1 Obituary: The Nine Lives of Richard D. Alexander

2

3 Richard D. Alexander, T.H. Hubbell Distinguished

4 University Professor of Biology at the University of

5 Michigan, Curator of Insects at the Museum of

6 Zoology there, a member of the National

7 Academy of Sciences, and a pioneer in the

8 study of the evolutionary basis of human

9 behavior, died on the 20th of August, 2018 at age

10 88. Alexander is survived by his wife of 68 years

11 Lorraine Kearnes Alexander; his brother Noel

12 (Donna); his daughters Susan (Sarita) and Nancy;

13 (Photo by Mark O’Brien) his grandchildren Morgan, Lydia, Lincoln, and

14 Winona; and his great-grandson Ezekiel; several nieces and nephews; and “young"

15 Tom Pyle who lived with Alexander’s family for years while growing up.

16

17 Alexander’s life is an iconic American success story. He rose from humble beginnings,

18 having been born on November 18th, 1929 and raised on a small, single-family farm in

19 rural Illinois, without electricity or indoor plumbing. Although his early schooling took

20 place in a one room school house, and he had no thought of attending college, his good

21 grades and keen intellect enabled him to attend Blackburn College and then Illinois

22 State Normal University, obtaining his bachelor’s degree in 1950. He served in the army

23 during the Korean War, stationed at Fort Knox, then went on complete a PhD in

1 24 Entomology at Ohio State University in 1956. As a graduate student he pioneered the

25 use of new acoustic recording technology developed in WWII, to study insect behavior,

26 revolutionizing the study of acoustic communication and speciation in the process. In

27 1957, he was hired by the , where he spent his career. At

28 Michigan Alexander became a national leader in evolutionary biology. His early career

29 awards include the Newcomb Cleveland Prize (1961) from the American Association for

30 the Advancement of Science for his paper "The role of behavioral study in cricket

31 classification” and the Daniel Giraud Eliot medal (1971) from the National Academy of

32 Sciences for “outstanding fundamental work on the systematics, evolution, and behavior

33 of crickets."

34

35 Richard Alexander and friend in 2015 (photo by David Lahti)

2 36 The "nine lives" in the title of this obituary does not refer to a particular fondness for cats

37 on Alexander’s part (in fact, he was partial to horses), or to some series of near death

38 experiences (although he had some of those). Rather, it refers to the many different

39 interests that Alexander pursued during his lifetime. Growing up, he worked as a farmer,

40 rancher and horse trainer, activities he continued throughout his life. He was also a

41 talented poet, songwriter, musician, and wood-carver. In addition to his professional

42 scientific writings, he was a prolific author of many kinds of books, including children’s

43 stories, biographical texts and practical guides, especially on horse training.

44

45 Evolutionary Entomology

46 Alexander began his professional career in the bosom of

47 entomology, with a firm focus on the inter-related fields of

48 acoustic communication, systematics and speciation. It

49 was his expertise in those fields that equipped him to

50 become a major contributor to our understanding of the

51 (cricket by R.D. Alexander) evolution of cooperation in general and a leading thinker on

52 the evolution of the social behavior of that “uniquely unique” species -- humans. His

53 early studies of insect behavior convinced him that behavior and communication are

54 clearly evolved phenomena, underlain by genes as certainly as morphology is, an

55 insight he came to partly because of the utility of behavior in distinguishing species.

56 This understanding led him to realize the importance of behavior in adaptive evolution,

57 leading naturally to further insights into social evolution. The communication systems of

58 crickets had consequences for diversification and speciation, and the social behavior of

3 59 insects like wasps that benefitted offspring, as well as more distant kin, via

60 and mutualism – were all comprehensible in terms of Darwinian selection and likewise

61 applicable to humans.

62

63 A meeting in 1987 of several of the thinkers who were responsible for the modern unification of

64 evolutionary and behavioral science. Left to right, in the back: , George C. Williams, Martin

65 Daly, and Mildred Dickemann. In the front, William D. Hamilton, , and Richard D.

66 Alexander. Three other people who profoundly influenced Alexander’s thinking are , William

67 Irons, and . Photo from richarddalexander.com maintained by David Lahti.

68

69 From beginnings in evolutionary entomology, Richard Alexander developed multiple,

70 ground-breaking theories concerning the evolution and development of key human

71 social traits, including monogamy, juvenile helplessness (altriciality), parental and

72 alloparental care, incest and cousin-marriage, cooperation in increasingly large social

4 73 groups and the associated problems of warfare, deceit and self-deception, language

74 and scenario-building, music and the arts, humor, religion, and even science as a

75 human endeavor.

76

77 Alexander was instrumental in founding the multi-disciplinary Human Behavior and

78 Evolution Program at the University of Michigan, alumni of which founded the Human

79 Behavior and Evolution Society. Long before "" or “evolutionary

80 ” were widely discussed, Alexander had already written many profoundly

81 influential works on evolution and social behavior. His review article entitled “The

82 Evolution of Social Behavior”, published in 1974 in the “Annual Review of Ecology and

83 Systematics,” has been cited over 4000 times. He continued to publish significant

84 contributions on the evolution of social behavior on a regular basis throughout the rest

85 of his career. A volume in his honor celebrating and summarizing many of these

86 contributions was published in 2013 (Human Social Evolution: The Foundational Works

87 of Richard D. Alexander (K. Summers and B. Crespi, eds), 2013, Oxford University

88 Press).

89

90 Alexander’s (1974) review of the evolution of social behavior presented a

91 comprehensive theoretical framework for understanding eusociality and social systems

92 in insects, birds, and mammals. The 58 page synthetic review laid out hypotheses that

93 a generation of biologists and anthropologists have spent their lives testing. When

94 asked why it was so frequently cited, Alexander offered an uncharacteristically self-

5 95 deprecating answer: ‘because I got so many things wrong and every hot-shot, young

96 scientist wants to make his reputation by showing me up’.

97

98 One criticism of the review led Alexander to one of his best known discoveries,

99 eusociality – societies with sterile workers -- in the naked mole-rat: why had eusociality

100 evolved many times among the hymenoptera and only once in all other insects?

101 William Hamilton had recently suggested that kin selection might help answer the

102 question since hymenoptera (ants, bees, wasps) are haplodiploid which means sisters

103 are more closely related to each other than they are to brothers or their own offspring,

104 something that favors sisters becoming workers and rearing more sisters instead of

105 their own young. It turned out that the factors driving the evolution of sterile workers are

106 more complicated than simple genetic relatedness, but the insight of this finding is still

107 important. In his 1974 review, Alexander argued that parental care (not asymmetric

108 relatedness) was the essential ancestral character in the evolution of insect eusociality.

109 Unlike Hamilton’s haplodiploid hypothesis, Alexander’s included the Isoptera (termites),

110 a diploid group that evolved from ancestral wood roaches with parental care. One

111 criticism of Alexander’s parental care hypothesis was that there are many other taxa

112 with parental care, particularly within vertebrates, where eusociality has failed to

113 emerge.

114

115 Alexander took this criticism seriously and explored it by posing the related question: if

116 there were a eusocial vertebrate, what would it be like? He speculated that such a

117 vertebrate would have certain characteristics and suggested a hypothetical

6 118 subterranean rodent, living in the African savannah (associated with patchily distributed

119 plants with large storage root storage organs), which fed on these tubers and suffered

120 predation by snakes. Each trait followed from a deep understanding of life history

121 constraints and tradeoffs. Underground burrows would allow expansion for large

122 colonies; roots would allow low risk foraging; snakes would require self-sacrifice to

123 defend a colony. After listening to Alexander present this hypothetical eusocial

124 vertebrate at a seminar at Northern Arizona University, mammologist Terry Vaughn

125 pointed out that it sounded very much like the naked mole-rat and, soon after,

126 Alexander went to Kenya to collect a live colony for observation. This led to an

127 explosion of scientific research on this odd-looking

128 mammal, culminating in the 1990 volume, “The Biology

129 of the Naked Mole Rat” (Sherman, Jarvis and Alexander

130 1990). Like the 1845 discovery of the planet Neptune by

131 Adams and Leverrier, Alexander explored evolutionary

132 space by extrapolation, with a deep understanding of the

133 forces that shape social behavior, and was able to

134 predict eusociality in a taxon where it had not yet been

135 directly observed.

136

137

138 Exactly one hundred years after Darwin published his great work on The Descent of

139 Man (1871), Alexander published his first paper on the same topic, entitled "The Search

140 for an Evolutionary Philosophy of Man" (Alexander 1971), sketching a quest that would

7 141 occupy most of his attention for the remainder of his career. Because of that paper, and

142 Robert Trivers' monumental first publication "The Evolution of "

143 (Trivers 1971), the year 1971 can reasonably be hailed as inaugurating the modern

144 evolutionary study of human behavior. Alexander developed a new, synthetic approach

145 to understanding human psychology, rooted firmly in the fresh understanding of

146 adaptation that had emerged in the mid-1960s thanks especially to inclusive fitness

147 theory as developed by William D. Hamilton and subsequently applied and enriched by

148 George C. Williams, Robert Trivers and John Maynard Smith. With such a foundation,

149 along with a thorough study of ethnographic works, the behavioral sciences, and the

150 lifestyles of animals, Alexander drew together disparate lines of logic and evidence and

151 introduced new ones to construct what would eventually become a comprehensive

152 explanation of human behavior and life history that was based on an unwavering

153 emphasis on the power of . His approach fully respected genes,

154 development, and environment as interacting partners. The theory eventually

155 incorporated plasticity and learning while regarding behaviors as evolving traits like any

156 others. Most impressively, it managed to integrate a vast array of human social traits --

157 with special reference to those that were unique or rare among animals-- into a

158 compelling explanatory structure that was internally consistent, mutually reinforcing, and

159 empirically sound. He continued to develop these ideas throughout the rest of his life.

160 One theme of Alexander’s work dealt with the suppression of conflicts within groups.

161 This work was strongly influenced by Egbert Leigh’s (1971, 1977) publications on the

162 evolution of Mendelian segregation and “fair meiosis”, and the concept of the

163 “parliament of genes” evolved to suppress rogue driving elements in the genome.

8 164 Alexander and Borgia (1978) made novel contributions to this topic, and he was able to

165 see the relevance of this theory to the evolution of “reproductive leveling mechanisms”

166 in a general sense, and particularly to human groups and polities. Alexander was also

167 influenced by reading the moral philosophers, particularly Rawls’ (1971) famous theory

168 of justice, in which impartial justice is developed from the assumption of a “veil of

169 ignorance” by those who write the laws. Alexander was able to unite these disparate

170 intellectual threads to develop a general theory of cooperation through suppression of

171 intragroup conflict (Alexander, 1987). This theory has been formalized and further

172 developed, then applied to many areas of evolutionary biology, such as sperm

173 competition (Frank 2013). Alexander’s theory of cooperation through suppression of

174 within-group conflict is a major part of our understanding of cooperation, and especially

175 human cooperation (Frank 2013).

176

177 Another key contribution of Alexander’s work, related to his ideas concerning the

178 suppression-of-conflict in groups, was the recognition of the importance of intergroup

179 aggression and competition in human evolution, a topic originally broached by Darwin

180 (1871). Alexander proposed that hominids became so ecologically dominant that

181 competition with other groups of humans became a crucial factor influencing survival

182 and reproductive success. Starting in the late 1960’s, Alexander (e.g. Alexander and

183 Tinkle 1968) argued that intergroup aggression was likely to have favored the evolution

184 of complex human cooperation and extreme intelligence, traits that are far more

185 advanced in humans than in other primates. This became known as the “Balance of

186 Power” hypothesis: “The general hypothesis that I support to account for the

9 187 maintenance and elaboration of group-living and complex sociality in humans… derives

188 from a theme attributable to Darwin (1871) and Keith (1949), and developed by a

189 succession of more recent authors… It includes group-against-group, within species

190 competition as a central driving force, leading to balance-of-power races with a positive

191 feedback upon cooperative abilities and social complexity. It implies that the only

192 plausible way to account for the striking departure of humans from their predecessors

193 and all other species with respect to mental and social attributes is to assume that

194 humans uniquely became their own principle hostile force of nature” (Alexander 1989).

195 The importance of intergroup competition in the evolution cooperation and intelligence

196 has become a major theme in the scientific literature, thanks in large part to Alexander’s

197 contributions.

198

199 Alexander’s ideas about intelligence were also strongly influenced by Humphrey’s

200 theory on the paramount importance of social interactions in the evolution of intelligence

201 (Humphrey 1976). But Alexander recognized that the evolution of extreme intelligence

202 in the human lineage depended on the multilevel nature of human interactions within

203 hierarchical groups (and groups within groups), particularly in the context of intense

204 intergroup competition. This led to open-ended coevolutionary arms races of

205 strategizing and counter-strategizing (requiring continuously expanding cognitive

206 capacities), both to succeed in intergroup competition with other groups of strategizing

207 humans, and to successfully negotiate advancement in the increasingly complex

208 multilevel hierarchies comprising human groups (from small multifamily groups, to

209 nomadic bands, to semi-permanent groups, to villages, to village coalitions, to tribes,

10 210 and on up to nation states). By combining his ideas about the effects of intergroup

211 aggression with those on the key importance of intra-group social interactions on the

212 evolution of intelligence, he was able to provide a cohesive and comprehensive

213 explanatory framework that led to many new insights into the evolution of human

214 cognitive capacities (Alexander 1989, 1990). Alexander realized that these evolving

215 cognitive capacities provide the key to understanding our most cherished abilities and

216 traditions, including the evolution of language and “scenario-building” (the intellectual

217 ability to imagine situations, analyzing them “in the mind’s eye”) and the development of

218 culture, religion, art and science.

219

220 In parallel with these ideas, Alexander developed increasingly sophisticated ideas about

221 the evolution of human family structure and other uniquely human traits. He began from

222 a comparative perspective, evaluating evidence regarding the ancestral state of hominid

223 family structure and then trying to infer what factors could have driven the broad swath

224 of uniquely human traits, including not only such commonly discussed phenomena as

225 consciousness, foresight, tool-use, language and symbolic thought, but also less often

226 discussed traits such as monogamy, paternal care, extended childhood, relative

227 hairlessness, and concealed ovulation, among many others.

228

229 Alexander and Noonan (1979) realized that distinctive traits like concealed ovulation

230 were likely to have played a key role in the evolution of the family centered patterns of

231 cooperation in human societies, in which every human retains an interest in having the

232 opportunity to reproduce. They had the critical perception that concealed ovulation and

11 233 related traits were adaptations that enhanced the stability and permanence of human

234 pair bonds, allowing for the increased investment required to produce successful

235 offspring in an increasingly competitive social environment. They argued that females

236 could develop and maintain consortships with specific males in multimale/multifemale

237 groups, in part through the evolution of concealed ovulation (favoring long-term

238 association by the male to ensure paternity). These relationships then provided high

239 confidence of paternity – and a direct payoff to males investing in (their own) offspring.

240 They benefitted females through investment by their male partner, including protection

241 from aggression or infanticide by other males. Alexander thought that the extreme

242 altriciality of human infants and children must have evolved in conjunction with the

243 prodigious learning capacities required to be a successful adult in an increasingly

244 complex social world. He argued that this complexity was likely to be positively

245 reinforcing in a social runaway process (Alexander 1990a)

246

247 Alexander and Noonan (1979) originally proposed that dominant males would be the

248 first to form pair bonds, but later work indicated that this hypothesis was more likely to

249 apply to subordinate males, given that dominant males have higher incentives to pursue

250 polygynous mating strategies rather than investing in parental care (reviewed in

251 Strassmann 2013). Yet, why would dominant males not break up exclusive associations

252 between subordinate males and females? As the importance of inter-group competition

253 increased in the human lineage, the value of subordinates to dominants within groups

254 also increased, placing constraints on the levels of despotism and reproductive skew

255 that dominants could afford to impose (Alexander 1979). Alexander (1979) coined the

12 256 term “Socially Imposed Monogamy” (SIM) to capture this dynamic, which he contrasted

257 to “ecologically imposed monogamy”, where harsh environmental conditions make it

258 impossible for males to monopolize more than a single female.

259

260 Of course, human history reveals episodes and societies characterized by extreme

261 inequality in reproductive opportunity (Alexander, 1979). Nevertheless, Alexander

262 thought that, for the majority of humans that have lived across the course of human

263 history, most have had some expectation of opportunities to mate and produce their

264 own offspring. He further suggested (e.g. Alexander 1987) that trends toward neolocal

265 nuclear human families and associated large-scale patterns of reproductive opportunity-

266 leveling in modern times have been propelled by the continued (and enhanced)

267 importance of inter-group competition and aggression (on a broad scale), and

268 consequent pressure for rulers and elites to concede reproductive opportunities to those

269 lower in the hierarchy. Subsequent comparative work has supported that claim, and has

270 brought to light additional factors that are likely to be involved.

271

272 Another important contribution was Alexander’s development of the theory of indirect

273 reciprocity. In 1971, Robert Trivers published his classic paper (Trivers 1971) on

274 “reciprocal altruism”, which elaborated how reciprocal exchange of benefits could

275 increase the fitness of both parties in an interaction, given certain assumptions, such as

276 the reciprocally asymmetric value of exchanged goods and services (often created by

277 specialization in complex societies), and repeated interactions between the same

278 individuals, with indefinite end points. This theory profoundly influenced Alexander’s

13 279 thinking (and that of many others), but he realized that it was insufficient to explain the

280 kind of large scale levels of cooperation seen in human groups and societies involving

281 multitudes of participants and interactions. Expanding on Trivers’ concept of

282 “generalized reciprocity”, Alexander developed the theory of indirect reciprocity, which

283 posited that in contrast to direct reciprocity “in indirect reciprocity, the return is expected

284 from someone other than the recipient of the beneficence. The return can come from

285 essentially any individual or collection of individuals in the group” (Alexander 1987).

286 Alexander began writing about indirect reciprocity in the 1970’s, but his ideas were

287 largely overlooked as theoreticians focused on the mechanisms and implications of

288 direct reciprocity. However, in the 1990’s, theoreticians began exploring the

289 mechanisms and implications of Alexander’s concept of indirect reciprocity in earnest,

290 and this led to confirmation of the potential importance of this mechanism in the

291 evolution of wide-scale cooperation in large societies (reviewed by Sigmund 2013). The

292 key role of indirect reciprocity is now a central theme of both theoretical and empirical

293 work on the evolution of cooperation in large human societies.

294

295 Culture

296 Multifarious lines of reasoning were combined by Alexander into a comprehensive, yet

297 subtle and nuanced view of evolution and human behavior. One of the challenges in

298 reading Alexander's work is precisely the heavily integrated nature of its framework; one

299 can read some piece of his on human ecological dominance, or our mating strategies

300 and marriage, or concealment of ovulation, or lifelong parenting, extensive and

301 differential nepotism, direct and indirect reciprocity, in-group/out-group dynamics,

14 302 extended juvenile period, our mind as a social tool, scenario-building, consciousness,

303 self-deception, learning, culture, morality, law, political structures, humor, the arts, or

304 religion... but understanding the function and relevance of any one of these in

305 Alexander's thought requires an understanding of many others. The flip side of this, of

306 course, is that as more of these elements are understood, the more that a big picture

307 begins to emerge, and the more easily additional pieces fit into place.

308

309 Alexander was careful to consider and include the complex social and cognitive abilities

310 of humans in the development of this theories. He recognized the importance of

311 developmental, behavioral, and cultural plasticity in human behavior and especially, the

312 role of the environment during human development. One of Alexander’s key

313 contributions was his early appreciation of how people could behave adaptively without

314 having specific genes “for” particular behaviors. This understanding involved his

315 realization that genetic variants under strong natural selection would tend to go to

316 fixation, and yet could work through plastic developmental and psychological

317 mechanisms to endow their owners with the adaptive flexibility to do the right thing for

318 reproduction in the various environmental circumstances encountered. As Alexander

319 (1990b) wrote: “Adaptation is not restricted to situations in which genes program

320 specifically for particular behavioral alternatives: natural selection of alternative alleles

321 may also yield abilities and tendencies to engage in conditional strategies, to assess

322 costs and benefits in directly or indirectly reproductive terms. In humans, such cost-

323 benefit assessments may be conducted entirely through mental scenario-building, or

15 324 even through absorbing and judging the mental scenarios of others, without either

325 admission or cognizance of the reproductive significance of the assessment.”

326

327 Alexander’s views of human behavior gave him a unique perspective on the evolution of

328 the human psyche. Well before disagreements unfolded between evolutionary

329 psychologists, evolutionary anthropologists and gene-culture coevolutionists, Alexander

330 had developed deep insights into the extreme flexibility of the human mind and the

331 implications for . Alexander saw human cognitive capacities, including

332 intelligence, consciousness, foresight, empathy, theory of mind, moral reasoning,

333 language, abilities such as scenario-building and story-telling, and cultural legacies such

334 as art and religion, as stemming from continual arms races of social competition

335 (Alexander 2006; Flinn & Alexander 2007). He emphasized the interplay of cooperation

336 and competition between individuals and groups. The cross-generational, cumulative

337 effects of human reproductive striving, as collected and codified in cultural traditions and

338 trends, have perennially created new environments in which human strategizing and

339 social competition has unfolded.

340

341 Alexander appreciated the likely importance of “Darwinian algorithms” (psychological

342 mechanisms designed to accomplish adaptive ends), in biasing human perception and

343 behavior in (historically) adaptive directions, as appreciated by evolutionary

344 psychologists. But his keen awareness of the value of novelty and creativity in the

345 context of social arms races led him to be cautious about proposing limits to the power

346 of the human mind to adapt to novel circumstances. His deep understanding of the

16 347 pervasive influence of natural selection on human conscious and unconscious thought

348 and emotion (and attendant strategies of deceit and self-deception) led him to be

349 skeptical concerning cultural evolution as a process independent of organic evolution,

350 untethered from the adaptive strategies of human beings (Alexander 1979). Instead,

351 Alexander viewed cultural evolution as intimately and inextricably linked to individual

352 reproductive striving.

353

354

355 Morality

356 The faculty and institution of morality was a chief and overriding interest during all of

357 these pursuits in Alexander's quest to understand humanity. Morality was the human

358 trait he contemplated most extensively, and after Darwinism and Human Affairs (1979)

359 was the sole human affair he chose to investigate further in a book of its own, The

360 Biology of Moral Systems (1987). In considering humans as a product of natural

361 selection, Alexander found in moral exhortations to selfless beneficence a fascinating

362 professional challenge along the same lines as that posed to Darwin by the presence of

363 sterile castes in social insects. Alexander started from a hypothesis that would be

364 uncontroversial to evolutionary biologists with respect to the traits of any other

365 organism, but got him maligned and misunderstood by many when he suggested it of

366 morality: that it is "reproductively selfish". Even human moral attitudes and behaviors

367 that seem so other-regarding, so selfless, tended to return benefits to the actor. The

368 theory would also have to address some very peculiar features of humans-- things

369 Alexander called the moral paradoxes, the convolutedness of morality. For instance,

17 370 why do we not practice what we preach? We claim the equal value of all people

371 regardless of their relation to us, we promulgate the Golden Rule, we teach our kids to

372 be good regardless of the possibility of being caught... and yet nobody truly acts as

373 though we believe these things. We still privilege our own groups, we place ourselves

374 and our people far above others in our practical estimations, and we are inordinately

375 concerned for reputation and how our actions appear to observers. Thus a workable

376 evolutionary theory of morality has to explain not only the ideals we tend to espouse but

377 also our typical failure to abide by them.

378 A brief synopsis of Alexander’s theory of morality (drawing on the insights discussed

379 above) is as follows: early humans achieved ecological dominance, to such an extent

380 that the most significant selective agents impinging on their survival and reproduction

381 were other humans. As humans lived in social groups, competition would manifest itself

382 not only within a group but between groups. This would further intensify our

383 dependence on groups, and create a ratcheting effect where traits contributory to group

384 cohesion would be increasingly favored. In this situation, individuals could benefit

385 themselves and their kin reproductively in two different ways: directly by competing with

386 others within their groups, and indirectly by helping others in their groups, which in turn

387 would strengthen the group in competition with other groups. Thus we evolved to

388 cooperate in order to compete, both within and between social groups. The result was

389 the primacy of individual social reputation, and a heavily scenario-building, socially

390 intuitive, and strategizing human personality. Each individual would balance the direct

391 and indirect means of garnering benefits. Each individual would also benefit more by the

392 cooperation of others than by cooperating oneself, resulting in a few powerful items

18 393 entering into the human strategic toolbox: tendencies to over-encourage beneficence in

394 others, to overestimate one's own level of commitment, to look for violations in others

395 and conceal them in oneself, and in general to dispense kindness strategically

396 depending on the expected returns to oneself and one's kin. Moreover, these objectives

397 could often be undertaken with greater efficiency if the motivating factors were

398 concealed from the consciousness not only of others but of the agents themselves. All

399 of these strategies and others presuppose conflicts of interest among genetically

400 different individuals. Moral systems are essentially the means by which these conflicts

401 are identified and resolved.

402 Reception to these ideas was (and has continued to be) uneven, for several reasons,

403 some of which remain relevant even for those who understand evolution and selection.

404 First, the ideas are intellectually demanding, and require substantial investment in order

405 for one to understand them and avoid hyperbole, simplification, or an imbalance of

406 components. Often commentators have taken the easier route of lumping Alexander’s

407 work with facile treatments of these problems, that pay mere lip service to kin selection,

408 reciprocal altruism, and other subjects whose complicated nature is discussed and

409 documented by Alexander. As Alexander was developing and publishing his ideas,

410 essentially no rival well-developed evolutionary theory of morality existed that was

411 placed fully into the context of human life history, and that took seriously the real moral

412 experience of people, warts and all. Many people, including those who depict humans

413 as as fundamentally good, prefer to overlook those warts rather than attempt to explain

414 them. Many are discomforted by the picture of a strategizing human who has not

415 thoroughly abandoned the organismal tendency towards selfishness. Many are

19 416 additionally disgusted at the idea of self-deception. To this, Alexander might first offer

417 the olive branch that selfishness and self-deception are used in an evolutionary sense,

418 and on that meaning neither deception nor selfishness are expected always to be

419 conscious. Strangely enough, "self-deception" actually rescues the possibility of

420 authentic moral action by separating evolved objectives from consciousness. But

421 Alexander would never let that molasses go down without the medicine, for the

422 objection to evolutionary selfishness is usually symptomatic of a general human trait

423 that frustrates efforts like Alexander’s to understand ourselves: our natural resistance to

424 honest self-study. We tend to avoid being confronted with our typical attitudes and

425 actions and their reproductive functions. Alexander insisted that we must investigate

426 and accept whatever we find to underlie our thoughts and deeds, both the noble and the

427 disgusting, as this knowledge is our only hope if we want to improve ourselves and the

428 world.

429 Both the depth and iconoclasm in Alexander's ideas on morality can be illustrated in one

430 of his favorite stories. Theodore H. Hubbell, a friend and colleague at the UMMZ, was

431 troubled by the contention that human behavior is by and large self-interested. Once he

432 thought he had a good counter-example, and approached Alexander: “Dick, this

433 morning on my way to work I saw a caterpillar moving across the sidewalk. I knew it had

434 fallen off its host plant, so I picked it up and replaced it on the proper plant species. Was

435 that not an act of pure altruism?” To this Alexander replied, “It may have been, until you

436 told me about it.”

437 Despite Alexander's evolutionary analysis of morality, and despite his consistent refusal

438 to resort to what he called "the transcendent", Alexander never exhibited any signs of

20 439 retreating into the moral cynicism or nihilism that is often associated with "evolutionary

440 ethics" (a term he avoided). In fact, he struggled with increasing fervor to solve what he

441 called the world's most terrible puzzle: our "unholy capacity and willingness to turn

442 close-knit groups into fighting machines" (Alexander 2014, p. 58), a tendency he well

443 knew was a product of the mechanism that had fashioned our moral psychology in the

444 first place. Whereas in the 1980s and 1990s he would end his papers on morality with

445 the general idea that understanding ourselves and our biases is half the battle, by the

446 2010s his primary goal was to nail specific solutions to the "reciprocating echoes of

447 intra-group amity and inter-group enmity" (Alexander 2014, p. 56). When he sat down to

448 write his final professional papers in his 80s, he focused not on evolutionary explanation

449 as an end in itself, but rather insofar as it might contribute to "global harmony" (2013)

450 and "the future of human society" (2014). He considered the central condition for the

451 survival of humanity to be the dissolution of the evolved concept of "the other" as it

452 manifests as a motivator of hatred towards the outgroup. Hence, Alexander (2013, p.

453 417) wrote: “The greatest difficulty in seeking global harmony may derive from human

454 groups targeting one another. Humans alone – among all the world’s species – plot,

455 plan, and organize massive conflicts to defeat or displace similarly organized and

456 cooperative members of their own species. Can we learn to use the current

457 consciousness of our human background to adjust team efforts of all kinds so that

458 honesty, fairness, and negotiation can increase and lead us toward global harmony?”

459 For Alexander the keys to this project would be the universalization of morality, the

460 reduction of aggression and hyper-competitiveness, temperance with respect to views

461 of morality and God, the conversion of despotic governments that treat their citizens as

21 462 property, and the radical extrapolation of kinship and expansion of social reciprocity. He

463 issued various concrete proposals in this vein, for instance that team sports could soften

464 and redirect outgroup animosity. He also wondered whether God might be translated

465 into a naturalistic concept based on a universal social group or extended kinship in the

466 context of our system of morality. Nevertheless, he repeatedly expressed towards the

467 end of his life (e.g. Alexander 2011) that the biggest regret of his professional career

468 was that he had not made satisfactory progress towards fostering our peaceful

469 coexistence. Thus, Alexander left us with a consistent plea, a take-home message from

470 over half a century of thought: accept and fully interpret our evolutionary heritage; for

471 our own sake, strive sympathetically and constructively to understand humanity.

472

473 Conclusion

474 Richard Alexander did not develop his major ideas in a linear fashion. Rather, they were

475 all developed interactively in the ferment of his mind over the course of his life. Over

476 those many years, he generated an expansive vision of human behavioral evolution,

477 composed of a large set of interacting hypotheses, consistent within themselves and

478 among each other, and able to explain many aspects of the human condition. His

479 excitement in discovery and his tireless critical thinking, sustained over a period of so

480 many years, was shared openly with his students and we all benefitted from it. One

481 wrote, speaking for all, that we were lucky to have a seat at the table.

482 Alexander was a great teacher; his students have dispersed across academia and

483 beyond. Over his long and distinguished career he mentored many graduate and

484 undergraduate students, including Kenneth C. Shaw of Iowa State University, Mary

22 485 Jane West Eberhard of the Smithsonian Tropical Research Institute, Daniel Otte of the

486 Academy of Natural Sciences in Philadelphia, Mitchell Weiss of Rutgers University,

487 John Waage of Brown University, Ann Pace of the Bell Museum of Natural History at

488 the University of Minnesota, Harry Power of Rutgers University, Paul W. Sherman of

489 Cornell University, John L. Hoogland of the Appalachian Environmental Laboratory at

490 the University of Maryland, Richard D. Howard of Purdue University, Marianne N.

491 Feaver of North Carolina State University, Gerald Borgia of the University of Maryland,

492 Katherine M. Noonan of Albany, California, David Foltz of Louisiana State University,

493 Cynthia Kagarise Sherman of Ithaca, New York, Joan Strassmann of Washington

494 University, Nancy Moran of the University of Texas, Marlene Zuk of the University of

495 Minnesota, David Queller of Washington University, Alex Mintzer of Texas A&M

496 University, Bernard J. Crespi of Simon Fraser University, Richard Connor of the

497 University of Massachusetts at Dartmouth, Beverly Strassmann of the University of

498 Michigan, Steven Frank of the University of California at Irvine, Stanton Braude of

499 Washington University, Eileen Lacey of the University of California at Berkeley, Kyle

500 Summers of East Carolina University, Andrew F. Richards of the City College of New

501 York, John Pepper of the National Institutes of Health, Deborah Chizek of Boulder

502 Colorado, David Marshall and John Cooley of the University of Connecticut, Anna Bess

503 Sorin of the University of Memphis, Bret Weinstein and Heather Heying of the Aspen

504 Center for Human Development, Daniel Kruger of the University of Michigan, and David

505 Lahti of the City University of New York. Alexander also mentored many postdoctoral

506 scholars, including James Lloyd of the University of Florida, Jasper J. Loftus-Hills of the

507 University of Michigan, Daniel Otte of the Philadelphia Academy of Natural Sciences,

23 508 Paul Turke of Turke and Tomashow Pediatrics, Laura Betzig of the University of

509 Michigan, Mark V. Flinn of Baylor University, Andrew F. Richards of the City University

510 of New York, Rachel Smolker of the University of Vermont, and David C. Marshall of the

511 University of Connecticut.

512

513 We end this obituary with an excerpt from a poem (“Heroes are works of art”) by

514 Alexander (2011, p. 52). He did not write this with reference to himself, but we think it is

515 appropriate.

516

517 Heroes are for all times, all ages

518 they help us to know what we

519 hadn’t even known we wanted to know,

520 to facilitate all that we discover

521 can be discovered, all that

522 can be absorbed into ourselves.

523

524 Submitted by Kyle Summers1, David Lahti2, Stanton Braude3, Beverly Strassmann4,

525 Joan Strassmann3.

24 526 1) Department of Biology, East Carolina University, Greenville, NC 27858

527 2) Department of Biology, Queen’s College, City University of New York, Flushing,

528 NY, 11367

529 3) Department of Biology, Washington University in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO, 63130

530 4) Department of Anthropology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI, 48104

531

532 The authors gratefully acknowledge valuable advice, discussion and commentary from

533 Nancy Alexander, Laura Betzig, Gerald Borgia, Napoleon Chagnon, Richard Connor,

534 John Cooley, , Mary Jane West Eberhard, , Steven Frank, John

535 Hoogland, William Irons, Daniel Kruger, Eileen Lacey, Bobbi Low, David Marshall,

536 David Queller, Andrew Richards, Anna Bess Sorin and Paul Turke.

537

538 Literature Cited

539

540 Alexander, R.D. and Tinkle, D.W. 1968. A comparative review (of On Aggression and

541 The Territorial Imperative). Bio. Science 18(3): 245-248.

542

543 Alexander, R.D. 1971. The search for an evolutionary philosophy of man. Proc. Royal

544 Soc. Victoria, Melbourne 84: 99-120.

545

546 Alexander, R.D. 1974. The evolution of social behavior. Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 5: 352-

547 383.

548

25 549 Alexander, R.D. and Borgia, G. 1978. , altruism, and the levels of

550 organization of life. Ann. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 9: 449-474.

551

552 Alexander, R.D. and Noonan, K.M. 1979. Concealment of ovulation, parental care and

553 human social evolution. In Evolutionary Biology and Human Social Behavior: An

554 Anthropological Perspective, N. A. Chagnon and W. G. Irons (eds), North Scituate,

555 Mass.: Duxbury Press, pp. 436-453.

556

557 Alexander, R.D. 1979. Darwinism and Human Affairs, University of Washington Press,

558 Seattle, WA.

559

560 Alexander, R.D. 1987. The Biology of Moral Systems, Aldine de Gruyter, Hawthorne,

561 NY.

562

563 Alexander, R.D. 1989. The evolution of the human psyche. In The Human Revolution,

564 C. Stringer and P. Mellars (eds), Univ. of Edinburgh Press, pp. 455-513.

565

566 Alexander, R.D. 1990a. How Did Humans Evolve? Reflections on the Uniquely Unique

567 Species. Univ. Mich. Zool. Special Publication 1: 1-38.

568 Alexander, R.D. 1990b. Epigenetic rules and Darwinian algorithms: the adaptive study

569 of learning and development. Ethology and Sociobiology 11:241-303.

570

26 571 Alexander, R.D. 2003. Evolutionary selection and the nature of humanity. In Darwinism

572 and Philosophy, V. Hosle and Ch. Illies (eds), University of Notre Dame Press.

573

574 Alexander, R.D. 2006. The Challenge of Human Social Behavior. Evolutionary

575 Psychology (on-line): 4(2):1-28.

576

577 Alexander, R.D. 2011. The Mockingbird's River Song: Poems, Essays, Songs, and

578 Stories: 1946-2011. Manchester, MI: Woodlane Farm Books.

579

580 Alexander, R.D. 2013. Religion, evolution and the quest for global harmony – Original

581 essay for this volume. In K. Summers and B. Crespi (eds), Human Social Evolution: the

582 Foundational Works of Richard D. Alexander. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.

583

584 Alexander, R.D. 2014. Darwin’s challenges and the future of human society. In

585 Predicting the Future in Science, Economics, and Politics, F. Wayman, P. Williamson,

586 and B. Bueno de Mesquita (eds), Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, pp. 55-108.

587

588 Darwin, C. 1871. The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex. Appleton, New

589 York, NY.

590

591 Flinn, M. and Alexander, R.D. 2007. Runaway in Humans. In: S.W.

592 Gangestad (ed), The Evolution of Mind. Fundamental Questions and Controversies. Pp.

593 249-255.

27 594

595 Frank, S. 2013. A new theory of cooperation. In K. Summers and B. Crespi (eds),

596 Human Social Evolution: the Foundational Works of Richard D. Alexander. Oxford

597 University Press, Oxford, UK.

598

599 Humprhey, N.K. 1976. The social function of intellect. In Growing Points in Ethology,

600 P.P.G. Bateson and R.A. Hinde (eds), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, pp.

601 303-317.

602

603 Keith, A. 1949. A New Theory of Human Evolution. Philosophy Library, New York, NY.

604

605 Leigh, E.G. 1971. Adaptation and Diversity. Freeman, Cooper: San Francisco, CA.

606

607 Leigh, E.G. 1977. How does selection reconcile individual advantage with the good of

608 the group. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 74:4542-4546.

609

610 Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Press: Cambridge, MA.

611

612 Sherman, P., Jarvis, J., Alexander, R.D. 1991. The Biology of the Naked Mole Rat.

613 Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

614

28 615 Sigmund, K. 2013. Introduction: the basis of morality, Richard Alexander on indirect

616 reciprocity. In K. Summers and B. Crespi (eds), Human Social Evolution: the

617 Foundational Works of Richard D. Alexander. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.

618

619 Strassmann, B. 2013. Introduction: concealed ovulation in humans: further evidence. In

620 K. Summers and B. Crespi (eds), Human Social Evolution: the Foundational Works of

621 Richard D. Alexander. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.

622

623 Summers, K. and Crespi, B. 2013. Human Social Evolution: the Foundational Works of

624 Richard D. Alexander. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.

625

626 Trivers, R. 1971. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quart. Rev. Biol. 46:35-57.

29