<<

THE MONOTONE CLASS THEOREM

JACOPO DE SIMOI

Abstract. The proof of the Monotone Class Theorem is given in the bookby Lieb–Loss but differs from the one I gave in class. Please find below the version that was given in class on Sept 13. Recall the relevant definitions; here 푋 is a non-empty . • an algebra of sets on 푋 is a 풜 ⊂ 풫(푋) that is closed under and finite unions • an algebra is a σ-algebra if it is also closed under countable unions. • a monotone class is a family of sets 풞 ⊂ 풫(푋) with the property that the (countable) of any increasing sequence of sets in 풞 is also in 풞 and the (countable) intersection of any decreasing sequence of sets in 풞 is also in 풞. Observe that any σ-algebra is a monotone class. Lemma 0.1. If a family ℱ is an algebra and a monotone class then it is indeed a σ-algebra. Proof. We need to show that countable union of any sequence of sets in ℱ belongs to ℱ. Let {퐸푘}푘∈N ⊂ ℱ be a sequence of sets; then construct the sequence 푘 퐹푘 = ⋃ 퐸푘 푖=1

Since ℱ is an algebra, 퐹푘 ∈ ℱ for any 푘 ∈ N; moreover the sets 퐹푘 form an increasing sequence, therefore

ℱ ∋ ⋃ 퐹푘 = ⋃ 퐸푘. 푘∈N 푘∈N We conclude that ℱ is a σ-algebra.  Given any family ℱ ⊂ 풫(푋) we can define the following objects • the σ-algebra generated by ℱ, denoted by ℳ(ℱ) is the smallest σ-algebra of sets of 푋 that contains ℱ; • the monotone class generated by ℱ, denoted by 풞(ℱ) is the smalles t monotone class that contains ℱ. Notice that if ℱ ⊂ ℳ(ℱ′) (resp. ℱ ⊂ 풞(ℱ′)) we have ℳ(ℱ) ⊂ ℳ(ℱ′). Moreover, since any σ-algebra is a monotone class we immediately conclude that for any family ℱ, 풞(ℱ) ⊂ ℳ(ℱ). The Monotone Class Theorem guarantees that if ℱ is an algebra, then this becomes an . 1 2 JACOPO DE SIMOI

Theorem 0.2. Let 풜 be an algebra of sets on 푋; then 풞(풜) = ℳ(풜). Proof. To ease notation, since 풜 is fixed let us write 풞 = 풞(풜) and ℳ = ℳ(풜) without possibility of confusion. First of all observe that it suffices to show that 풞 is a σ-algebra; then since 풞 ⊃ 풜 and by the minimality of ℳ we can conclude that ℳ ⊂ 풞; this, together with the trivial inclusion mentioned above concludes the proof. Observe moreover that by the above lemma it suffices to show that 풞 is an algebra; in order to do so we need to show that the class is invariant under finite unions and complements. In order to show the by the complement , let us define

풞∗ = {퐸 ∈ 풞|푋 ∖ 퐸 ∈ 풞}

Observe that by design 풞∗ ⊂ 풞; moreover since 풜 is an algebra we have that each element of 풜 will be in 풞∗, therefore we have 풜 ⊂ 풞∗. If we now show that 풞∗ is a monotone class, we can conclude –by the minimality of 풞– that 풞 ⊂ 풞∗, which would then imply that 풞∗ is the entire 풞, i.e. 풞 is closed by the complement operation. The proof that 풞∗ is a monotone class is a routine check and follows from the definition [it is left to the reader] Let us now show that the set 풞 is closed under finite unions. For any element 퐸 ∈ 풞 we define

풞퐸 = {퐹 ∈ 풞|퐸 ∪ 퐹 ∈ 풞} ⊂ 풞}

Observe that, by the symmetry of the definition we have 퐹 ∈ 풞퐸 if and only if 퐸 ∈ 풞퐹. Also, a routine check shows that 풞퐸 is a monotone class for any choice of 퐸 [do it!]. If we manage to show that 풜 ⊂ 풞퐸 for any 퐸 ∈ 풞, we will conclude that 풞 ⊂ 풞퐸, and thus 풞 = 풞퐸 for any 퐸 which shows closure of 풞 under finite unions. In order to prove that 풜 ⊂ 풞퐸 for any 퐸 ∈ 풞, let us now choose 퐴 ∈ 풜; observe that for any 퐵 ∈ 풜 we have 퐴 ∪ 퐵 ∈ 풜 (by definition of algebra), thus 퐴 ∪ 퐵 ∈ 풞, which implies that 퐵 ∈ 풞퐴. Since 퐵 was arbitrary we conclude that 풜 ⊂ 풞퐴 for any 퐴 ∈ 풜. Since 풞퐴 is a monotone class, by minimality of 풞 among all minimal classes containing 풜, we conclude that 풞퐴 = 풞. Otherwise said: for any 퐸 ∈ 풞 and 퐴 ∈ 풜 we have 퐸 ∈ 풞퐴. But by symmetry this implies that 퐴 ∈ 풞퐸 for any 퐸 ∈ 풞, or 풜 ⊂ 풞, that was what we wanted to show.