Research Seminar Academic Style in Science and Research Course Syllabus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Research Seminar Academic Style in Science and Research Course Syllabus Research Seminar Academic Style in Science and Research Course Syllabus Lecturer: Dominic Rubin Seminar Teacher: Dominic Rubin Course Description Philosophy and Methodology of the Natural and Social Sciences is a one semester course for first year International Relations students. The course provides a broad introduction to the main themes and issues in the philosophy of science in general and the philosophy of social science in particular. It is principally concerned with the epistemological, logical, metaphysical and ethical underpinnings of scientific methodology. Fundamental philosophical questions are presented with a view to demonstrating how they are relevant to and how they inform scientific inquiry. The course explores topics such as, among others, the possibility of knowledge, the distinctiveness of science, the logic of scientific method, scientific explanation, whether science describes reality or not, whether social science should be based on the methods of natural science, the nature of practical rationality, the place of ethical values in relation to science, and critiques of scientific rationality. All topics are presented as problems and areas of dispute. Course Objectives Aside from providing an introduction to the principal questions explored by the philosophy of science and social science, the course aims to cultivate in students a critical awareness of the assumptions and conditions that lie behind scientific theories and arguments. Upon successful completion of the course, students should be able to analyse and judge the validity of an argument, construct extended coherent arguments that engage critically with the existing philosophical literature, apply and connect philosophical arguments to pertinent issues in the sciences (particularly in those disciplines that they are currently studying) and use the conceptual resource provided by the course to think logically, critically and independently. The particular content of the course is relevant to scientific study in general and the skills that the course develops are transferable and widely applicable in academic and professional life. The educational ethos of the course is to contribute to the development of the students’ faculty of autonomous critical reasoning rather than the robotic repetition of given information. Methods The methods and forms of study used on this course include lectures, seminars, teachers’ consultations and students’ own self-study. There is one weekly lecture and one weekly seminar. Each seminar is based on the contents of the preceding lecture. Seminar discussions encourage students to actively engage with the ideas presented in the lectures, a process that should clarify and deepen their understanding of the issues. Students must do a set preparatory reading before participating in a seminar. The forms of assessment used on the course include a two thousand-word essay, a five- minute presentation, a mark for seminar participation, and an end-of-course exam (a three-hour written exam in which students are to answer four exam essay questions). Main Reading 1. Godfrey-Smith, P., Theory and Reality: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2003). 2. Hollis, M., The Philosophy of Social Science: an Introduction, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994). 3. Ladyman, J., Understanding the Philosophy of Science, (London: Routledge, 2002). 4. Turner, S. P. and Roth, P. A. (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Social Science, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003). Supplementary Reading i. Losee, J., A Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001). ii. Machamer, P. and Silberstein, M. (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002). iii. Psillos, S., Philosophy of Science A – Z, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2007). iv. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Philosophy of Science, (London: Routledge, 1998). Internet Resources Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP): http://plato.stanford.edu/ Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (IEP): http://www.iep.utm.edu/ Grade Determination The final grade consists of the following four components: Exam 50% Essay 30% Presentation 10% Seminar participation 10% Course Outline 1. Knowledge as such What is knowledge? The challenge of scepticism. Rationalist, empiricist and constructivist approaches to epistemology. The problem of the criterion and responses to it. The relationship between philosophy and science; Quine’s epistemological naturalism and objections to it. (1, pp.149-155; 2, pp.23-93; 3, pp.5-14) 2. What is specific about science? The emergence of science. The shift from the Aristotelian teleological worldview to a mechanical one. Methodological distinctions between science and pre-science. The demarcation question between science and pseudo-science. Science and ideology. Popper on falsifiability. (1, pp.13-17, 57-74; 3, pp.62-6; i, pp.46-71) 3. The logic of scientific method in general: deduction and induction Deductive and inductive logical validity. The inductive and the hypothetico-deductive methods. The use of observations, theories, models and axioms. Attempts to develop a logic of induction. Inductive and abductive inference. (1, pp.19-46; 3, pp.14-30; i, pp.132-142) 4. The problem of induction and methodological alternatives Hume’s inductive scepticism. Paradoxes of confirmation: Hempel’s ‘raven’s paradox’; Goodman’s ‘new riddle of induction’. Justifications of induction (meta-inductive, pragmatic). The falsificationist alternative and problems with it. Quine’s confirmation holism. (1, pp.30-34, 46-56, 57-74; 2, pp.71-83; 3, pp.31-91) 5. Bayesian confirmation theory Evidence and probability. Subjectivist probability. How Bayesianism relates to the problem of induction. Objections to Bayesian epistemology. (1, pp.202-217; i, pp.220-227; ii, pp.149-172) 6. Scientific explanation Theories of explanation in science: Hempel’s covering law theory (both deductive- nomological and inductive-statistical versions); Salmon on statistical relevance and causation; Kitcher on unificationism. (1, pp.190-201; 3, pp.196-228; i, pp.210-21; ii, pp.37-54) 7. Laws of nature The place of ‘laws of nature’ in science. What is a law? Necessity versus regularity. The status of statistical laws. (iv, pp.211-215; IEP, SEP) 8. Realism and anti-realism Does science describe reality? Appearance and reality: the place of unobservables in science. Arguments in favour of realism. Forms of anti-realism: phenomenalism, instrumentalism, constructivism. The theory-ladenness of observation. The underdetermination of theory (Quine). Kuhn on the incommensurability of paradigms. (1, pp.173-189; 2, pp.50-59, 77-90; 3, pp.129-194; i, pp.252-263) 9. Scientific change and progress Cumulative continuity versus discontinuity in theories of scientific change. Bachelard and Kuhn on epistemological breaks and paradigm shifts. Kuhn on normal and revolutionary science. Lakatos on research programmes. Laudan on problem-solving. (1, pp.75-110; 2, pp.84-90; 3, pp.93-123; i, pp.197-209) 10. The specificities of social science Positivism, social scientific naturalism and the unity of science. Dilthey and Weber on meaningfulness and social ‘understanding’. Interpretivism: causes and reasons, explaining and understanding. (2, pp.142-162, 183-201; 4, pp.311-333) 11. Rational agency Social action as rational behaviour. What is rationality? Instrumental reason: rational choice theory; game theory; decision theory. Alternatives to the instrumental conception of rationality, e.g. Habermas’s communicative reason. (2, pp.115-141; 4, pp.110-165) 12. Methodological individualism versus holism Individuals versus structures: conflicting social ontologies and their methodological consequences. Functional explanations and specifically social facts. Self and roles, social and personal identity. Ideological assumptions and implications involved in the methodological debates on the issue. (2, pp.94-114, pp.163-182; SEP) 13. Science and normativity The distinction between facts and values (Hume, Moore). The questioning of this (Dewey, Laudan). The possibility of a value-neutral social science. Weber on value-freedom and value- relevance. Critiques of the supposed value-neutrality of the social and human sciences (the Frankfurt School, Foucault). The norms of science and the scientific community (Merton). (1, pp.122-125; 2, pp.202-223; IEP) 14. The limits of scientific rationality Heidegger on scientific objectification and the forgetting of being. Adorno and Horkheimer on the dialectic of Enlightenment. Derrida on logocentrism. Lyotard on meta-narratives and incommensurable language-games. Feyerabend’s epistemological anarchism. Paradoxes and paraconsistent logic. (1, pp.110-117; iv, pp.172-175; SEP; IEP) Distribution of hours for topics and types of work No Topic Total Lectures Classes Self-study 1. Knowledge as such 8 2 2 4 2. What is specific about science? 8 2 2 4 3. The logic of scientific method in general: 8 2 2 4 deduction and induction 4. The problem of induction and methodological 16 4 4 8 alternatives 5. Bayesian confirmation theory 8 2 2 4 No Topic Total Lectures Classes Self-study 6. Scientific explanation 8 2 2 4 7. Laws of nature 8 2 2 4 8. Realism and anti-realism 8 2 2 4 9. Scientific change and progress 8 2 2 4 10. The specificities of social science 8 2 2 4 11. Rational agency 8 2 2 4 12. Methodological individualism versus holism 8 2 2 4 13. Science and normativity 8 2 2 4 14. The limits of scientific rationality 16 4 4 8 Total 128 32 32 64 .
Recommended publications
  • Holism and Compositionality
    Holism and Compositionality Francis Jeffry Pelletier 1 Introduction A brief acquaintance with the web shows that the terms ‘holism’1 and ‘compositionality’ are used in many different fields, both academic and non-academic. And given any two academic fields, it is usually not obvious that the terms mean the same to the practitioners. Even just within philosophy and linguistics it seems that rather different conceptions are in play when we read any two different authors. We start, therefore, with a brief survey of some of the senses in which these terms are used. A little later we will make some more careful remarks about the notions. 1.1 Two Kinds of Compositionality A recent interdisciplinary conference revealed that there are (at least) two different things that are thought of when the issue of compositionality is considered. One concerns a (generalized) notion of “what is a complex item (of my theory) made of?” Here are a few places where this notion arose: Prototypes: Current prototype theory says that a prototype is a structure that has a number of attribute-value pairs. A question of interest in this area is: Given that prototype-1 has a structure [A: value-a; B: value-b; . ] and that prototype-2 has the structure [C: value-c; D: value-d . ], is the prototype of the “combined prototypes” (that is, the conceptual combination of the two proto- types) made up only from the material in the two component prototypes, that is, from the attribute-value pairs that are in one or the other of the prototypes? 1 ‘Whole’, and presumably also ’hole’, is derived from the Greek .
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Examination of Quinean Naturalism______A Closer Look at Quine’S Naturalized Epistemology
    A Critical Examination of Quinean Naturalism_________ A Closer Look at Quine’s Naturalized Epistemology Ashley Spring Florida Atlantic University We always speak from within a theory, a system of the world. There is no neutral or presuppositionless position from which we can make judgments about the world and our theory of it: all of our judgments must be evaluated as being part of a substantive theory of the world. In particular our philosophical remarks are made from within such a theory. —Peter Hylton Introduction The resources of traditional epistemology have been exhausted. The result is the necessary paradigmatic shift from ‘first philosophy’ to a more plausible, and albeit, naturalized enterprise. W.V. Quine’s shift towards naturalizing epistemology serves as a catalyst for epistemic inquiry through the inclusion of the natural sciences in epistemology. In so naturalizing epistemology, Quine does not view epistemology as a prior or foundational discipline that can be justified a priori but rather, as an integral part of our web of beliefs about the world. 1 Such a radical departure from the foundationalist program better captures our epistemic aims by focusing on the resources found in the natural sciences relative to knowledge acquisition. This paper will provide a critical examination of Quiean naturalism through a close examination of Quine’s “Epistemology Naturalized.” Indeed, through this critical examination of Quine’s epistemological project, we should see how Quine’s naturalized epistemology serves as a radical yet, practical starting point for epistemic inquiry, along with how such a naturalized shift establishes a more philosophically plausible approach to epistemology.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics, Time, and Confirmation
    Mathematics, Time, and Confirmation Ulrich Meyer Doctor of Philosophy in Mathematics University of Cambridge, 1995 Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy in partial fulfil- ment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. September 2001 Author: ................................. .. .... Department of Linguistics aKPhilosophy August 10, 2001 Certified by: .......................... Robert C. Stalnaker Professor of Philosophy Thesis Supervisor Accepted by: .............. Vann McGee Professor of Philosophy Chair, Committee on Graduate Students @Ulrich Meyer 2001. All rights reserved. The author hereby grants permission to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology to reproduce and distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis in whole or in part. MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY OCT 11 2001 ARCMly LIBRARIES Mathematics, Time, and Confirmation by Ulrich Meyer Submitted to The Department of Linguistics and Philosophy on 10 August 2001 in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy ABSTRACT This dissertation discusses two issues about abstract objects: their role in scientific theories, and their relation to time. Chapter 1, "Why Apply Mathematics?" argues that scientific theories are not about the mathematics that is applied in them, and defends this thesis against the Quine-Putnam Indispensability Argument. Chapter 2, "Scientific Ontology," is a critical study of W. V. Quine's claim that metaphysics and mathematics are epistemologically on a par with nat- ural science. It is argued that Quine's view relies on a unacceptable account of empirical confirmation. Chapter 3, "Prior and the Platonist," demonstrates the incompatibility of two popular views about time: the "Platonist" thesis that some objects exist "outside" time, and A.
    [Show full text]
  • Quine's Revolution: Epistemological Holism in Science and Philosophy
    Quine’s Revolution: Epistemological Holism in Science and Philosophy David Paul Boaz To be is to be the value of a bound variable. —W. V. Quine “On What There Is”: Quine’s Ontological Relativity. Willard Van Orman Quine (1908– 2000) is considered by many in the philosophy trade to be the most important American philosopher of the 20th century. His Ontological Relativity (indeterminacy of reference, indeterminacy of translation) is the thesis that ontology—”what there is”—is relative to language, that is, to the subjective deep background reality assumptions in our individual and collective “web of belief” as it arises and is instantiated in language. (Epistemology is how we know what there is. There are no objective facts, only linguistic meanings.) In his seminal “Ontological Relativity” (1969) Quine develops his thesis that when a theory postulates its existent entities in a given language—its “object language”—it does so by translating its theory’s propositions (statements) about those entities into a more inclusive “meta-language,” langue (Saussure), or background matrix or web of prior assumptions and beliefs. The ontological status of entities or objects of the object language are relative to and supervene or are dependent upon the intersubjective prior cognitive “coordinate grid” that are the assumptions and beliefs of the meta-language into which they are translated. Unfortunately, through ontology is minimized, Quine’s personal ontological flavor is Physicalism. It’s all just physical, which explains his epistemology, namely empiricism and naturalism. Quine was never able to shake the imperious physicalist doctrine of his early teacher Rudolf Carnap and the Vienna Circle of the Logical Positivists.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Quine a Verificationist?
    Appeared in: The Southern Journal of Philosophy Vol. XLI, 2003. IS QUINE A VERIFICATIONIST? Panu Raatikainen I Although Quine is widely known as an influential critic of logical positivism, there is now a growing tendency to emphasize the similarities between him and the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle.1 In particular, it has become usual to classify Quine as an adherent of verificationism, even if it is recognized that his position is somehow different from that of the positivists in being more holistic in character.2 For example, Cheryl Misak in her book-length examination of verificationism writes that ‘the holist [such as Quine] need not reject verificationism, if it is suitably formulated. Indeed, Quine often describes himself as a verificationist’.3 Misak concludes that Quine ‘can be described as a verificationist who thinks that the unit of meaning is large’;4 and when comparing Dummett and Quine, Misak states that ‘both can be, and in fact are, verificationists’.5 Further, it is remarkable that Roger Gibson, arguably the leading expositor of Quine’s philosophy, whose understanding of Quine’s thought has been repeatedly praised by Quine himself, interprets Quine unqualifiedly as a verificationist. Gibson speaks of ‘Quine’s explicit commitment to verificationism’.6 He cites as evidence the following well-known passage 1 from Quine’s famous article ‘Epistemology Naturalized’: ‘If we recognize with Peirce that the meaning of a sentence turns on what would count as evidence for its truth, and if we recognize with Duhem that theoretical sentences have their evidence not as single sentences but as larger blocks of theory, then the indeterminacy of translation is the natural conclusion.’7 And Gibson continues: ‘If this quotation leaves a lingering doubt as to whether Quine would really call himself a verificationist, the following quotation should erase all doubt’.
    [Show full text]
  • Confirmation Holism and Underdetermination in Quine's
    Filosofi a Unisinos 13(2):96-113, may/aug 2012 © 2012 by Unisinos – doi: 10.4013/fsu.2012.132.01 Confirmation Holism and Underdetermination in Quine’s Thought Holismo confirmacional e subdeterminação no pensamento de Quine Rogério Passos Severo1 Universidade Federal de Santa Maria Abstract Quine is frequently acknowledged as one of the main proponents of both confi rmation holism and underdetermination. In the recent literature, however, his views have been often criticized and misrepresented: the distinction between the two theses has been often blurred, the obviousness of holism has been rejected, and the plausibility of underdetermination has come under attack. This paper attempts to formulate both theses as clearly as possible and to defend Quine’s views against some recurrent criticisms. In particular, it is argued that Quine’s theses are signifi cantly weaker than they have been taken to be and that only confi rmation holism, but not underdetermination, plays a fundamental role in his philosophy. Key words: confi rmation holism, underdetermination, Quine. Resumo Quine é frequentemente reconhecido como um dos principais proponentes tanto do holismo confi rmacional quanto da subdeterminação. Na literatura recente, entretanto, suas concepções têm sido com frequência criticadas e representadas de forma distorcida: a distinção entre as duas teses tem sido com frequência ofuscada, o caráter óbvio do holismo tem sido rejeitado e a plausibilidade da subdeterminação tem sido atacada. Este artigo tenta reformular ambas as teses tão claramente quanto possível e defende a concepção de Quine contra lgumas críticas recorrentes. Em particular, argumenta-se que as teses de Quine são signifi cativamente mais fracas do que têm sido sido interpretadas, e que apenas o holismo confi rmacional, mas não a subdeterminação, desempenha um papel fundamental em sua fi losofi a.
    [Show full text]
  • Copyright by Brian Townsend Miller 2016 the Dissertation Committee for Brian Townsend Miller Certifies That This Is the Approved Version of the Following Dissertation
    Copyright by Brian Townsend Miller 2016 The Dissertation Committee for Brian Townsend Miller certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: The Structure of Perceptual Justification Committee: Ernest David Sosa, Supervisor Josh Dever Sinan Dogramaci James Pryor Richard Mark Sainsbury Miriam Schoenfield The Structure of Perceptual Justification by Brian Townsend Miller, B.A.; M.A. DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of The University of Texas at Austin in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY THE UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS AT AUSTIN August 2016 Dedicated to Julie and Neva. Acknowledgments A beginning graduate student asked me which faculty members I find to be especially helpful to work with. After answering I realized that I’d just named the members of my dissertation committee: David Sosa, Josh Dever, Sinan Dogramaci, Jim Pryor, Mark Sainsbury, and Miriam Schoenfield. I thank you all for your insights, your encouragement, and your patience. Warm thanks to my parents, Ron and Nell, who nurtured the curiosity that drives me. v The Structure of Perceptual Justification Publication No. Brian Townsend Miller, Ph.D. The University of Texas at Austin, 2016 Supervisor: Ernest David Sosa When does a perceptual experience as of my hands provide justification for me to believe that I have hands? One initially plausible positive require- ment is that I must have reasons to believe something else: that my experience is veridical. Also plausible is the negative requirement that I must not have reasons to believe that my experience is in this case non-veridical.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Method
    Philosophy 2233 : Intuitions and Philosophy Hamilton College Fall 2011 Russell Marcus Class 6 - Scientific Method I. Holism, Reflective Equilibrium, and Science Our course is centrally concerned with methodology in philosophy. We started by looking at foundationalist epistemologies, and a bit at coherentist ones, in order to examine the ultimate methods of justification for our beliefs. We have found two sorts of problems with foundationalist theories. The first kind of problem involved particular choices of foundational beliefs. Perhaps Descartes just took the wrong axioms. Perhaps sense-data are not the ultimate atomic facts. These problems seemed worrisome, but not fatal to the foundationalist attitude. Better choices of foundations could ameliorate such worries. The second kind of problem was more profound, and arose in two directions. The color incompatibility problem led us to Sellars’s insights about the myth of the given. According to the foundationalist, our atomic beliefs are supposed to be immediately, or self, justifying. If there are no self-justifying givens, then there are no immediately-perceivable, atomic facts. There are two kinds of resultant holism. Semantic holism is the thesis that meaning is a property of entire languages (or at least large swaths of language). Confirmation holism is the thesis that a statement is neither confirmed nor refuted by itself, but presupposes a larger theory. From another direction, Goodman argued that justifications for induction and deduction follow the same patterns. He noticed that we accept certain general principles because they yield the specific claims we believe. We justify those beliefs because they are derived from acceptable general principles.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 412 / 510 – Philosophy of Science A. Course Overview And
    PHIL 412 / 510 – Philosophy of Science Fall Term 2011 Tue, Thu 2:00–3:20 pm, Assiniboia Hall 2-02A Instructor: Ingo Brigandt E-mail: [email protected] Phone: 780-492-3307 ext. 12 (voicemail only) Office: 3-49 Assiniboia Hall Office hours: Mon, Wed 2:10–3:00 pm, and by appointment Website at https://eclass.srv.ualberta.ca A. Course overview and aims The aim of this class is to give an advanced overview of most major topics in contemporary philosophy of science. To this end, we will read and discuss influential articles from the primary literature written in the last decades, grouped around several core topics. We start out with various issues pertaining to the confirmation of theories by evidence, including the problem of induction, Popper’s falsificationism, confirmation holism (the Duhem-Quine problem), Kuhnian incommensurability, Bayesian confirmation theory, and the underdeter- mination of theory by evidence. The next basic topic is realism vs. antirealism, where we cover arguments for realism, van Fraassen’s anti-realism (constructive empiricism), and the pessimistic meta-induction. After a short discussion of the nature of scientific laws, we move to the next topic—explanation. To be discussed are the Hempel-Oppenheim model (originally widely accepted but then criticized and abandoned), Salmon’s statistical relevance model, the related issue of intertheory reduction, and causal-mechanistic accounts as the most recent approaches to scientific explanation (which have also been used to go beyond the reduction–antireduction dichotomy). The class concludes with a look at scientific practice, uncovering a vital and recent perspective in philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Indispensability Arguments and Mathematical Explanation in Science
    Indispensability Arguments and Mathematical Explanation in Science A thesis submitted by Josephine Marie Salverda in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of MPhil Stud in Philosophical Studies at University College London. 1 I, Josephine Marie Salverda, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 Abstract The aim of this thesis is to find a way to undermine the indispensability argument for mathematical platonism. In chapter 1 I provide a brief survey of the indispensability argument, arguing that the explanatory indispensability argument is stronger than earlier forms of the argument. This is because it has less controversial premises, appealing neither to confirmational holism nor to a strong naturalism but rather to inference to the best explanation, a principle of inference which both sides in the indispensability debate are taken to accept. Hence I take the explanatory indispensability argument as my target. In chapter 2, I provide a more detailed account of the way in which inference to the best explanation, or IBE, is involved in the explanatory indispensability argument. I present two readings of the argument, rejecting the first reading and arguing that a second reading, which involves an instance of IBE, is the most plausible. Chapter 3 considers whether there are genuine cases of mathematical explanation in science, focusing on an explanation from evolutionary biology provided by Alan Baker. I draw on the biological literature to argue that there is some reason to doubt that Baker's explanation meets the conditions for a successful application of IBE.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 6 ESCAPE from the HUMEAN PREDICAMENT As We
    CHAPTER 6 ESCAPE FROM THE HUMEAN PREDICAMENT As we discovered in the previous chapter, a number of critics contend that Quine has no serious reply to the skeptic, and that his view itself leads to skepticism. Quine has an interesting response to this attack: because skeptical doubts themselves arise within science, we can conclude that the skeptic is “overreacting.” The aim of this chapter is to propose a new anti-skeptical strategy inspired by this response, one that can even be used against skeptical elements of Quine’s own philosophy, and at least in part against other prominent forms of skepticism in the empiricist tradition. One of Quine’s examples of the scientific nature of skeptical doubt concerns forms of the argument from illusion. Quine points out that these cases presuppose an understanding of “veridical” perception of reality, in contrast to which some cases are understood as “illusory.” Another example is the doubt stemming from the discovery of the retinal image, and the worry about how three- dimensional awareness can result from projection on a two-dimensional surface. Quine points out that even this worry presupposes an understanding of a three-dimensional eye in a three-dimensional world. As I have noted in chapter 5, it looks like Quine does not take these points to establish that skepticism is somehow incoherent. He writes that the skeptic “is quite within his rights in assuming science in order to refute science; this, if carried out, would be a straightforward argument by reductio ad absurdum” (1975b, 68). Quine’s claim that he is only criticizing the skeptic’s overreaction (rather than any incoherence) leads critics such as Stroud (1984) and Williams (1996) to suggest that Quine is trying to use science to defuse the skeptic’s reductio: if the skeptic has the right to assume science at the outset of a reductio, then anti-skeptic also has the right to show how full consideration of science blocks this reductio, by showing that skeptical absurdities are merely apparent, arising only from scientific assumptions made in isolation from others.
    [Show full text]
  • Holism About Fact and Value Kenny Walden
    Holism about Fact and Value Kenny Walden “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” has two projects, one negative and one pos- itive. The negative project is an attack on Carnap’s distinction between internal and external questions, which Quine undertakes with an argument against the ana- lytic/synthetic distinction. The positive project is to sketch an alternative picture of the dynamics of inquiry, a picture of how science looks without Carnap’s dichot- omy. In place of Carnap’s bifurcated science of evidence and conventional frame- work, Quine gives us a holistic science suffused with both fact and convention. Knowledge, as he says elsewhere, is “a fabric of sentences [which] develops and changes, through more or less arbitrary and deliberate revisions and additions of our own, more or less directly occasioned by the continuing stimulation of our sense organs. It is a pale grey lore, black with fact and white with convention. But I have found no substantial reasons for concluding that there are any quite black threads in it, or any white ones.”1 When joined with a mild form of methodological naturalism, this “Quinean holism” leads to a distinctive approach to metaphysics, epistemology, and seman- tics. It does not necessarily entail particular first-order doctrines in these fields but prescribes a uniformity of regard. The thought is that once we appreciate this ho- lism, we see that there are no good grounds for distinguishing between different parts of the “web of belief”—of saying that sector A of the web is substantive, while sector B is merely conventional, that sector C aims to represent the world while sector D is merely expressive, or that the objects of quantification for sector E gen- uinely exist, while those of F are mere posits.
    [Show full text]