopian literature at the end of last year. For at last making this choice self- evident, I am very grateful to Prof. dr. Eric Schliesser, who introduced me to many exciting texts and triggered my interest in early modern political philosophy. His course on modern philosophy not only settled the topic but also the supervisor, and I would like to thank him especially for agreeing to take up this task despite the adverse practical and spatial circumstances, and of course for his time and greatly valued input. Prof. dr. Bart Keunen deserves special mention for opening the door to the world of -topian thought almost five years ago and, ever since, always keeping his own door open. None of this would have been possible without my family, to whom I am especially grateful for never questioning the need to endlessly keep studying. I would like to thank my grandparents for the financial support; my brother for the philosophical-theological pub talks; my mother for her infinite supply of wise advice; and my father for his valuable remarks on this text, and, I suspect, for being the cause of my decision to study philosophy in the first place.
    [Show full text]
  • Censorship and the Institution of Knowledge in Bacon's New Atlantis
    180 Francis Bacon’s New Atlantis 9 Censorship and the institution of knowledge in Bacon’s New Atlantis SIMON WORTHAM I Critical readers of Bacon’s New Atlantis have often drawn atten- tion to the complex relationship between, on the one hand, the production and dissemination of enlightened scientific know- ledge in Bensalem – and, indeed, the forms of social community for which it implicitly provides a model – and, on the other, the secret or concealed conditions of this very same process of pro- duction. For example, Robert K. Faulkner in Francis Bacon and the Project of Progress notes that, while ‘every official performs his function [and] everyone does what he is ordered,’ never- theless ‘all this order is the more remarkable since the relation of king, city, nation, state, and scientist is not clarified. The order that orders … is hidden.’1 Jerry Weinberger, meanwhile, argues that Bensalemite ‘science is shrouded in secrecy, denying the possibility of full enlightenment.’ Such secrecy surrounding the activities which contribute to the production of scientific know- ledge Weinberger reads in terms of, as he sees it, Bacon’s idea that ‘the politics of science must be secret and retired because only the most resolute souls will be willing to embrace such a world with full knowledge of its moral risks and dangers.’2 What these critics would appear to suggest, then, is that the production of various sorts of ground-breaking scientific knowledge and enlightened social relationships remain dependent, at bottom, upon a supplementary dose of censorship that simply cannot be dispensed Simon Wortham - 9781526137388 Downloaded from manchesterhive.com at 09/29/2021 04:11:19AM via free access Price_09_Ch9 180 14/10/02, 9:50 am Censorship and the institution of knowledge 181 with if the project of the Bensalemites is to persist and thrive.
    [Show full text]
  • Francis Bacon's
    Reconsideration Francis Bacon’s God Stephen A. McKnight Editor’s Note: With this issue, we are pleased to offer the first in our series of “Reconsiderations,” essays that reexamine great thinkers and great works at the intersection of science, technology, ethics, and politics. It is only fitting that we should launch this series with an analysis of Francis Bacon’s “New Atlantis,” the story that gave our journal its name and that helped give birth to the age of modern science and technology. n 1968 Howard B. White published Peace among the Willows, the first book-length analysis of Bacon’s “New Atlantis.” White, a political the- Iorist who regards Bacon as a principal shaper of modern political ideas, maintains that it is this utopian work and not one of Bacon’s philosophi- cal treatises that provides the fullest statement of Bacon’s political theory. White is especially interested in what he regards as Bacon’s secularization of politics and glorification of the power of science to serve the interests of the secular state. In developing his argument, White maintains that “New Atlantis” must be read with meticulous care in order to understand Bacon’s complex interweaving and transformation of political iconography, ancient history and fables, religious symbols, scientific methodologies, and pseudo- scientific concepts. White devotes considerable attention to Bacon’s use of religious themes and argues that he manipulates them in order to subvert Christian ideas and transform them into a culturally acceptable justifica- tion for a preoccupation with luxury and materialism. According to White, Bacon’s purpose is to transform the human quest from the search for the “heavenly city” to the creation of the well-governed country, and to change the philosophical quest from an effort to understand God, God’s Creation, and humanity’s place in it to a pursuit to understand what humans can make of themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and Politics in the New Atlantis
    60 Francis Bacon’s New Atlantis 4 Ethics and politics in the New Atlantis DAVID COLCLOUGH God forbid that we should give out a dream of our own imagination for a pattern of the world; rather may he graciously grant to us to write an apocalypse or true vision of the footsteps of the Creator imprinted on his creatures.1 I The New Atlantis is a text about natural philosophy which seems to offer connections at almost every point with moral and poli- tical philosophy. The celebrated description of Salomon’s House raises the question of the place of the scientist in society and the allusion to Plato’s Critias and Timaeus in the work’s title sug- gests an engagement with that philosopher’s description of the ideal state.2 Furthermore, a reference to More’s Utopia, together with the recognisably ‘utopian’ framework of the narrative, pro- mises responses to other ‘best state’ exercises, perhaps including Andreae’s Christianopolis (1619) and Campanella’s Civitas Solis (1623).3 Bacon’s own political activities are well known, and in successive editions of the Essays, as well as in his speeches and pieces of advice, he had shown himself willing and able to treat what he considered the most pressing issues of political and ethical theory and practical negotiation. Nor was this engagement halted by Bacon’s disgrace in 1621: in the years after his fall from office, he wrote a series of works which could be read as attempts to regain favour and political influence; the New Atlantis could David Colclough - 9781526137388 Downloaded from manchesterhive.com at 09/25/2021 05:26:55PM via free access Price_04_Ch4 60 14/10/02, 9:33 am Ethics and politics 61 well be read as an unfinished contribution to this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Francis Bacon's Alternative to More's ​Utopia
    FRANCIS BACON'S ALTERNATIVE TO MORE'S UTOPIA ​ CURRICULUM UNIT © CTMS Contents I. Thomas More's Utopia vs. Francis Bacon's New Atlantis ​ ​ ​ II. Study Questions III. Study Outline - Bacon's New Atlantis ​ IV. Text of New Atlantis ​ I. Thomas More's Utopia vs. Francis Bacon's New Atlantis In his New Atlantis, Bacon presents the first model society based on empirical science and on ​ ​ Machiavelli's critique of classical utopias. As such, he does not present a utopia (“no place”) as More did, but Bacon sets forth what he considers to be a realizable city of peace and prosperity founded on a scientifically inductive study of nature and of “humanity.” To appreciate the issues at stake in the difference between Thomas More’s Utopia and ​ ​ Bacon’s New Atlantis, you might consider books three and four of Jonathan Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels ​ ​ ​ as well as Swift’s “Battle of the Books.” In this battle between the “ancients” and the “moderns,” Swift sides with Thomas More while satirizing such enterprises as Bacon’s New Atlantis in the voyage ​ to Laputa and in the “pure reason” of the Houyhnhnms. In book three, Swift also praises More as one of the six great defenders of freedom of all time. What is the difference between an “ancient” utopia and a “modern” model of society? To help reflection on this issue, see the questions that follow as well as CTMS Study Questions on Utopia and Gulliver’s Travels. A download of the text of the New Atlantis, as well as PDF versions of ​ ​ ​ the questions and outline below are available on the Publications page.
    [Show full text]
  • Utopia and Education in the Seventeenth Century: Bacon's
    Utopia and education in the seventeenth century: Bacon’s 'Salomon’s House' and its influence Book or Report Section Accepted Version Houston, C. (2010) Utopia and education in the seventeenth century: Bacon’s 'Salomon’s House' and its influence. In: Houston, C. (ed.) New Worlds Reflected: Travel and Utopia in the Early Modern Period. Ashgate Publishing, pp. 161-178. ISBN 9780754666479 Available at http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/25441/ It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the work. See Guidance on citing . Publisher: Ashgate Publishing All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in the End User Agreement . www.reading.ac.uk/centaur CentAUR Central Archive at the University of Reading Reading’s research outputs online 1 Chapter 7 Utopia and Education in the Seventeenth Century: Bacon‟s Salomon‟s House and its Influence Chloë Houston Thomas More‟s Utopia of 1516, which became the foundation-stone of modern utopian literature, is a deeply ambiguous and ironic text. Its full title, De optimo reipublicae statu deque nova insula Utopia libellus vere aureus, nec minus salutaris quam festinus, clarissimi disertissimique viri Thomae Mori inclytae civitatis Londinesis civis et Vicecomitis, exemplifies Utopia‟s tendency to open questions rather than to resolve them. The title suggests that the book will give a description „of the best state of a commonwealth‟ and „of the new island of Utopia‟.
    [Show full text]
  • Humanism and Transhumanism Fred Baumann
    Humanism and Transhumanism Fred Baumann The name of the movement known as “transhumanism” may suggest that it arises out of humanism. At the very least, it is a descendant of what was once known as humanism, and could be seen as just one more utopian humanism. But the “trans” is the operative part of the term, and it should be taken seriously. Transhumanism is not simply utopian in the same way as the humanisms of Marx or B. F. Skinner; rather, it is qualitatively dif- ferent in that it “goes beyond,” avowedly disregarding and leaving behind human beings themselves — the very beings that were the central concern of all previous humanisms. The history of these humanisms is extraordinarily rich and complex. But because transhumanism cheerfully “transcends” all of it, we can cheerfully omit much of the detail here. In brief, humanism meant look- ing at the world from the point of view and the interests of the human being, as opposed to the subhuman (that is, the material or natural) or the superhuman (that is, the divine). In its most utopian forms, inspired by the technical possibilities of applied natural science, humanism sought the utter transformation of the world to fit human needs. Marx’s communism, however much he denied that it was utopian, is a good case in point. Marx understood that human beings would change in the new communist world — but he believed that the change would be of their own choice and in their own power. The world of communism would in fact be a realm of freedom instead of one in which external necessity ruled: a freely developed culture that would put an end to class war.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge Is Power. Francis Bacon's Theory of Ideology and Culture
    Knowledge is Power. Francis Bacon’s Theory of Ideology and Culture Ensaio Eugenio-Enrique Cortes-Ramirez|Universidad de Castilla (La Mancha, Spain) 1. Francis Bacon’s Theory of Idols as the Concept of Ideology’s Intellectual Precedent Human beings have conceived ideas as weapons that help to fulfil our desires or interests, rather than the discovery of truth. Francis Bacon established that, when a man wishes something were true, the more he readily believes it, the more mankind commonly talks of the wish as being father to the thought (White 22). Thinkers have always been aware that there have been several obstacles that had impeded their knowledge of the world. Most of these obstacles are located in the human being’s cognitive capacity itself. With the disintegration of medieval society, a new scientific approach to the knowledge of nature received impulse and began to supersede scholastic philosophy. In this way, theoretical contemplation of a hierarchical and sacred world was replaced by a conception that valued the practical function of thought. The development of trade, money exchange, secularised education, communities, cities, and so on, led to a new consideration of knowledge in its social and historical perspective (Houghton 48). An accurate and unprejudiced knowledge of nature is needed for it to be practically mastered, and this became the irresistible preoccupation of intellectuals. The new trends arise in opposition to the feudal system and its theological view of the world. The development of a precise knowledge of nature had been deeply limited, not just by some theocentric ideas such as the notion that human beings are essentially unable to conceive the world, but also by some artificial impediments that had prevented Citação: Eugenio-Enrique Cortes-Ramirez, “Knowledge is Power.
    [Show full text]
  • Order of Man, Order of Nature: Francis Bacon's Idea of a 'Dominion' Over
    ISSN 2045-5577 ORDER: GOD’S, MAN’S AND NATURE’S Order of man, order of nature: Francis Bacon’s idea of a 1 ‘dominion’ over nature E. Montuschi Abstract The image of man’s dominion over nature is deeply rooted in Western thought. It first appears, in different forms, in the Book of Genesis. It also reappears as one of the leading images of the emerging ‘new science’ in the 16th century. Francis Bacon puts particular emphasis on this image, which he takes to be the guiding principle of his new vision of science and practical knowledge. It is this vision which, as is widely acknowledged, will open the path to modern science. In what follows I will first sketch some relevant background for the emergence of this image. I will then analyse how the image takes shape in the context of Bacon’s philosophical project, paying attention to the novelties of his project but also to its continuities with tradition (especially Christian thought). It is indeed this mixture of past and future which suggests how natural order and human rule come to speak as one voice in the vision of the new science. Prologue: Man, nature and the ‘ideal garden’. Over the ages, Western thought has been variously concerned with the image of the ideal garden. At the same time, it has been rather eclectic in its illustration of what constitutes such an ideal. 2 If we look, for example, at the planning and construction of gardens in the 17th and then 18th/nineteenth centuries, we will soon and vividly appreciate these differences in conception.
    [Show full text]
  • Daedalus and Icarus Revisited Charles T
    Daedalus and Icarus Revisited Charles T. Rubin Doubts about the goodness of scientific and technological progress are hardly new, and fears about the dangers of human knowledge existed long before it became plausible to worry that the fate of the entire world might be in peril. The physicist Freeman Dyson offers one common—and very modern—way of describing our predicament: “Progress of science is destined to bring enormous confusion and misery to mankind unless it is accompanied by progress in ethics.” In other words, we need some novel ethic to match our technological ingenuity. But progress in ethics might also mean what Abraham Lincoln had in mind when describing the prin- ciples of the Declaration of Independence as “a standard maxim for free society … constantly looked to, constantly labored for, and even though never perfectly attained, constantly approximated.” Dyson’s idea suggests new ideals replacing old ones as history moves technologically forward; Lincoln’s idea suggests more permanent human aspirations that serve as the measure of different ages. Either meaning poses very serious chal- lenges. Genuinely novel ethics are not always genuine improvements, while many anciently articulated ethical goals remain elusive. The ambiguity in the meaning of moral progress is at the heart of a 1923 debate between biochemist J.B. S. Haldane and logician Bertrand Russell, two of the greatest and most argumentative public intellectuals of twentieth-century Britain. Haldane, who would go on to an extremely distinguished career as a biochemist and geneticist, spoke under the aus- pices of the Cambridge Heretics discussion club. Russell, already a famous philosopher, answered him as part of a speakers series sponsored by the Fabian Society under the general title, “Is Civilization Decaying?” The published version of Haldane’s remarks created no little controversy; even Albert Einstein had a copy in his library.
    [Show full text]
  • Salvation Through Science? Bacon's New Atlantis and Transhumanism
    Salvation Through Science? Bacon’s New Atlantis and Transhumanism David N. Whitney Nicholls State University The interplay between politics and science is certainly not a new phenomenon, but astonishing scientific advances in medicine and technology during the 20th century, and into the first two decades of the 21st, have forced us to reconsider that relationship. While those advances have led to unprecedented wealth and accumulation of material comforts, man’s increased control over nature also means he can destroy his fellow man with greater ease. Thus, in addition to penicillin, vaccinations for crippling diseases such as polio and smallpox, the mass production of the automobile, television, the internet and countless other beneficial inventions, the 20th century saw tens of millions die at the hands of their own governments.1 Atomic energy can provide power for a whole city, but the same technology can also be used to decimate that very city. Natural science gives us incredible power, but it does not provide any guidelines as to how that power should be used. Therefore, a series of questions must be raised as to the proper relationship between science and politics. Should governments control scientific research agendas? Should they determine what inventions to allow? And if so, how can such determinations be made? Who ultimately decides if a scientific advancement is good or bad for society? The answers to such questions go a long way in determining the role of science within a society. 1 R. J. Rummel has coined the term “democide” to refer to the Killing of citizens by their own governments.
    [Show full text]