Theology and Constitutional Theory in Thomas Hobbes and James Harrington

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Theology and Constitutional Theory in Thomas Hobbes and James Harrington Theology and Constitutional Theory in Thomas Hobbes and James Harrington For Workshop on ‘Theological Foundations of Modern Constitutional Theory’, Institute d’Etudes Avancées de Nantes, 20-21 January 2016 Thomas Poole London School of Economics & Political Science Politics is concerned with coercive forms of human association. Constitutions concern how such associations are organized. Three forms of association are relevant to an inquiry into the theological roots of modern constitutional theory. First and most obvious is civil association: that is, membership of a political community or body politic, a form of association whose characteristic feature is subjection to the same body of (civil) law. Second, religious association: that is, membership of a religious community or Church. A central feature of this type of association is a shared set of beliefs about man’s relationship to the world and to the Divine, and associated obligations, practices and rituals. Third, an association of political associations – increasingly as we move into the modern period an association of states – or what we have come to call the international order, centrally comprised of the rights and duties of sovereign states, a system which remained largely inchoate during the period in question.1 The first two forms of association – civil and religious – naturally form the central focus of an inquiry into early modern political theology. Indeed, the manner in which the early moderns began to articulate a vision of man and his place in the world in which the political and the theological were separated is a defining moment in the arrival of modernity.2 This is not to deny the continued resonance of conceptions, arrangements 1 One of the leading historians of international law, Martti Koskenniemi, argues that there is no international law properly so called until the later nineteenth century: see his The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-1960 (Cambridge, 2001). Bentham seems to have been the first to coin the phrase ‘international law’ in the 1780s. 2 This is a key aspect of what Jonathan Israel calls the ‘crisis of the European mind’: see Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650-1750 (Oxford, 2001), 14-22. See also Israel, A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy (Princeton, 2010). 1 and habits of mind derived from medieval politics and theology.3 But, over time, the new conception came to dismantle the ‘enchanted world’ and led to the redrawing of the presuppositions and practices of social and political life. 4 And, indeed, most of the thinkers discussed in our workshop – with the exception of Grotius but including Thomas Hobbes and James Harrington, the subjects of this paper – had as their primary concern the domestic or interior construction of the commonwealth. It is a mistake to overlook the third type of association, however, and with it the outward facing dimensions of the state and its interactions with other political forms.5 Not only is it an important, if under-elaborated, aspect of this body of thought, one which affords us glimpses into the developing world of modern, post-Westphalian international law and international relations. It also reveals the extent and consequences of the deconstruction of pre-existing juridical and associational linkages across the ius publicum europaeum, a process that involved the fracturing of the medieval image of the res publica Christiana. This process of destruction and reconstruction opened up new vistas for the newly sovereign state. A benefit of pairing Hobbes and Harrington is that despite a considerable overlap in their political outlook, they reach rather different conclusions about the future shape of the international order. Their analysis raises the question of empire and of imperial- commercial confrontation, soon to become endemic to the European state system. It also invites us to reflect about how legal relations between the newly minted sovereign states or commonwealths, all the more so given that these writers saw the modern state as an architectonic structure of legal rule – an ‘Artificiall Man’ (Hobbes) 6 – whose function was to make peaceful coexistence possible by way of a sovereign power of legislation and a unitary power of judicature – an ‘empire of laws and not of men’ (Harrington).7 To our disenchanted eyes, these now appear straight questions of law and politics into which theology need not intrude, questions of ‘public reason’ in the 3 See, e.g., Joseph R. Strayer, On the Medieval Origins of the Modern State (Princeton, 1970); Michael Oakeshott, Lectures in the History of Political Thought (Imprint Academic, 2006), chs 23 & 24. 4 For a majestic philosophical and historical analysis of these changes see Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Harvard, 2007). For a reconsideration of the pre-modern condition see, e.g., Euan Cameron, Enchanted Europe: Superstition and Religion 1250-1750 (Oxford, 2010). 5 Richard Tuck makes a similar observation in The Rights of War and Peace: Political Thought and the International Order from Grotius to Kant (Oxford, 1999). See also David Armitage, Foundations of Modern International Thought (Cambridge, 2013). 6 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Cambridge, ed. Richard Tuck, 1991), 9. 7 James Harrington, The Commonwealth of Oceana (Cambridge, ed. J.G.A. Pocock, 1992), 21. See also Leviathan, 168: ‘all Judicature is essentially annexed to the Soveraignty’. 2 Rawlsian idiom.8 But as we shall see, to contemporaries – even those, like Hobbes and Harrington, who were not obviously religious – they were anything but. * * * * * Let us consider first how the ‘master leveller’ 9 himself handled the three modes of association and the relationship between them. One is tempted to call Hobbes’s strategy on this point one of divide and conquer. Let me explain why. The goal of his political theory was the erection and maintenance of an institutionally untrammelled and normatively untroubled sovereign state apparatus, the existence of which was essential, Hobbes argued, for peaceful coexistence. This theory required a primary conceptual move that rendered our forms of association are distinct and separate (or at least separable) modes. This is not to deny that, in some sense or other, these forms of association had a distinct conceptual existence within the medieval political imaginary.10 This is evident if we consider the intellectual traditions on which Hobbes drew: Erastianism, for instance, which sought to claim civil jurisdiction over ecclesiastical matters;11 and the tradition of idealizing civil religion that went back to Machiavelli.12 Hobbes navigates these modes of association in an original way,13 the effect of which is systematically to redraw the boundaries between them. (The modes of association interact as a complex whole in Hobbes’s theory, but for the sake of the analysis I treat them separately.) With civil association we see a thorough and complete move to deny any independent authority to intermediate forms of association – Norberto Bobbio calls them partial societies14 – those institutions that represent or reflect sites of power other than those of the sovereign. As sovereignty is centrally a matter of jurisdiction, the power 8 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (Columbia, 1993). 9 Mark Lilla, The Stillborn God: Religion, Politics, and the Modern West (Vintage, 2008), 77. 10 On the relationship between Hobbes and both the Protestant Reformation jurists and theologians and the Catholic Scholastic tradition see Annabel S. Brett, Changes of State: Nature and the Limits of the City in Early Modern Natural Law (Princeton, 2011). 11 Erastianism exerted a considerable pull in England from the mid-sixteenth century for reasons connected with Tudor statecraft: see Jeffrey R. Collins, The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes (Oxford, 2005), ch. 1. 12 See, e.g., J.G.A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, 1975), ch. 11. 13 J.P. Sommerville, ‘Absolutism and Royalism’ in J.H. Burns and Mark Goldie (eds), The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450-1700 (Cambridge, 1991), 372: ‘In England, only the most extreme of Erastian theorists denied that the clergy possessed spiritual authority independently of the prince.’ 14 Norberto Bobbio, Thomas Hobbes and the Natural Law Tradition (Chicago, 1993), ch. 6. Hobbes himself tends to use the term ‘systems’ to indicate collective bodies – see e.g. the title of Leviathan, ch. 22 ‘Of Systems Subject, Political and Private’. 3 to legislate and to adjudicate, the legal dimensions of this move are especially clear. Hobbes systematically downgrades forms of law other than civil law, which is now defined austerely as the public commands of the sovereign.15 Common law, canon law, customary law, natural law – each a familiar semi-autonomous source of normativity – all are brought under the sovereign’s jurisdiction. The proximate rationale for this root and branch programme of juridical harmonizing was the need for a single public voice. The sovereign’s commands provide the standards of right in relation to which the subjects are to organize their lives and resolve their conflicts. These laws are in the final analysis self-imposed and self-authored, 16 and constitute ‘Artificiall Chains’17 that link sovereign and subject. The ultimate rationale is peace: any other arrangement runs the risk of disagreement and so tends towards the dissolution of the
Recommended publications
  • Res Publica: an International Framework for Education in Democracy
    RES PUBLICA: AN INTERNATIONAL FRAMEWORK FOR EDUCATION IN DEMOCRACY Revised January 2006 Civitas: An International Civic Education Exchange Program of the Center for Civic Education 5146 Douglas Fir Road / Calabasas, CA 91302 / USA 818-591-9321 / fax 818-591-9330 / [email protected] 1 This project is conducted as a part of Civitas: An International Civic Education Exchange Program administered by the Center for Civic Education. The project is supported by the United States Department of Education and conducted with the assistance of the United States Information Agency and its affiliated offices in nations throughout the world. 2003 Center for Civic Education 07 06 05 1 2 3 All rights reserved. Except for use in a review, reproduction or transmittal of this work in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, and use of this work in any form in any information storage or retrieval system is forbidden without prior written permission from the publisher. The U.S. Department of Education disclaims any responsibility for any opinion or conclusions contained herein. The federal government reserves a nonexclusive license to use and reproduce for government purposes, without payment, this material where the government deems it in its interest to do so. ISBN 0-89818-194-1 Res Publica: An International Framework for Education in Democracy Introduction Res Publica: An International Framework for Education in Democracy is an attempt to develop a cross- cultural and trans-national general statement of the central meanings and character of the ideas, values, principles, and institutions of democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Law As the Law of the Res Publica Elisabeth Zoller
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Indiana University Bloomington Maurer School of Law Maurer School of Law: Indiana University Digital Repository @ Maurer Law Articles by Maurer Faculty Faculty Scholarship 2008 Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica Elisabeth Zoller Follow this and additional works at: http://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, European Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Zoller, Elisabeth, "Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica" (2008). Articles by Maurer Faculty. Paper 146. http://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub/146 This Conference Proceeding is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by Maurer Faculty by an authorized administrator of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PUBLIC LAW AS THE LAW OF THE RES PUBLICA Elisabeth Zoller* A LECTURE GIVEN AS PART OF SUFFOLK TRANSNATIONAL LAW REVIEW'S 2008 DISTINGUISHED SPEAKER COLLOQUIUM SERIES In 1989, on the occasion of the Bicentennial of the French Revolution, I gave a talk at Suffolk University Law School on The Distinction Between Man and the Citizen in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen of 1789.1 In retrospect, I am afraid that this may not have been one of my best talks. The truth of the matter is that I failed to give the rationale for this crucial distinction and its meaning in the Declaration of 1789.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Jurisprudence: Liberty and Equality in Rawls and Dworkin
    The Catholic Lawyer Volume 25 Number 2 Volume 25, Spring 1980, Number 2 Article 4 The Politics of Jurisprudence: Liberty and Equality in Rawls and Dworkin Stephen C. Hicks Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl Part of the Jurisprudence Commons This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Catholic Lawyer by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE POLITICS OF JURISPRUDENCE: LIBERTY AND EQUALITY IN RAWLS AND DWORKIN STEPHEN C. HICKS* Law as a general system of rules impartially applied acts as the me- dium of sovereign governmental order harmonizing the interests of indi- viduals and groups in society as equally and fairly as possible. The indi- vidual is free within the rules establishing security and order and is free from law which is not conducive to the general good. Similarly, an indi- vidual is free to pursue his own ends if they are compatible with the greatest happiness of the greatest number and also is free not to act on behalf of the common good. While these boundaries are defined by law, the actual social relations within them are the concern of ethics or psy- chology, not legislation.' Thus, political theory as utilitarianism sees the law according to its own representation of the good and its own descrip- tion of human nature. This is the original coordination of individual soci- ety and the body politic in our tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Public Law As the Law of the Res Publica
    Maurer School of Law: Indiana University Digital Repository @ Maurer Law Articles by Maurer Faculty Faculty Scholarship 2008 Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica Elisabeth Zoller Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, European Law Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Zoller, Elisabeth, "Public Law as the Law of the Res Publica" (2008). Articles by Maurer Faculty. 146. https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/facpub/146 This Conference Proceeding is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by Maurer Faculty by an authorized administrator of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PUBLIC LAW AS THE LAW OF THE RES PUBLICA Elisabeth Zoller* A LECTURE GIVEN AS PART OF SUFFOLK TRANSNATIONAL LAW REVIEW'S 2008 DISTINGUISHED SPEAKER COLLOQUIUM SERIES In 1989, on the occasion of the Bicentennial of the French Revolution, I gave a talk at Suffolk University Law School on The Distinction Between Man and the Citizen in the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen of 1789.1 In retrospect, I am afraid that this may not have been one of my best talks. The truth of the matter is that I failed to give the rationale for this crucial distinction and its meaning in the Declaration of 1789. I said that the distinction was almost invisible in this country and much less important than in the French legal system, but I did not explain why.
    [Show full text]
  • The Icelandic Federalist Papers
    The Icelandic Federalist Papers No. 16: The Conformity of the Plan to Republican Principles To the People of Iceland: Before examining the republican character of the new plan, it is first necessary to explain the meanings of the terms and their relevance to the standards fixed in Iceland. The term republic originates from Latin “res publica,” “the common weal, a commonwealth, state, republic,” liter- ally res publica “public interest, the state,” from res “affair, matter, thing” combined with publi- ca, feminine of publicus or “public.”1 From a constitutional perspective, a republic is a country in which the head of state’s position is not hereditary.2 The president (or other chief executive) may be elected, appointed, or nominated to exercise the head of state position. This concept is the opposite of a kingdom, in which a monarch exercises power because of filiation. Historically, the term “republic” was first used in ancient Rome and thereafter where power was not exercised by a royal family, as for example in the case of Venice. The term may refer to a system that is neither monarchical nor imperial. A republic does not necessarily mean democracy since the president may be designated through authority; there are many examples of undemocratic republics among Latin American dictatorships or in the former USSR. The founda- tions of a republic are based on a will, a desire to represent the social body. It also has a norma- tive meaning connected to a judgment of values and the possibility for people to exercise their sovereignty. Even though the idea of both democracy and constitutional government emerged in Athens, the first known city republic took shape around 506 BC in India where, for the first time, a ruler was elected.
    [Show full text]
  • Talking Politics Constructing the Res Publica After Caesar’S Assassination
    TALKING POLITICS: CONSTRUCTING THE RES PUBLICA AFTER CAESAR'S ASSASSINATION Hannah J. Swithinbank A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2010 Full metadata for this item is available in Research@StAndrews:FullText at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/910 This item is protected by original copyright This item is licensed under a Creative Commons Licence Talking Politics Constructing the res publica after Caesar’s assassination Hannah J. Swithinbank Ph.D. December 2009 Abstract The nature of the Republican constitution has been much contested by scholars studying the history of the Roman Republic. In considering the problems of the late Republic, the nature of the constitution is an important question, for if we do not understand what the constitution was, how can we explain Rome’s transition from ‘Republic’ to ‘Empire’? Such a question is particularly pertinent when looking at events at Rome following the assassination of Caesar, as we try to understand why it was that the Republic, as we understand it as a polity without a sole ruler, was not restored. This thesis examines the Roman understanding of the constitution in the aftermath of Caesar’s death and argues that for the Romans the constitution was a contested entity, its proper nature debated and fought over, and that this contest led to conflict on the political stage, becoming a key factor in the failure to restore the Republic and the establishment of the Second Triumvirate.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Download
    Oñati Socio-Legal Series, v. 1, n. 5 (2011) ISSN: 2079-5971 A European res publica ∗ OLA ZETTERQUIST Abstract The article analyses the fundamental constitutional enigma of the European Union (EU), namely whether the EU can be considered as a (from its Member States) separate and independent constitutional legal order. The EU is often referred to as a legal order sui generis, i.e. of a unique character that defies traditional definitions. More specifically, the notion of an independent and separate EU is at odds with the idea of the sovereign state. The notion of the EU as a legal order sui generis is too much influenced by the models of the sovereign state and sovereignty (in the vein of Thomas Hobbes). The key component in the Hobbesian idea of sovereignty is freedom as non-interference. A sovereign state is consequently a state that is free from, i.e. not interfered with by, external actors like, for example, the EU. Put differently, either the EU is sovereign or the Member States are sovereign. By shifting the perspective to a neo-Roman republican understanding of freedom as non-domination the constitutional picture of the EU will become more nuanced. Res publica is best understood as what citizens hold in common and above their narrow self-interest. According to a republican notion of the constitution the purpose of the law is to eliminate the possibility of arbitrary domination. For that reason, not all interference is to be considered as a restriction of freedom but only those restrictions that cannot be justified according to the res publica.
    [Show full text]
  • Civic Virtue Must Begin with Nitarians Especially) Worry That Widespread the Meaning of Virtue in General
    C i v i c V i r t u e always under that description. One might argue, for example, that a failure in the F r a n k L o v e t t necessary congruence ultimately doomed soviet-style communism, and some (commu- Any discussion of civic virtue must begin with nitarians especially) worry that widespread the meaning of virtue in general. A virtue, on liberal individualism is gradually eroding the the standard view at least since Aristotle, is a institutional foundations of liberal societies as settled disposition exhibiting type-specific well. Though he did not use the expression excellence. Thus, for example, since the central “civic virtue,” the problem of congruence was purpose of a knife is to cut things, it is a virtue absolutely central to the third part of Rawls’s A in knives to be sharp. Similarly, one might Theory of Justice . In the mainstream tradition argue, since sociability is an important of western political thought, however, the characteristic of human beings, it is a human importance of civic virtue most strongly reso- virtue to be disposed to form friendships. To be nated among writers associated with what is a genuine virtue, of course, this disposition usually called the “classical republican” political must be firmly settled or resilient: much as it tradition. would detract from the virtuosity of an excep- The classical republicans were a diverse tionally sharp knife if its edge dulled after a group of political writers, including among single use, so too would it detract from the others Machiavelli and his fifteenth-century virtue of a human being if he or she were only a Italian predecessors; the English republicans fair-weather friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Belief Defending Religious Liberty Through the British Bill of Rights
    Green Paper Green Paper Green Paper Green Paper Green Paper November 2016 Beyond Belief Defending religious liberty through the British Bill of Rights James Orr About the Author Dr James Orr is McDonald Postdoctoral Fellow in Theology, Ethics, and Public Life at Christ Church, University of Oxford. Dr Orr’s research spans topics and thinkers on both the continental and analytic traditions of philosophical theology and theological ethics. His current work engages recent attempts to formulate a coherent theory of value. Acknowledgements The author would like to thank Nola Leach, Dan Boucher, Phillip Blond, Caroline Julian, John Milbank, William Kløverød Griffiths and Vanessa Schneider for their assistance on this project. A special thanks is also due to Care, as without their support this project would not be possible. ResPublica would also like to thank the following members of the project Advisory Group: 1. Professor Eileen Barker OBE, Emeritus Professor of Sociology, LSE 2. Br James Boner, General Secretary, Conference of Religions 3. Fiona Bruce MP, Chair, APPG on Religious Education 4. Paul Diamond, Standing Counsel, Christian Legal Centre 5. The Rt Hon Sir Jeffrey Donaldson MP, Vice Chair, APPG on Christians in Parliament 6. Peter Kearney, Director, Scottish Catholic Media Office 7. Mohammad Kozbar, Vice President, Muslim Association of Britain 8. Jay Lakhani, Director of Religious Education, Hindu Council UK 9. Michelle Lawrence, Founder and Director, Link Up (UK) 10. Simon McCrossan, Head of Public Policy, Evangelical Alliance 11. Gurmel Singh, Secretary General, Sikh Council UK 12. Nick Spencer, Research Director, Theos 13. Dr Opinderjit Kaur Takhar, Senior Lecturer, University of Wolverhampton 14.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continental Shelf and the Extension of the Territorial Sea
    University of Miami Law Review Volume 10 Number 4 Miami Law Quarterly Article 5 7-1-1956 The Continental Shelf and the Extension of the Territorial Sea Dr. Theodore Alvarado Garaioca Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umlr Recommended Citation Dr. Theodore Alvarado Garaioca, The Continental Shelf and the Extension of the Territorial Sea, 10 U. Miami L. Rev. 490 (1956) Available at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umlr/vol10/iss4/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Miami Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE CONTINENTAL SHELF AND THE EXTENSION OF THE TERRITORIAL SEA DR. THEODORE ALVARADO GARAIOCA* International Law, influenced by the progress of modern armaments, as well as by the discovery of new natural resources, has had to consider claims tending to modify the traditional determination of the territorial sea, incorporating a new and important element: the so-called continental shelf. It is well to remember that the concept of the "territorial sea" was the subject of a long and arduous discussion. In this inflamed theoretical dispute, several theories were advanced, based upon the opposite principles of the "closed sea" and the "free sea"; the concept of the sea being "rcs nullius" (belonging to nobody) was advanced against the concept of the sea as "res communis" (common to all).
    [Show full text]
  • The Body Politic from Medieval Lombardy to the Dutch Republic
    _full_journalsubtitle: A Journal for the Study of Science, Technology and Medicine in the Pre-modern Period _full_abbrevjournaltitle: ESM _full_ppubnumber: ISSN 1383-7427 (print version) _full_epubnumber: ISSN 1573-3823 (online version) _full_issue: 1 _full_issuetitle: The Body Politic from Medieval Lombardy to the Dutch Republic _full_alt_author_running_head (neem stramien J2 voor dit article en vul alleen 0 in hierna): 0 _full_alt_articletitle_running_head (rechter kopregel - mag alles zijn): The Body Politic: Introduction _full_is_advance_article: 0 _full_article_language: en indien anders: engelse articletitle: 0 The Body Politic: EarlyIntroduction Science and Medicine 25 (2020) 1-7 1 www.brill.com/esm The Body Politic from Medieval Lombardy to the Dutch Republic: An Introduction Vasileios Syros University of Jyväskylä, Finland [email protected] The content of this special issue is based on three of the presentations de- livered at the international conference “The Body Politic and Social Harmony: From the Middle Ages to the Present.” The event was held on 28 and 29 May 2018 at the Meeting and Conference Center Soeterbeeck in Ravenstein, The Netherlands, under the auspices of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences (KNAW), and corresponded with my appointment as KNAW Visit- ing Professor at the Faculty of Philosophy, Theology and Religious Studies at Radboud University Nijmegen during spring 2017 and spring 2018. The body politic metaphor, widely invoked in envisioning various modes of the existence and operation of a harmonious society, has been an enduring feature in the evolution of political thought, both in the “West” and elsewhere. The conference drew upon the cumulative expertise of scholars from different disciplinary backgrounds. It explored iterations of the body politic metaphor and its normative value for conceptions of social and political harmony from the Middle Ages to the present in the European, Islamic, Jewish, Indian, Rus- sian, and East Asian traditions of political theorizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Gendered Citizenship and Islamic Jurisprudence
    Undergraduate Journal of Global Citizenship Volume 3 Issue 1 The Undergraduate Journal of Global Article 5 Citizenship Volume III Issue I May 2019 Woman In The Body Politic: Gendered Citizenship and Islamic Jurisprudence Ankushi A. Mitra Georgetown University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.fairfield.edu/jogc Recommended Citation Mitra, Ankushi A. (2019) "Woman In The Body Politic: Gendered Citizenship and Islamic Jurisprudence," Undergraduate Journal of Global Citizenship: Vol. 3 : Iss. 1 , Article 5. Available at: https://digitalcommons.fairfield.edu/jogc/vol3/iss1/5 This item has been accepted for inclusion in DigitalCommons@Fairfield by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@Fairfield. It is brought to you by DigitalCommons@Fairfield with permission from the rights- holder(s) and is protected by copyright and/or related rights. You are free to use this item in any way that is permitted by the copyright and related rights legislation that applies to your use. For other uses, you need to obtain permission from the rights-holder(s) directly, unless additional rights are indicated by a Creative Commons license in the record and/or on the work itself. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Mitra: Gendered Citizenship and Islamic Jurisprudence Introduction Scholars contest ‘citizenship’ as a concept on a variety of dimensions – from its conceptual meaning1 to political implementation.2 In his influential classical formulation, T. H. Marshall defines citizenship as “a status bestowed on those who are full members of a community,” 3 equal in their rights and duties. My analytical perspective draws on the Marshallian conceptualization, taking citizenship narrowly to mean legal membership of a political4 community (the nation-state).
    [Show full text]