The Concept of Perversity As a Means Towards a Non-Humanist Existentialism in the Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre and Friedrich Nietzsche

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Concept of Perversity As a Means Towards a Non-Humanist Existentialism in the Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre and Friedrich Nietzsche 1 The concept of perversity as a means towards a non-humanist existentialism in the philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre and Friedrich Nietzsche Thesis submitted in accordance with the requirements of the University of Liverpool for the degree of Doctor in Philosophy by David Mitchell October 2013 2 Contents Title page 1 Contents 2 List of abbreviations 3 Abstract 4 Introduction: A means towards a non-humanist existentialism 5 Chapter 1: Nietzsche [i] the free spirit as perverse genesis 22 Chapter 2: Nietzsche [ii] Perversity and genealogy 48 Chapter 3: Sartre [i] Nothingness and perversity 89 Chapter 4: Sartre [ii] Perversity and self-evasion 121 Conclusion: Ontology and ethics 158 Bibliography 164 3 List of Abbreviations Sartre BN Being and Nothingness EH Existentialism is a humanism TE Transcendence of the Ego Heidegger BT Being and Time LH Letter on Humanism Nietzsche BG Beyond Good and Evil EcH Ecce Homo D Daybreak HH Human, All too Human GM On the Genealogy of Morality BT The Birth of Tragedy GS The Gay Science TSZ Thus Spoke Zarathustra UTM Untimely Meditations Abbreviated forms are used after one full reference to the text in each chapter. 4 Abstract Existentialism, broadly construed, can be understood in terms of a desire to ‘return to man’. In other words, underpinning existentialist thought is a sense that modern philosophy has lost touch with the essential goal of allowing man to comprehend his own existence. And it is this aim then, of a return to man’s being as it is concretely lived and experienced, that it seeks to realise. However it will be argued in this thesis that, against familiar criticisms of such a project, this ‘return’ does not simply necessitate a return to, or acceptance of, ‘humanism’. For influenced by Heidegger’s Letter on Humanism, Marxist, structuralist and post- structuralist critics have all suggested this movement is synonymous with a naive or romantic ‘humanist’ idea of the subject. That is, they have suggested that existentialism’s ‘return to man’ amounts at best to the radicalisation of a discredited subject-entity concept. As such, against this, we will argue that existentialism and its ‘return to man’ is not simply another humanism. And we will attempt to demonstrate this point, and resolve this apparent contradiction, by exploring the idea of perversity in the work of Sartre and Nietzsche. For if man is understood as a ‘perversion’ of something other than himself then it may be possible to have a philosophy of man without appealing to the notion of an isolated subject-entity. How will we do this though? In the first half of the thesis we will look at the way in which for Nietzsche the human can be understood as a perversion of fundamental natural forces. We will attempt this first of all by looking at the genesis of the free spirit as a perversion of man’s normal, fettered state. Secondly we will look at On The Genealogy of Morality, and explore how man can be understood there as a ‘perverse animal’; as a perversion of the active force of will-to-power. Continuing, in the second half of the thesis, we will then explore the idea of man as a ‘perversion of being’ that we find in Sartre’s Being and Nothingness. We will see there how man exists, first of all, as a perverse non-being in relation to being. Next though we will look at how this ontological fact implies a secondary perverse attempt by man to conceal this reality from himself. Consequently then by exploring such a ‘perverse’ conception of man we hope to show how a non-humanist existentialism, and ‘return to man’, is possible. 5 Introduction: The concept of perversity as a means towards a non-humanist existentialism A. The meaning of existentialism And I say this to the overthrowers of statues: To throw salt into the sea and statues into the mud are perhaps the greatest of follies. The statue lay in the mud of your contempt: but this precisely is its law, that its life and living beauty grow again out of contempt! And now it arises again, with divine features and sorrowfully seductive; and in truth! It will even thank you for overthrowing it, you overthrowers! Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, ‘Of great events’1 It is not exaggerating to say that in recent decades the ‘statue’ of existentialism has very much been thrown into the metaphorical mud. Once dominating the intellectual landscape, along with a Marxism that has suffered a similar fall from grace, what became known as ‘existentialism’ and its concerns are now widely regarded as philosophically outmoded. Authenticity, angst, alienation, being-for-others?2 It would seem many have accepted Levi-Strauss’s claim that such talk is ‘Metaphysique pour midinette.’3 And whilst its most recognisable proponent, Sartre, is derided as a ‘philosopher of a world that has passed’4, its other seminal figures, Nietzsche and Heidegger, have been salvaged only at the price of expunging the ‘existentialist’ label from their thought altogether. Yet such ‘contempt’ is not as fatal as it might seem. Rather, following Nietzsche’s logic in our quote, we will argue in this thesis that from the ‘mud’ of such criticism a revitalised and philosophically credible existentialism can be recovered. That is to say, by responding to a particular misconception underpinning these critiques we can separate a genuine existentialism from the ossified image 1 F. Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra trans. by R.J Hollingdale [London: Penguin, 1961], p154 2 See J. Golomb, In Search of Authenticity [London: Routledge, 1995], for discussion of the ‘death of authenticity’ as a concept in light of post-modernism, p203-204: ‘‘There is today a grave danger that we are facing the death of authenticity. Post-structuralist thought and the other currently fashionable streams of what is vaguely called ‘post-modernism’ attempt to dissolve the subjective pathos of authenticity which lies at the heart of existentialist concern.’ 3 ‘Shop girl metaphysics’, See K. Morris, Sartre [Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2008], p54: FN 18 [Quoted in Moi 1990: 28] 4 N.F. Fox, The New Sartre [New York: Continuum, 2003], p1 6 with which it has become associated. And it is by doing this further that we will be able to recover its true distinctiveness and interest as a philosophy. In short, by doing this we will be able to ask, after Crowell, whether existentialism ‘...might not merely have a history, but also a future?’5 [i] Defining existentialism But what though is the basis of this misconception which will allow us to do this? What lies at the root of those criticisms which have led to existentialism’s dismissal, and which in being countered will help us to recover its true meaning? In order to answer this question we must ask initially what has been meant, and what can be meant, by ‘existentialism’ in the first place. And we begin in this fashion by noting that the very capacity of the term to describe anything meaningful at all has often been questioned. As Cooper notes, ‘It has been denied, that is, that there ever was a distinctive philosophical perspective or tendency shared by those thinkers who have been labelled ‘existentialists.’6 Yet whilst the term is certainly more problematic than say that of ‘empiricism’ or ‘phenomenology’ it would be an exaggeration to say that such thinkers have nothing meaningful in common. 7 Indeed, it is the very problematical nature of defining ‘existentialists’ itself that is taken by some as the starting point for a characterisation of the term. For, as Kaufmann argues, ‘Existentialism is not a philosophy but a label for several widely different revolts against traditional philosophy.’8 In this way, then one possible understanding of existentialism is that it is not so much a ‘philosophy’ in the conventional sense, but a sort of ‘anti-philosophy’. That is, based on a sense that traditional philosophy is incapable of grasping the richness or immediacy of human life, such an understanding says that ‘existentialism defined itself against systems.’9 In short it suggests that existentialism defined itself against any form of systematic thought. And in 5 S. Crowell, ‘Existentialism and its legacy’, in The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism, ed. by S. Crowell [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012], p4 6 D. Cooper, ‘Existentialism as a philosophical movement’, in The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism, ed. by S. Crowell [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012], p27 7 Gabriel Marcel first used the term in 1945 to describe Sartre and De Beauvoir. Nevertheless most of those associated with ‘existentialism’ rejected the label. See R. Schacht, ‘Nietzsche: after the death of God’, in The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism, ed. S. Crowell [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012], p112- 114 8 W. Kaufmann, Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre [New York: Meridian, 1956], p11 9J. Judaken, ‘Introduction’, in Situating Existentialism, ed. by J. Judaken and R. Bernasconi [New York: Columbia University Press, 2012], p1 7 this way, further, such an interpretation ties existential thinkers to what Solomon calls the ‘existential attitude.’10 In other words, such understanding ties existentialism to the figure of the ‘existential hero’, such as is given form in Sartre’s Roquentin, and Camus’s Meursalt. For it links existentialism to the attitude of figures whose primary goal is not philosophical knowledge. Rather for these figures the goal is an ‘authentic life’ based on confrontation with the true meaninglessness of existence, and resistance to all human endeavours to evade this.11 However such a notion, taken in itself, is of course for our purposes limited. That is to say, whilst this notion of existentialism as an ‘attitude’ doubtless captures something, and is an advance on jettisoning the term altogether, it is hardly the basis for recovering a philosophically credible mode of thought.
Recommended publications
  • Beyond Good and Evil—1
    Nietzsche & Asian Philosophy Beyond Good and Evil—1 Beyond good and Evil Preface supposing truth is a woman philosophers like love-sick suitors who don’t understand the woman-truth central problem of philosophy is Plato’s error: denying perspective, the basic condition of all life On the Prejudices of Philosophers 1) questioning the will to truth who is it that really wants truth? What in us wants truth? Why not untruth? 2) origin of the will to truth out of the will to untruth, deception can anything arise out of its opposite? A dangerous questioning? Nietzsche sees new philosophers coming up who have the strength for the dangerous “maybe.” Note in general Nietzsche’s preference for the conditional tense, his penchant for beginning his questioning with “perhaps” or “suppose” or “maybe.” In many of the passages throughout this book Nietzsche takes up a perspective which perhaps none had dared take up before, a perspective to question what had seemed previously to be unquestionable. He seems to constantly be tempting the reader with a dangerous thought experiment. This begins with the questioning of the will to truth and the supposition that, perhaps, the will to truth may have arisen out of its opposite, the will to untruth, ignorance, deception. 3) the supposition that the greater part of conscious thinking must be included among instinctive activities Nietzsche emphasizes that consciousness is a surface phenomenon conscious thinking is directed by what goes on beneath the surface contrary to Plato’s notion of pure reason, the conscious
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Revaluation of All Values Joseph Anthony Kranak Marquette University
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Nietzsche's Revaluation of All Values Joseph Anthony Kranak Marquette University Recommended Citation Kranak, Joseph Anthony, "Nietzsche's Revaluation of All Values" (2014). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 415. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/415 NIETZSCHE’S REVALUATION OF ALL VALUES by Joseph Kranak A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2014 ABSTRACT NIETZSCHE’S REVALUTION OF ALL VALUES Joseph Kranak Marquette University, 2014 This dissertation looks at the details of Friedrich Nietzsche’s concept of the revaluation of all values. The dissertation will look at the idea in several ways to elucidate the depth and complexity of the idea. First, it will be looked at through its evolution, as it began as an idea early in Nietzsche’s career and reached its full complexity at the end of his career with the planned publication of his Revaluation of All Values, just before the onset of his madness. Several questions will be explored: What is the nature of the revaluator who is supposed to be instrumental in the process of revaluation? What will the values after the revaluation be like (a rebirth of ancient values or creation of entirely new values)? What will be the scope of the revaluation? And what is the relation of other major ideas of Nietzsche’s (will to power, eternal return, overman, and amor fati) to the revaluation? Different answers to these questions will be explored.
    [Show full text]
  • How Philosophers Rise and Empires Fall in the Work of Leo Strauss
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2019 Ungodly Freedom: How Philosophers Rise and Empires Fall in the Work of Leo Strauss Eli Karetny The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/2819 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] UNGODLY FREEDOM: HOW PHILOSOPHERS RISE AND EMPIRES FALL IN THE WORK OF LEO STRAUSS by Eli Karetny A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2019 © 2018 Eli Karetny All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. PROFESSOR COREY ROBIN _________________ ____________________________________ Date Committee Chair _______________ PROFESSOR ALYSON COLE Date ____________________________________ Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: Corey Robin Alyson Cole Carol Gould THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract UNGODLY FREEDOM: HOW PHILOSOPHERS RISE AND EMPIRES FALL IN THE WORK OF LEO STRAUSS by Eli Karetny Advisor: Professor Corey Robin This dissertation argues that to fully understand the work of Leo Strauss, scholars must look beyond the Platonic and Machiavellian elements in Strauss and explore how Nietzsche’s ideas about nihilism, the will to power, the eternal return, and the ubermensch influence Strauss’s critique of modernity, his understanding of the relationship between philosophy and politics, and his redefinition of the philosopher as a prophetic lawgiver.
    [Show full text]
  • A Media Event Event
    THE DEATH OF MARX: A MEDIA EVENT EVENT The 'new philosophers '. have enjoyed a recent intense vogue in France, 1 and have even provoked interest in the English speaking press - I have read articles on them in The Sunday Times, The Observer,observer, Encounter and Time magazine. on examination, they appear to be saying very little, so it is interesting to ask what their value is for the foreign press. It will be seen that I too treat them in a 'journalistic' rather than a serious academic fashion, and that this is, in fact, unavoidable. Nevertheless, whilst of little intrinsic interest, the new philosophers are illustrative ofof·two two problems, both of which are of some import. The first is that in French political and culturalculturaJ thought all problems and debates exist within a framework marked by two reference points - the' legislative elections in March 1978, and May 1968. These points are !'\ptApt symmetrical; however, they do mark the beginning and the end of the present •'epoch'.epoch'. The new philosophers are only possible v,i thin this framewor:j.{. The second is of a different order, and concerns the relations of intEll­ini;Ell­ lectuals to journalism, and the changes that these relations have bee~ undergoing. I shall return to these problems at the end, but first $hf.!,ll give an outline description of the phenomenon. * * * * The new philosophy oonsists primarily of publici,ty. The publicitypUblicity hasb,as peen ferocious - in magazines, journals, newspapers, pUblicpublic dis6ussions,disoussions, as ",ell¥ell as on radio and television. It has been centred on personalities - on the new philosophers rather than the new philosophy - and in the articles, I ,', ," interviews and so on the original books published seem of little importl,illce.importl,U1ce.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Aristocratic Radicalism
    Wright State University CORE Scholar Browse all Theses and Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2012 Nietzsche's Aristocratic Radicalism Jonathan James Michalski Wright State University Follow this and additional works at: https://corescholar.libraries.wright.edu/etd_all Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Repository Citation Michalski, Jonathan James, "Nietzsche's Aristocratic Radicalism" (2012). Browse all Theses and Dissertations. 584. https://corescholar.libraries.wright.edu/etd_all/584 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at CORE Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Browse all Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of CORE Scholar. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Nietzsche’s Aristocratic Radicalism A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Humanities By Jonathan Michalski B.A. Wright State University, 2008. 2012 Wright State University Wright State University School of Graduate Studies June 4, 2012 I hereby recommend that the thesis prepared under my supervision by Jonathan Michalski entitled Nietzsche’s Aristocratic Radicalism be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Humanities. _____________________________ Donovan Miyasaki, Ph.D. Project Director _____________________________ Ava Chamberlain, Ph.D. Director, Master of Humanities Program College of Liberal Arts Committee on Final Examination: __________________________________________ Donovan Miyasaki, Ph.D. __________________________________________ Sean Wilson, Ph.D __________________________________________ Linda Farmer, Ph.D. __________________________________________ Andrew T. Hsu, Ph.D. Dean, School of Graduate Studies Abstract Michalski, Jonathan. M.H. Department of the Humanities, Wright State University, 2012. Nietzsche’s Aristocratic Radicalism. My thesis is that Nietzsche’s political philosophy is a form of aristocratic radicalism, which means that society should be ruled by the few.
    [Show full text]
  • Nousletter 2015
    Department of Philosophy Noûsletter Number 21 - Summer 2015 No. 21 · Summer 2015 noûsletter Page 2 Table of Contents Peter Hare Outstanding Assistant Awards .............. 45 Letter from the Chair ................................................................... 3 Hare Award for Best Overall Essay .............................. 46 From the Director of Undergraduate Education ........... 7 Hourani Award for Outstanding Essay in Ethics .. 46 Faculty of the Department of Philosophy ......................... 7 Perry Awards for Best Dissertation ............................. 46 In Remembrance ............................................................................ 8 Steinberg Essay Prize Winners ...................................... 46 William Baumer (1932 —2014) ....................................... 8 Whitman Scholarship Winner ........................................ 46 Newton Garver (1928 – 2014) .......................................... 9 Confucian Institute Dissertation Fellowship .......... 46 Anthony Fay (1979-2015) ................................................ 11 The People Who Make It Possible ..................................... 47 Faculty Updates ........................................................................... 12 The Peter Hare Award ........................................................ 47 Introducing Alexandra King ............................................. 12 The Hourani Lectures ......................................................... 47 Introducing Nicolas Bommarito ...................................
    [Show full text]
  • Download File
    Translating Revolution in Twentieth-Century China and France Diana King Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2017 © 2017 Diana King All rights reserved ABSTRACT Translating Revolution in Twentieth-Century China and France Diana King In “Translating Revolution in Twentieth-Century China and France,” I examine how the two countries translated each other’s revolutions during critical moments of political and cultural crisis (the 1911 Revolution, the May Fourth Movement (1919), the Cultural Revolution (1966-76), and May 1968 in France), and subsequently (or simultaneously), how that knowledge was mobilized in practice and shaped the historical contexts in which it was produced. Drawing upon a broad range of discourses including political journals, travel narratives, films and novels in French, English and Chinese, I argue that translation served as a key site of knowledge production, shaping the formulation of various political and cultural projects from constructing a Chinese national identity to articulating women’s rights to thinking about radical emancipation in an era of decolonization. While there have been isolated studies on the influence of the French Revolution in early twentieth-century China, and the impact of the Chinese Cultural Revolution on the development of French Maoism and French theory in the sixties, there have been few studies that examine the circulation of revolutionary ideas and practices across multiple historical moments and cultural contexts. In addition, the tendency of much current scholarship to focus exclusively on the texts of prominent French or Chinese intellectuals overlooks the vital role played by translation, and by non-elite thinkers, writers, students and migrant workers in the cross-fertilization of revolutionary discourses and practices.
    [Show full text]
  • Crisis & Critique Democracy and Revolution Volume I
    C R I S I S & C R CRISISI & T I Q U E # CRISIS & CRITIQUE1 CRITIQUE CRISIS & CRITIQUE DEMOCRACY AND REVOLUTION VOLUME I / ISSUE I, 2014 Dialectical Materialism Collective 1 The Impasses of Today’s Radical Politics C R I S I S & C R CRISISI & T I Q U E # CRISIS & CRITIQUE1 CRITIQUECRISIS & CRITIQUE Editorial Board: DEMOCRACY AND REVOLUTION Henrik Jøker Bjerre VOLUME I / ISSUE I, 2014 Aaron Schuster Adrian Johnston Joan Copjec Editor-in-Chief Robert Pfaller Agon Hamza Frank Ruda Gabriel Tupinambá Sead Zimeri Fabio Vighi 2 Slavoj Žižek Benjamin Noys Roland Boer Editorial note, 238 C H.J.Bjerre & A.Hamza Communism is Wrong, R by Jana Tsoneva I 8 S The Impasses of Today’s Radical 264 I Politics, by Slavoj Žižek The Jews and the Zionists; The Story ofS a Reversal, by Sina Badiei 46 & Socialist Democracy with Chinese 280 Characteristics, by Roland Boer Review articles: C R CRISIS &66 H.J.Bjerre: Prolegomena to Any FutureI The Indignant of the Earth, Materialism, by Adrian Johnston T by Frank Ruda I C.Crockett: From Myth to Symptom: theQ 90 case of Kosovo, by S. Žižek & A.HamzaU Democracy and revolution on the Inter- E net, by Katarina Peović Vuković D.Tutt: Enjoying What We Don’t Have: The Political Project of Psychoanalysis,# 116 by Todd McGowan 1 Alain Badiou and the aporia of democracy within generic communism, A.Ryder: Badiou and the Philosophers, by Panagiotis Sotiris ed.T.Tho & G.Bianco CRITIQUE136 308 Climate Crisis, Ideology, and Collective Notes on Contributers Action, by Ted Stolze 154 Lacan and Rational Choice, by Yuan Yao 166 Redemptive
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Journal of French Philosophy Volume 17, Number 1, Spring 2007 Slaughterbench of Humanisms: The 1987 Heidegger Affair in Intellectual-Historical Perspective Stefanos Geroulanos In the fall of 1987, one of the most significant affairs in recent intellectual history erupted in France when the unknown Chilean writer Victor Farias published a well-researched but philosophically unimpressive book on Martin Heidegger’s Nazism. To publishers abroad, notably in Germany, the volume rang a hollow bell, and remained unprinted, as debates on existentialism, Heidegger’s engagement with the Nazi party, and his continuing political position in the fifties lay in the past.1 But in France, despite a certain academic awareness of Heidegger’s Nazi engagement, the effect was very different:2 Farias struck a nerve, and suddenly the intellectual milieu erupted into furious polemics. This 1987 Heidegger Affair has long been read as the final curtain for a movement that lent support to several epistemological ruptures in French philosophy (according to some of the more positive accounts) or flourished as an uncritical and pretentious audience for Heidegger (in the less generous ones). Yet although it provided a number of signs indicating shifts in intellectual tendencies, the affair has never been seriously treated as a barometer for the recent past of French thought.3 The present essay attempts to offer a necessarily schematic intellectual- historical description of the 1987 affair as an intellectual event emerging with the rise of a neo-humanist politics that
    [Show full text]
  • 'NIW PHILOSOPHIRS' and THI IND Or Llrtism
    THI 'NIW PHILOSOPHIRS' AND THI IND or LlrTISM Peter Dews Introduction The New Renegades At the time of its first appearance the New Philo­ sophy was surrounded by a good deal of confusion. Fashion moves fast in Parisian salons, and the taste Did its emergence signify, as the sympathetic res­ for intellectual scandal demands the constant break­ panse of Le Nouvel Observateur, France's leading ing of fresh taboos. Three years ago, in the spring left-wing weekly, seemed to suggest, the first of 1977, a group of young authors styling themselves serious attempt by thinkers on the left to deal the 'New Philosophers' moved rapidly to the centre squarely and without double -think with abuses of of attention, making headlines not only in France but power by socialist states and the question of human around the globe. The shocking novelty of the New rights? Or were the New Philosophers, as the Philosophers consisted in the fact that here was a approving reaction of certain commentators, and group of young thinkers who were no longer prepared some of the company they kept, might lead to to dialogue with or work within the framework of believe, the heralds of a swing to the right among marxism, but who openly denounced marxist thought intellectuals in the advanced capitalist countries? as a philosophy of domination. After decades in In part this uncertainty was due to -the way in which which the vast majority of French intellectuals had the Nouvelle Philosophie was reported in a press instinctively placed themselves on the left, this always eager to relay the opinions of intellectuals attitude marked an important departure.
    [Show full text]
  • Jacques Derrida Law As Absolute Hospitality
    JACQUES DERRIDA LAW AS ABSOLUTE HOSPITALITY JACQUES DE VILLE NOMIKOI CRITICAL LEGAL THINKERS Jacques Derrida Jacques Derrida: Law as Absolute Hospitality presents a comprehensive account and understanding of Derrida’s approach to law and justice. Through a detailed reading of Derrida’s texts, Jacques de Ville contends that it is only by way of Derrida’s deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence, and specifi cally in relation to the texts of Husserl, Levinas, Freud and Heidegger, that the reasoning behind his elusive works on law and justice can be grasped. Through detailed readings of texts such as ‘To Speculate – on Freud’, Adieu, ‘Declarations of Independence’, ‘Before the Law’, ‘Cogito and the History of Madness’, Given Time, ‘Force of Law’ and Specters of Marx, de Ville contends that there is a continuity in Derrida’s thinking, and rejects the idea of an ‘ethical turn’. Derrida is shown to be neither a postmodernist nor a political liberal, but a radical revolutionary. De Ville also controversially contends that justice in Derrida’s thinking must be radically distinguished from Levinas’s refl ections on ‘the Other’. It is the notion of absolute hospitality – which Derrida derives from Levinas, but radically transforms – that provides the basis of this argument. Justice must, on de Ville’s reading, be understood in terms of a demand of absolute hospitality which is imposed on both the individual and the collective subject. A much needed account of Derrida’s infl uential approach to law, Jacques Derrida: Law as Absolute Hospitality will be an invaluable resource for those with an interest in legal theory, and for those with an interest in the ethics and politics of deconstruction.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysical Origins of Analytic Philosophy
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY FRASER MACBRIDE. ON THE GENEALOGY OF UNIVERSALS: VOLUME 8, NUMBER 8 THE METAPHYSICAL ORIGINS OF ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY. EDITOR IN CHIEF OXFORD: OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS, 2018. VIII + 263 MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT PAGES. $72 HARDCOVER. ISBN 978-0-19-8811251. REVIEWED BY LANDON D. C. ELKIND EDITORIAL BOARD ANNALISA COLIVA, UC IRVINE HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LaURet, UnIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS CONSUELO PRETI, THE COLLEGE OF NEW JERSEY ANTHONY SKELTON, WESTERN UnIVERSITY MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY EDITORS FOR SPECIAL ISSUES SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY ALEXANDER KLEIN, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY REVIEW EDITORS SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER SANFORD SHIEH, WESLEYAN UnIVERSITY DESIGN AND LAYOUT DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS ISSN: 2159-0303 JHAPONLINE.ORG © 2020 LaNDON D. C. ELKIND REVIEW: ON THE GENEALOGY OF UNIVERSALS: THE tions of the texts considered. Even this lengthy review does not METAPHYSICAL ORIGINS OF ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY, fully do it justice. In the next section, I summarize the book’s genealogical project BY FRASER MACBRIDE and overall argument. Then I discuss each chapter in more detail. LANDON D. C. ELKIND 1. THE PROJECT Lapointe and Pincock (2017, 13–15) recently offered a provisional Fraser MacBride’s recent book is a welcome and substantial but nonetheless helpful list of six overlapping and mutually sup- contribution to the history of analytic philosophy. Its focus is porting tasks that historians of philosophy undertake. One of metaphysics: MacBride supplies a genealogy of the universal- these is genealogical narrative: particular distinction as it evolved from Kant, early Moore, early Genealogical narratives fulfill an important role in the shaping of Russell, Stout, middle Moore and Whitehead, middle Russell, one’s identity as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]