Scientific Modeling Without Representationalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Scientific Modeling Without Representationalism Scientific Modeling Without Representationalism A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Cincinnati in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) in the Department of Philosophy of the College of Arts and Sciences by Guilherme SANCHES DE OLIVEIRA M.A. University of São Paulo, 2014 M.A. University of Cincinnati, 2017 Commitee Chair: Angela POTOCHNIK, Ph.D. August 23, 2019 i Abstract Scientists often gain insight into real-world phenomena indirectly, through building and manipulating models. But what accounts for the epistemic import of model-based research? Why can scientists learn about real-world systems (such as the global climate or biological populations) by interacting not with the real-world systems themselves, but with computer simulations and mathematical equations? The traditional answer is that models teach us about certain real-world phenomena because they represent those phenomena. My dissertation challenges this representationalist intuition and provides an alternative framework for making sense of scientific modeling. The philosophical debate about scientific model-based representation has, by and large, proceeded in isolation from the debate about mental representation in philos- ophy of mind and cognitive science. Chapter one exposes and challenges this anti- psychologism. Drawing from ‘wide computationalist’ embodied cognitive science re- search, I put forward an account of scientific models as socially-distributed and materially- extended mental representations. This account illustrates how views on mental rep- resentation can help advance philosophical understanding of scientific representation, while raising the question of how other views from (embodied) cognitive science might inform philosophical theorizing about scientific modeling. Chapter two argues that representationalism is untenable because it relies on on- tological and epistemological assumptions that undermine one another no matter the theory of representation adopted. Views of scientific representation as mind-independent fail with the ontological claim that ‘models represent their targets’ and thereby un- dermine the epistemological claim that ‘we learn from models because they represent ii their targets’. On the other hand, views of scientific representation as mind-dependent support the ontological claim, but they do so in a way that also undermines the epis- temological claim: if ‘representation’ entails only use rather than success or accuracy, then the epistemic value of modeling cannot be explained purely in representational terms. Chapter three focuses on emerging “artifactualist” views of models as tools, arti- facts, and instruments. The artifactualism of current accounts is a conciliatory view that is compatible with representationalism and merely promotes a shift in emphasis in theorizing. I argue against this version of artifactualism (which I call “weak artifac- tualism”), and I put forward an alternative formulation free from representationalism (“strong artifactualism”). Strong artifactualism is not only desirable, but it’s also viable and promising as an approach to making sense of how we learn through modeling. Chapter four draws from ecological psychology to offer an empirically-informed account of modeling as a tool-building practice. I propose that the epistemic worth of modeling is best understood in terms of the “affordances” that the practice gives rise to for suitably-positioned embodied cognitive agents. This account develops a strong ar- tifactualist view of models (chapter three) and it circumvents the challenges inherent to representationalism (chapter two) because it anchors the epistemic worth of modeling in the models’ affordances, which are agent-relative but mind-independent. Moreover, this account provides an additional reason to give up anti-psychologism in philoso- phy: not only can views on mental representation help us better understand scientific representation (chapter one), but anti-representational views in psychology can also inform a nonrepresentational understanding of how and why modeling works. iii c 2019 Guilherme Sanches de Oliveira All rights reserved iv Acknowledgements In the sciences and in philosophy of science, we use the term “model” to refer to a computational, mathematical or concrete object that’s designed and used to facilitate learning about some other object, typically a system or phenomenon in the real world that’s the ultimate “target” of investigation: in this technical sense, philosophers often think of models as imitations or copies of that target. But this is exactly the opposite of how we use the term in ordinary contexts: in real life, a “model” is the thing to be imitated, not the thing that’s imitating something else. It is in this ordinary sense of the term that I want to acknowledge and thank my models—the people I have been working hard to learn from, whose virtues I will continue trying to emulate. My committee chair, Angela Potochnik, is my model of intellectual insight and gen- erosity. Angela was the first person to get excited about my dissertation, and I mean that literally: she was excited about my dissertation even before I knew what it was going to be about. She saw potential in the very first paper I wrote in my very first semester at UC, and she encouraged me to keep developing those still rudimentary ideas. Over the course of five years, she was always open to reading my nonsense and giving it the benefit of the doubt. Angela’s generosity was, of course, evident in the feedback she would give me, which was always timely, rigorous, and abundant. But I want to emphasize her generosity in supporting my professional development: the countless letters of recommendation (for grants, awards, fellowships, workshops, sum- mer schools, jobs, you name it); the opportunities to learn new skills (including LATEX), v to get involved in cool initiatives (PhilPapers, the Center for Public Engagement with Science), and to collaborate in research (co-authored paper forthcoming!); and all the advice, which I’m slowly coming to understand (e.g., learning when and what to say “no” to). For all of this and so much more, thank you! I’m lucky to have found a mentor in Tony Chemero, my interdisciplinary hero, the person who not only told me but also showed me that it’s possible to do good phi- losophy and good science all at once. Being around Tony made me realize that pretty much all of my clever ideas had already been had by pragmatists and phenomenolo- gists, and that turning to them could help dissolve my philosophical problems. Tony also helped me see the light and embrace the teachings of St. Jimmy (while always keeping a healthy dose of scientific skepticism!), and for this I will be forever grate- ful. Even though he’s a rockstar (or karate master?), Tony is always ready to share the spotlight with his students, and that speaks volumes about his character. Completing my committee, Tom Polger and Mike Richardson deserve recognition for their continued support. Tom gave me feedback on the first version of the paper that would become the basis for my dissertation and also on the first related conference presentation at the SSPP meeting in New Orleans; his (hard!) questions, since back then, have helped me avoid going down quite a few rabbit holes. Mike’s insight and encouragement, coming from the perspective of a modeler and ecological psychologist, made me believe in my project’s potential beyond disciplinary confines. My time at UC would not have been as productive and stimulating if it weren’t for all the amazing people I got to work with here. For their guidance, I thank the faculty in philosophy (especially Zvi Biener, John McEvoy, Jenefer Robinson, and Rob Skip- per), in psychology (especially Paula Silva, Kevin Shockley, Mike Riley, and Tehran vi Davis), and in the Graduate School (Steve Howe, David Stradling, and Mike Riley again). For their support and company, I thank good friends and colleagues in philos- ophy (especially Frank Faries, Valentina Petrolini, Walter Stepanenko, Sahar Heydari Fard, Mohan Pillai, and Jonathan McKinney), in psychology (especially Chris Riehm, Patric Nordbeck, Colin Annand, Francis Grover, Ed Baggs, and Patrick Nalepka), and, in both literal and metaphorical walks back and forth between McMicken and Ed- wards, my buddy Vicente Raja. Vesna Kocani deserves special thanks for her work behind the scenes, keeping everything running smoothly. I am indebted to Osvaldo Pessoa Jr. and to Caetano Plastino (University of São Paulo) for introducing me to philosophy of science, philosophy of mind and cognitive science. I am also indebted to Otávio Bueno (University of Miami) and Nancy Ners- essian (Georgia Tech) for their advice as I tried to figure out how to continue studying philosophy at the graduate level. Working on and completing a Ph.D. takes a lot of time and energy. I wouldn’t have been able to pour so much of myself into this project if it weren’t for my mom, my ultimate model of perseverance and unwavering optimism. My mom lost her parents at fifteen, and had to drop out of high school to work full time; years later, a failed marriage and a divorce made it so that she had to raise my sister and me all by her- self. Despite having gone through so many challenges in life (or, somehow, because of them), she has this resolutely positive outlook: if you work hard enough, things may still not turn out the way you wanted, but you’ll be okay. I’m not sure I totally buy that, but I am grateful that my mom does and that she worked hard so that I could have the educational opportunities she didn’t; her grit continues to be a source of inspiration. I dedicate this accomplishment to Maggie, who—along with Grafite, Friendly & vii Bijoux, Pulla & Snuffkin, all the chickens, and the occasional groundhog, fox and coy- ote—ensured that life, even during the PhD, was full and whole.
Recommended publications
  • Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238. Denying a Dualism: Goodman’s Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Catherine Z. Elgin The analytic synthetic/distinction forms the backbone of much modern Western philosophy. It underwrites a conception of the relation of representations to reality which affords an understanding of cognition. Its repudiation thus requires a fundamental reconception and perhaps a radical revision of philosophy. Many philosophers believe that the repudiation of the analytic/synthetic distinction and kindred dualisms constitutes a major loss, possibly even an irrecoverable loss, for philosophy. Nelson Goodman thinks otherwise. He believes that it liberates philosophy from unwarranted restrictions, creating opportunities for the development of powerful new approaches to and reconceptions of seemingly intractable problems. In this article I want to sketch some of the consequences of Goodman’s reconception. My focus is not on Goodman’s reasons for denying the dualism, but on some of the ways its absence affects his position. I do not contend that the Goodman obsessed over the issue. I have no reason to think that the repudiation of the distinction was a central factor in his intellectual life. But by considering the function that the analytic/synthetic distinction has performed in traditional philosophy, and appreciating what is lost and gained in repudiating it, we gain insight into Goodman’s contributions. I begin then by reviewing the distinction and the conception of philosophy it supports. The analytic/synthetic distinction is a distinction between truths that depend entirely on meaning and truths that depend on both meaning and fact. In the early modern period, it was cast as a distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Logic 2018 Course Description (Tentative) January 15, 2018
    Philosophical Logic 2018 Course description (tentative) January 15, 2018 Valentin Goranko Introduction This 7.5 hp course is mainly intended for students in philosophy and is generally accessible to a broad audience with basic background on formal classical logic and general appreciation of philosophical aspects of logic. Practical information The course will be given in English. It will comprise 18 two-hour long sessions combining lectures and exercises, grouped in 2 sessions per week over 9 teaching weeks. The weekly pairs of 2-hour time slots (incl. short breaks) allocated for these sessions, will be on Mondays during 10.00-12.00 and 13.00-15.00, except for the first lecture. The course will begin on Wednesday, April 4, 2018 (Week 14) at 10.00 am in D220, S¨odra huset, hus D. Lecturer's info: Name: Valentin Goranko Email: [email protected] Homepage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko Course webpage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko/Courses2018/PhilLogic-2018.html Prerequisites The course will be accessible to a broad audience with introductory background on classical formal logic. Some basic knowledge of modal logics would be an advantage but not a prerequisite. Brief description Philosophical logic studies a variety of non-classical logical systems intended to formalise and reason about various philosophical concepts and ideas. They include a broad family of modal logics, as well as many- valued, intuitionistic, relevant, conditional, non-monotonic, para-consistent, etc. logics. Modal logics extend classical logic with additional intensional logical operators, reflecting different modes of truth, including alethic, epistemic, doxastic, temporal, deontic, agentive, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy †
    Proceedings Philosophical Analysis on the Nature and Forms of Information—From the Perspective of Marxist Philosophy † Mingfang Feng 1 and Liang Feng 2,* 1 School of Economics & Law, Shaanxi University of Technology, No.1, First Eastern Ring Road, Hanzhong 723001, China; [email protected] 2 School of Marxism Studies, Xi’an Jiaotong University, No.28 Xianning West Road, Xi’an 710049, China * Correspondence: [email protected] † Presented at the IS4SI 2017 Summit DIGITALISATION FOR A SUSTAINABLE SOCIETY, Gothenburg, Sweden, 12–16 June 2017. Published: 8 June 2017 Abstract: The aim of this research essay attempt to reveal the nature of information form the perspective of Marxist Philosophy. The nature of Information is the first question that philosophy of information science and technology research must be answered, thus the problem is still debated. According to Marxist dialectical materialism method to the essence of information has made the analysis and argumentation, points out the essence of information between what is and its internal contact things, and this contact information is presented. Due to the connection between the protean and endless things, thus produce the endless, full of beautiful things in eyes, each are not identical information. To grasp the nature of information, must pay attention to and the specific form of information and information processing, the reorganization, transmission, storage, use and so on. Keywords: information; nature; connection; philosophy of information 1. Introduction The development of information science and technology has spar ked the nature of information exploration after World War II. The question that ‘What is the nature of information?’ is always unable to avoid in information science and philosophical technology research.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tyranny of Method: a Pragmatic Defense of Philosophical Pluralism
    THE TYRANNY OF METHOD: A PRAGMATIC DEFENSE OF PHILOSOPHICAL PLURALISM Vincent M. Colapietro Abstract: The history of philosophy is in no small measure a series of attempts to institute a fail-safe method. In response to what they take to be the scandal of disagreement (disagreement itself being judged as scandalous), a number of historically influential philosophers (e.g., Descartes, Peirce, Husserl, and Carnap) have time and again tried to craft a method for guaranteeing agreement. In light of the failure of these attempts, this tendency might be seen as remotely analogous to what is called in psychoanalytic parlance a “repetition compulsion.” In any event, historical reflections on this repeated tendency promise to be illuminating. But there is a polemical purpose animating these historical reflections. The author tries, in light of these reflections, to render plausible the suggestion that this tendency amounts to a tyranny of method and, in turn, such tyranny results in an inevitable impoverishment of philosophical thought. THE TOPIC of my essay is best brought into focus by recalling a central figure in the history of Western philosophy. 1 This recollection is, however, far from methodologically innocent. My deliberate turn toward a pivotal moment in our intellectual history – in brief, my turn toward history – will provide the basis for my critique of what I am disposed to identify as the tyranny of method. This tyranny is not so much exercised by any particular method as by the repeated impulse to institute a philosophical method of allegedly revolutionary significance. Most often, this impulse is bound up with the hope that philosophy can transform itself into a science (an unquestionable form of certain knowledge) either by adopting the method of science itself (e.g., the efforts of C.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium: the Ethics of Desire
    Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire FRISBEE C. C. SHEFFIELD 1 Contents Introduction 1 1. Ero¯s and the Good Life 8 2. Socrates’ Speech: The Nature of Ero¯s 40 3. Socrates’ Speech: The Aim of Ero¯s 75 4. Socrates’ Speech: The Activity of Ero¯s 112 5. Socrates’ Speech: Concern for Others? 154 6. ‘Nothing to do with Human AVairs?’: Alcibiades’ Response to Socrates 183 7. Shadow Lovers: The Symposiasts and Socrates 207 Conclusion 225 Appendix : Socratic Psychology or Tripartition in the Symposium? 227 References 240 Index 249 Introduction In the Symposium Plato invites us to imagine the following scene: A pair of lovers are locked in an embrace and Hephaestus stands over them with his mending tools asking: ‘What is it that you human beings really want from each other?’ The lovers are puzzled, and he asks them again: ‘Is this your heart’s desire, for the two of you to become parts of the same whole, and never to separate, day or night? If that is your desire, I’d like to weld you together and join you into something whole, so that the two of you are made into one. Look at your love and see if this is what you desire: wouldn’t this be all that you want?’ No one, apparently, would think that mere sex is the reason each lover takes such deep joy in being with the other. The soul of each lover apparently longs for something else, but cannot say what it is. The beloved holds out the promise of something beyond itself, but that something lovers are unable to name.1 Hephaestus’ question is a pressing one.
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege
    Synthese (2010) 174:237–261 DOI 10.1007/s11229-008-9420-9 The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege Willem R. de Jong Received: 10 April 2007 / Revised: 24 July 2007 / Accepted: 1 April 2008 / Published online: 8 November 2008 © The Author(s) 2008. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic- synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces con- siderable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, that is, within the Classical Model of Science: scientific knowledge as cognitio ex principiis. But as we will see, the way the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments or propositions functions within this model turns out to differ considerably between them. Keywords Analytic-synthetic · Science · Logic · Kant · Bolzano · Frege 1 Introduction As is well known, the critical Kant is the first to apply the analytic-synthetic distinction to such things as judgments, sentences or propositions. For Kant this distinction is not only important in his repudiation of traditional, so-called dogmatic, metaphysics, but it is also crucial in his inquiry into (the possibility of) metaphysics as a rational science. Namely, this distinction should be “indispensable with regard to the critique of human understanding, and therefore deserves to be classical in it” (Kant 1783, p.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Tracing the Development of Structural Realism
    1 2 TRACING THE DEVELOPMENT OF STRUCTURAL REALISM Ioannis Votsis 1. Introduction This chapter traces the development of structural realism within the scientific realism debate and the wider current of structuralism that has swept the philosophy of the natural sciences in the twentieth century. 1 The primary aim is to make perspicuous the many manifestations of structural realism and their underlying claims. Among other things, I will compare structural realism’s various manifestations in order to throw more light onto the relations between them. At the end of the chapter, I will identify the main objections raised against the epistemic form of structural realism. This last task will pave the way for the evaluation of the structural realist answer to the main epistemological question, an evaluation that will be central to the rest of this dissertation. Generally construed, structuralism is a point of view that emphasises the importance of relations. It takes the structure, i.e. the nexus of relations, of a given domain of interest to be the foremost goal of research and holds that an understanding of the subject matter has to be, and most successfully is, achieved in structural terms. The following quote from Redhead (2001a) nicely conveys this intuition: “Informally a structure is a system of related elements, and structuralism is a point of view which focuses attention on the relations between the elements as distinct from the elements themselves”(74). This vision has shaped research programmes in fields as diverse as mathematics, linguistics, literary criticism, aesthetics, anthropology, psychology, and philosophy of science. It is the last-mentioned that I am concerned with in this chapter.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Philosophical Analysis?
    JEFFREY C. KING WHAT IS A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS? (Received 24 January 1996) It is common for philosophers to offer philosophical accounts or analyses, as they are sometimes called, of knowledge, autonomy, representation, (moral) goodness, reference, and even modesty.1 These philosophical analyses raise deep questions. What is it that is being analyzed (i.e. what sorts of things are the objects of analysis)? What sort of thing is the analysis itself (a proposition? sentence?)? Under what conditions is an analysis correct? How can a correct analysis be informative? How, if at all, does the production of philo- sophical analyses differ from what scientists do? The purpose of the present paper is to provide answers to these questions. The traditional answers to the ®rst and last of these questions are that concepts are the objects of philosophical analysis and that philo- sophical analyses differ from the results of scienti®c investigation in being conceptual analyses. Like many philosophers I am suspicious of the notions of concept and conceptual analysis as traditionally understood. Though the critique of these notions is beyond the scope of the present work, the answers I shall give to the questions raised above shall not invoke concepts (understood as things distinct from properties).2 I count it as a virtue of my account that it is able to provide answers to the questions raised above without an appeal to concepts. And to the extent that it has been felt that concepts are needed to answer these questions, the present account weakens the case for positing concepts. Before addressing these questions, however, we shall make the simplifying assumption that analyses are given in a ªcanonical formº.
    [Show full text]
  • Models, Perspectives, and Scientific Realism
    MODELS, PERSPECTIVES, AND SCIENTIFIC REALISM: ON RONALD GIERE'S PERSPECTIVAL REALISM A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Brian R. Huth May, 2014 Thesis written by Brian R. Huth B.A., Kent State University 2012 M.A., Kent State University 2014 Approved by Frank X. Ryan, Advisor Linda Williams, Chair, Department of Philosophy James L. Blank, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS................................................................................................. iv INTRODUCTION............................................................................................................... 1 CHAPTER I. FROM THE RECEIVED VIEW TO THE MODEL-THEORETIC VIEW........................................................................................................... 7 Section 1.1.................................................................................................... 9 Section 1.2.................................................................................................... 16 II. RONALD GIERE'S CONSTRUCTIVISM AND PERSPECTIVAL REALISM.................................................................................................... 25 Section 2.1.................................................................................................... 25 Section 2.2.................................................................................................... 31 Section 2.3...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatics of Explanation: Remarks on Van Fraassen's Theory of Why-Questions1
    The Pragmatics of explanation: Remarks on van Fraassen’s theory of why-questions1 A Pragmática da explicação: Comentários sobre a teoria das questões-por-quê de van Fraassen Renato Cesar Cani Universidade Federal do Paraná – UFPR/CAPES – Brasil [email protected] Abstract: In this article, my aim is to analyze Bas van Fraassen’s pragmatic solution to two of the traditional problems concerning scientific explanation, namely, rejection and asymmetry. According to his view, an explanation is an answer to some request for information. The emergence of a question, as well as the evaluation of the explanations adduced, depends on considerations about contextual factors. In addition, I will evaluate the pertinence of objections raised by Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon against van Fraassen’s account. I will argue that their charge is not sound, for it actually misunderstands the role played by context in van Fraassen’s account. Although Salmon’s and Kitcher’s realist commitments motivate the point made by them, I will hold that a pragmatic account of explanation does not commit one to an anti-realist approach to science. Keywords: Pragmatics of Explanation. Bas van Fraassen. Why-questions. Asymmetry. Realism. Resumo: Neste artigo, meu objetivo é analisar a solução pragmática oferecida por Bas van Fraassen a dois dos tradicionais problemas da explicação científica, quais sejam, o da rejeição e o da assimetria. Em sua visão, uma explicação é uma resposta a alguma demanda por informação. O surgimento de uma questão, bem como a avaliação das possíveis explicações, depende de fatores contextuais. Além disso, avaliarei a pertinência das objeções de Philip Kitcher e Wesley Salmon contra a concepção de van Fraassen.
    [Show full text]