Set Theory and Lattices

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Set Theory and Lattices Appendix A SET THEORY AND LATTICES The objective of the Appendices is to present the main definitions and propositions of some of the mathematical structures used in the text. With a few exceptions, no attempt was made to present proofs of the propositions, for otherwise the length of the Appendices would be greater than the main text. Any serious student who needs to improve his knowledge about the topics treated below must consult mathematical texts as, e.g., [1-6] and also the following excellent texts on quantum theory[7-10]. A.1 MAIN DEFINITIONS There are two primitive concepts in set theory, the notion of set itself1 and the notion of pertinence as used, e.g., in sentences like "x is an element of the set S." We write xES if x is a member of a given set S and write x ~ S otherwise. In general a set S is determined by some property P shared by its members and we denote this fact writing S = {xIP(x)}. definition 1. Given any property P, the empty (or null, or void) set is the set 0= {xIP(x) is false}. (A. 1) definition 2. Let A and B be two sets such that Vx E A => x E B. We say that A is a subset of B and denote this fact, writing A ~ B or B ;2 A. If it happens that A ~ B and B ;2 A, then both sets are equal and we write A = B. If A ~ B or A :f:. B we say that A is a proper subset of B and write sometimes A C B. The symbol ~ (and also C) is called set theoretical inclusion. We observe that given any set S we have 0 ~ S (or better 0 C S). definition 3. Let A ~ S. The mapping A -+ S, (A.2) 1 if x E A, XA(X) = 0 if x ~ A. 187 188 NONLOCALITY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS is called the characteristic function of the set A. definition 4. Given two sets A and B, their union is the set denoted A U B such that Au B = {xix E A or x E B}. (A.3) definition 5. Given two sets A and B, their intersection is the set denoted A n B such that AnB = {xix E Aandx E B}. (A.4) If An B = 0, then A and B are said to be disjoint. definition 6. The complement of A ~ S is the set denoted AC (or S \ A) such that A C = {x ~ A, XES}. (A.5) definition 7. Let A, B ~ S. The difference of A and B is the set denoted A - B such that A - B = An BC= {xix E A and x ~ B}. (A.6) The difference of A and B is also called the relative complement of B in A. definition 8. The symmetric difference of A and B (A, B ~ S) is the set denoted Al:::,.B such that Al:::,.B = (A - B) U (B - A). (A.7) definition 9. Let J be a set whose elements we will call indexes. Given a set X, an indexedfamity of elements of X with indexes in J is a mapping x : J -t X, a t-+ XO. The indexed family is denoted {Xo}oEJ or simply {xo } when it is clear who the set J is. When J = N = {1, 2, ... }, the indexed family is said to be a sequence of elements ofX. definition 10. An indexed family {Ao} of subsets of A, with indexes in J is said to be a partition of A if \la, (3 E J, a :I (3, Ao n A,B = 0 and UOEJAo = A definition 11. The union and the intersection of the Ao are respectively the sets UOEJAo {xix E Ao for at least one E J}, noEJAo = {xix E Ao for all a E J}. (A.8) definition 12. Given a set S, the class of all its subsets is said to be the power set of S and is denoted by 28 . definition 13. The Cartesian product of the n sets AI, A2 , . .. An is the set When Ai = A, i = 1,2, ... n we write the Cartesian product as An. APPENDIX A: SET THEORY AND LATTICES 189 A.2 PO SETS definition 14. A (binary) relation in a set 8 is a specified subset R ~ 8 x 8. If (x, y) E R we say that x stands in relation with y and write xRy. definition 15. Let R ~ 8 x 8 be a relation in 8. It is said to be: (i) reflexive if xRx, 'Vx E S, (ii) symmetric if xRy ::::} yRx, (iii) transitive if xRy, yRz ::::} xRz, (iv) antisymmetric if xRy and yRx ::::} x = y. definition 16. An equivalence relation in a set 8 is a relation in 8 which is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. We often use the symbol x'" y to denote that x, y E 8 are equivalent. proposition 17. An equivalence relation in S leads to a unique partition of S. Conversely, any given partition of 8 defines an equivalence relation in 8. definition 18. Let'" be an equivalence relation in S. Let xES be an arbitrary but fixed element. Consider the collection of all y such that x '" y. This collection denoted [xl ~ 8 is called the equivalence class of x. We have, [xl = {y E 8 and y '" x}. (A 10) definition 19. Let E ~ S x 8 be an equivalence relation in 8. The quotient set of S modulo E, denoted by SI E is the class of all distinct equivalence classes induced in 8 by E. We have, 81E = {[xli x E 8}. (All) definition 20. The mapping 71' : S -t S IE; x t-+ [x Jis called the canonical mapping (or projection) of S onto SI E. definition 21. A relation in a set S is called an order relation if it is reflexive, anti symmetric and transitive. The symbol::; is used to denote in what follows the order relation. If x, y, z E 8 we have, (i) x < x, 'Vx E 8, (ii) x < y and y ::; x ::::} x = y, (iii) x < y and y ::; z ::::} x ::; z. (AI2) Sometimes instead of x ::; y (which reads x is less than or equal to y, or x is contained in y) we write y ~ x. If x::; y and x f:. y we write x < y. When x < yand there is no z such that x < z < y we say that y covers x and write x -< y. definition 22. Given a set 8 and an order relation::; in 8, the pair (8,::;) is called a poset (a short form for partially ordered set).2 definition 23. Let (8,::;) be a po set. If there exists 0 E 8 such that 0 ::; x, 'Vx E 8, then 0 is said to be the first (or smallest, or least) element of 8. If there exists 1 E 8 such that x ::; 1, 'Vx E 8, then 1 is said to be the last (or largest, or greatest) element of S. 190 NONLOCALITY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS proposition 24. The first element of 5 when it exists is unique. The last element of 5 if it exists, is unique. definition 25. Let (5, ::;) be a poset. m E 5 is called a minimal element of 5 if there is no element in 5 which is strictly smaller than m, i.e., if x ::; m, then x = m. An element m E 5 is said to be the maximal element of 5 if there is no element of 5 that is strictly greater than m, i.e., if m ::; x, then m = x. definition 26. Let (5, ::;) be a poset and A ~ 5 (eventually A = 5). l E 5 is said to be a lower bound of of A if and only if Va E A :::} l ::; a. An element u E 5 is called an upper bound of A if and only if Va E A :::} u :::: a. It is important to have in mind that A ~ 5 need not have necessarily any lower bound and even if it does, let us say b, in general b ¢ A. In this way it is clear that A may have many different lower bounds. An analogous comment is valid regarding upper bounds. definition 27. Let (5,::;) be a poset and A ~ 5. Denote by AL the set of all lower bounds of A. If AL has a last (greatest) element, then it is called the infimum (or the greatest lower bound) and is denoted inf(A). Denote the set of all upper bounds of A by Au. If Au has a first (smaller) element then it is called the supremum (or least upper bound) denoted sup(A). The notations VaEAa and AaEAa are often used respectively for inf(A) and sup(A). When A is a finite countable (infinite countable) set we write for the infimum Vi=l a (V~l a). For the supremum we write A;;' 1 a (A~l a). proposition 29. Let (5, ::;) be a poset and x, y, z E 5. Then, (i) inf{x,{y,z}} inf{x,y,z} (ii) sup{ x, {y, z}} sup{x,y,z} A.3 LATTICES definition 30. A poset C is called a lattice if: (i) :1 0 E C, :1 1 E C and 0 =j:. 1, (ii) each pair x, y E C, x =j:. y, has a supremum (also called union, join or dis­ junction) and denoted by x V y and an infimum (also called intersection, meet or conjunction) denoted by x A y.
Recommended publications
  • 2.1 the Algebra of Sets
    Chapter 2 I Abstract Algebra 83 part of abstract algebra, sets are fundamental to all areas of mathematics and we need to establish a precise language for sets. We also explore operations on sets and relations between sets, developing an “algebra of sets” that strongly resembles aspects of the algebra of sentential logic. In addition, as we discussed in chapter 1, a fundamental goal in mathematics is crafting articulate, thorough, convincing, and insightful arguments for the truth of mathematical statements. We continue the development of theorem-proving and proof-writing skills in the context of basic set theory. After exploring the algebra of sets, we study two number systems denoted Zn and U(n) that are closely related to the integers. Our approach is based on a widely used strategy of mathematicians: we work with specific examples and look for general patterns. This study leads to the definition of modified addition and multiplication operations on certain finite subsets of the integers. We isolate key axioms, or properties, that are satisfied by these and many other number systems and then examine number systems that share the “group” properties of the integers. Finally, we consider an application of this mathematics to check digit schemes, which have become increasingly important for the success of business and telecommunications in our technologically based society. Through the study of these topics, we engage in a thorough introduction to abstract algebra from the perspective of the mathematician— working with specific examples to identify key abstract properties common to diverse and interesting mathematical systems. 2.1 The Algebra of Sets Intuitively, a set is a “collection” of objects known as “elements.” But in the early 1900’s, a radical transformation occurred in mathematicians’ understanding of sets when the British philosopher Bertrand Russell identified a fundamental paradox inherent in this intuitive notion of a set (this paradox is discussed in exercises 66–70 at the end of this section).
    [Show full text]
  • An Elementary Approach to Boolean Algebra
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Plan B Papers Student Theses & Publications 6-1-1961 An Elementary Approach to Boolean Algebra Ruth Queary Follow this and additional works at: https://thekeep.eiu.edu/plan_b Recommended Citation Queary, Ruth, "An Elementary Approach to Boolean Algebra" (1961). Plan B Papers. 142. https://thekeep.eiu.edu/plan_b/142 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses & Publications at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Plan B Papers by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. r AN ELEr.:ENTARY APPRCACH TC BCCLF.AN ALGEBRA RUTH QUEAHY L _J AN ELE1~1ENTARY APPRCACH TC BC CLEAN ALGEBRA Submitted to the I<:athematics Department of EASTERN ILLINCIS UNIVERSITY as partial fulfillment for the degree of !•:ASTER CF SCIENCE IN EJUCATION. Date :---"'f~~-----/_,_ffo--..i.-/ _ RUTH QUEARY JUNE 1961 PURPOSE AND PLAN The purpose of this paper is to provide an elementary approach to Boolean algebra. It is designed to give an idea of what is meant by a Boclean algebra and to supply the necessary background material. The only prerequisite for this unit is one year of high school algebra and an open mind so that new concepts will be considered reason­ able even though they nay conflict with preconceived ideas. A mathematical science when put in final form consists of a set of undefined terms and unproved propositions called postulates, in terrrs of which all other concepts are defined, and from which all other propositions are proved.
    [Show full text]
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets, Functions, Relations
    Mathematics for Computer Scientists Lecture notes for the module G51MCS Venanzio Capretta University of Nottingham School of Computer Science Chapter 4 Sets, Functions and Relations 4.1 Sets Sets are such a basic notion in mathematics that the only way to ‘define’ them is by synonyms like collection, class, grouping and so on. A set is completely characterised by the elements it contains. There are two main ways of defining a set: (1) by explicitly listing all its elements or (2) by giving a property that all elements must satisfy. Here is a couple of examples, the first is a set of fruits given by listing its elements, the second is a set of natural numbers given by specifying a property: A = {apple, banana, cherry, peach} E = {n ∈ N | 2 divides n} The definition of E can be read: E is the set of those natural numbers that are divisible by 2, that is, it’s the set of all even naturals. The first definition method can be used only if the set has a finite number of elements. In some cases both methods can be used to define the same set, as in this example: 2 {n ∈ N | n is odd ∧ n + n ≤ 100} = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9} To say that a certain object x is an element of a set S, we write x ∈ S. To say that it isn’t an element of S we write x 6∈ S. For example: apple ∈ A 7 6∈ E strawberry 6∈ A 8 ∈ E If every element of a set X is also an element of another set Y , then we say that X is a subset of Y and we write this symbolically as X ⊆ Y .
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory Background for Probability Defining Sets (A Very Naïve Approach)
    Set theory background for probability Defining sets (a very naïve approach) A set is a collection of distinct objects. The objects within a set may be arbitrary, with the order of objects within them having no significance. Here are several examples, demonstrating the above properties: 2,3,5,7,11,13,17,19 (the set of all prime numbers smaller than 20) , , , , , ,′′ The brackets … surround the objects that belong to a certain set. Objects are separated by commas. Note that: 1,2,3 1,3,2 (there is no ordering of objects within a set) 1,2,3,3 1,2,3 (sets contain one copy of each distinct object) Working with sets 1. Membership If an object is a member of a set we write: ∈. If an object is not a member of a set we write: ∉. 2. Subsets Assume that we have a set and another set , such that every element in is also a member of . Then we can write: ⊆. We say that is a subset of . Formally, we can write: ∀∈∈ (any that is a member of is a member of ) No need to worry: we will usually not encounter this formal logic notation. Notice that the sets of , may actually be equal. If they are not, there must be some member of that is not a member of . In this case we can write: ⊂ i.e. is a true subset of , or in logic notation: ∀ ∈ ∈ ∧∃∈∈ (any that is in is in AND there exists a in that is not in ). 3. Set equality Sets , are equal if and only if ⊆ and ⊆.
    [Show full text]
  • Measures in Boolean Algebras
    MEASURES IN BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS BY ALFRED HORN AND ALFRED TARSKI Introduction. By a measure on a Boolean algebra we understand as usual a function defined over all elements of the algebra, assuming finite non-nega- tive real numbers as values (but not identically vanishing), and satisfying the condition of finite additivity: the function value at a sum of two disjoint elements equals the sum of the function values at these elements. By includ- ing in this definition some additional conditions we arrive at special kinds of measures: two-valued measures, strictly positive measures, and countably addi- tive measures. In §1 we concern ourselves with the general notion of measure; we show how a measure—and in particular a two-valued measure—defined on a sub- algebra of a given Boolean algebra, or even on an arbitrary subset of the algebra, can be extended to the whole algebra. In §§2 and 3 we consider spe- cial kinds of measures, in fact, strictly positive and countably additive meas- ures, and we establish several partial criteria (necessary or sufficient condi- tions) for their existence. Some of the results stated in this paper can be ob- tained in a roundabout way from what is to be found in the literature, but they will be provided here with rather simple and direct proofs, without applying notions not involved in the formulation of the results. Terminology and symbolism^). Given any two sets A and B, we denote their union (or sum) by A\JB, their intersection (or product) by AC\B, their difference by A —B.
    [Show full text]
  • Field ( -Algebra)
    σ-field (σ-algebra) We will shown later that the class 2X of all subsets can be too large for our quantities of interest to hold, with consistency, across all member of the class. In this section, we present smaller classes which have several “nice” properties. • Let X be a (nonempty) set (universal), and F is a family/set of subsets of X. F is called a field (or algebra ) (of sets) provided that 1) ∅∈F (or X ∈F or F is non-empty.) 2) AA∈⇒FFc ∈. 3) AB, ∈⇒∪∈FF A B . • F ⊂ 2X 3* ) AB, ∈⇒∩∈FF A B c Proof. AB∩=()cc A ∪ B • AB,\∈⇒FF A B ∈ Proof. A \ BA=∩c B. • Property (1) can be replaced by X ∈F because they are equivalent under property (2). • Property (1) can be replaced by (*) F is non-empty. This is because, (2) and (3) implies that (1) is equivalent to (*). Proof. “⇒” Trivial. ∅∈F ⇒ F is non-empty. “⇐” If F is non-empty, then there exists A∈ F. Now, by (2) , we have Ac is also in F. Hence, by (3), XAA=∪c ∈F . By (2), ∅ =∈X c F . • Property (3) can be replaced by (3* ) : AB, ∈ FF⇒∩∈ A B . Proof. Under (2), we will show that (3) is equivalent to (3* ) . Suppose AB, ∈ F ; by (2), we have ABcc, ∈ F . Now, suppose we have (3), then c ABcc∪∈F . Apply (2) again, we have AB∩ =∪( Acc B) ∈F . Similarly, suppose we have (3* ) . Then, ABcc∩ ∈ F . Apply (2) and we c then have AB∪=( Acc ∩ B) ∈F . • AB,\∈⇒Δ=FF A B() A B ∪ B\ A ∈.
    [Show full text]
  • Sigma-Algebra from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Sigma-algebra From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Algebra of sets The algebra of sets defines the properties and laws of sets, the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection, and complementation and the relations of set equality and set inclusion. It also provides systematic procedures for evalu- ating expressions, and performing calculations, involving these operations and relations. Any set of sets closed under the set-theoretic operations forms a Boolean algebra with the join operator being union, the meet operator being intersection, and the complement operator being set complement. 1.1 Fundamentals The algebra of sets is the set-theoretic analogue of the algebra of numbers. Just as arithmetic addition and multiplication are associative and commutative, so are set union and intersection; just as the arithmetic relation “less than or equal” is reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive, so is the set relation of “subset”. It is the algebra of the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection and complementation, and the relations of equality and inclusion. For a basic introduction to sets see the article on sets, for a fuller account see naive set theory, and for a full rigorous axiomatic treatment see axiomatic set theory. 1.2 The fundamental laws of set algebra The binary operations of set union ( [ ) and intersection ( \ ) satisfy many identities. Several of these identities or “laws” have well established names. Commutative laws: • A [ B = B [ A • A \ B = B \ A Associative laws: • (A [ B) [ C = A [ (B [ C) • (A \ B) \ C = A \ (B \ C) Distributive laws: • A [ (B \ C) = (A [ B) \ (A [ C) • A \ (B [ C) = (A \ B) [ (A \ C) The analogy between unions and intersections of sets, and addition and multiplication of numbers, is quite striking.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets and Probability
    CHAPTER 1 Sets and Probability In a survey of 200 people that had just returned from a trip to Europe, the following informa- tion was gathered. • 142 visited England • 95 visited Italy • 65 visited Germany • 70 visited both England and Italy • 50 visited both England and Germany • 30 visited both Italy and Germany • 20 visited all three of these countries How many went to England but not Italy or Germany? We will learn how to solve puzzles like this in the second section of the chapter when count- ing the elements in a set is discussed. Exerpt from Applied Finite Mathematics by Tomastik and Epstein (c) 2008 Cengage Learning 1.1 Introduction to Sets 13 1.1 Introduction to Sets This section discusses operations on sets and the laws governing these set opera- tions. These are fundamental notions that will be used throughout the remainder of this text. In the next two chapters we will see that probability and statistics are based on counting the elements in sets and manipulating set operations. Thus we first need to understand clearly the notion of sets and their operations. ✧ The Language of Sets We begin here with some definitions of the language and notation used when working with sets. The most basic definition is “What is a set?” A set is a HISTORICAL NOTE collection of items. These items are referred to as the elements or members of George Boole, 1815–1864 the set. For example, the set containing the numbers 1, 2, and 3 would be written {1,2,3}. Notice that the set is contained in curly brackets.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Boolean Algebras
    California State University, San Bernardino CSUSB ScholarWorks Electronic Theses, Projects, and Dissertations Office of aduateGr Studies 12-2016 AN INTRODUCTION TO BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Amy Schardijn California State University - San Bernardino Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/etd Part of the Algebra Commons Recommended Citation Schardijn, Amy, "AN INTRODUCTION TO BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS" (2016). Electronic Theses, Projects, and Dissertations. 421. https://scholarworks.lib.csusb.edu/etd/421 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Office of aduateGr Studies at CSUSB ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses, Projects, and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of CSUSB ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. An Introduction to Boolean Algebras A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of California State University, San Bernardino In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts in Mathematics by Amy Michiel Schardijn December 2016 An Introduction to Boolean Algebras A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of California State University, San Bernardino by Amy Michiel Schardijn December 2016 Approved by: Dr. Giovanna Llosent, Committee Chair Date Dr. Jeremy Aikin, Committee Member Dr. Corey Dunn, Committee Member Dr. Charles Stanton, Chair, Dr. Corey Dunn Department of Mathematics Graduate Coordinator, Department of Mathematics iii Abstract This thesis discusses the topic of Boolean algebras. In order to build intuitive understanding of the topic, research began with the investigation of Boolean algebras in the area of Abstract Algebra. The content of this initial research used a particular nota- tion. The ideas of partially ordered sets, lattices, least upper bounds, and greatest lower bounds were used to define the structure of a Boolean algebra.
    [Show full text]
  • Section 2.3. the Σ-Algebra of Lebesgue Measurable Sets
    2.3. Lebesgue Measurable Sets 1 Section 2.3. The σ-Algebra of Lebesgue Measurable Sets Note. In Theorem 2.18 we will see that there are disjoint sets A and B such that m∗(A ∪· B) < m∗(A) + m∗(B) and so m∗ is not countably additive (it is not even finitely additive). We must have countable additivity in our measure in order to use it for integration. To accomplish this, we restrict m∗ to a smaller class than P(R) on which m∗ is countably additive. As we will see, the following condition will yield a collection of sets on which m∗ is countably additive. Definition. Any set E is (Lebesgue) measurable if for all A ⊂ R, m∗(A) = m∗(A ∩ E) + m∗(A ∩ Ec). This is called the Carath´eodory splitting condition. Note. It certainly isn’t clear that the Carath´eodory splitting condition leads to countable additivity, but notice that it does involve the sum of measures of two disjoint sets (A ∩ E and A ∩ Ec). Note. The Carath´eodory splitting condition, in a sense, requires us to “check” all ℵ2 subsets A of R in order to establish the measurability of a set E. It is shown in Problem 2.20 that if m∗(E) < ∞, then E is measurable if and only if m∗((a, b)) = m∗((a, b)∩E)+m∗((a, b)∩Ec). This is a significant result, since there are “only” ℵ1 intervals of the form (a, b). 2.3. Lebesgue Measurable Sets 2 Note. Recall that we define a function to be Riemann integrable if the upper Riemann integral equals the lower Riemann integral.
    [Show full text]
  • A MINIMAL MODEL for SET THEORY in the Proof of The
    A MINIMAL MODEL FOR SET THEORY BY PAUL J. COHEN1 Communicated by Paul R. Halmos, March 22, 1963 In the proof of the consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis and the Axiom of Choice with the other axioms of set theory, Gödel [l] introduced the notion of a constructible set and showed that the con­ structible sets form a model for set theory. These sets are intuitively those which can be reached by means of a transfinite sequence of several simple operations. He then showed that the Axiom of Choice and Continuum Hypothesis held in the collection of constructible sets. If the original universe of sets is sufficiently rich in ordinal numbers, it will follow that every set is constructible, in which case we say that the Axiom of Constructibility is satisfied. This axiom implies the two axioms previously mentioned. However, from one point of view it may seem that this notion of constructibility does not intuitively cor­ respond to what is meant by constructive since it may happen that all sets in the universe are constructive. In this paper we show that a more restricted notion of "construction" will yield a class of sets which form a minimal model for set theory. In this manner we prove the consistency of a stronger form of the Axiom of Constructibility. We observe that the idea of a minimal collection of objects satisfying certain axioms is well known in mathematics, for example, in group theory one often considers the subgroup generated by a collection of elements, and in measure theory we define the Borel sets as the small­ est <r-algebra of sets containing the open sets.
    [Show full text]