Subjective Views of Kuhn

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Subjective Views of Kuhn Subjective Views of Kuhn Peter Achinstein Johns Hopkins University In response to a charge of subjectivism, Kuhn in his Postscript emphasizes the importance of “values” (accuracy, simplicity, explanatory power, etc) that are shared by scientists generally. However, Kuhn adds, these values are applied differently by different scientists. By employing a comparison with partially subjective views of Carnap on conªrming evidence, this paper raises questions about Kuhn’s position on values by considering ways it might be interpreted as subjective and ways it may not. Many philosophers of science have wrestled with the question of whether there is a universal scientiªc method, i.e., a set of rules for discovering or testing scientiªc hypotheses. The rules are universal because they hold for all sciences and all times. Examples might include rules of the sort that Descartes proposed (his 21 rules) in Rules for the Direction of the Mind, or the 4 rules of reasoning that begin the third book of Newton’s Principia. Two major ªgures in 20th century philosophy of science, Karl Popper and Paul Feyerabend, whose deaths occurred within a year or two of Kuhn’s, offered strikingly different answers to the question of whether universal rules exist. Popper’s answer I take to be a resounding, “Yes,” at least to the question of whether there are such rules in the case of scientiªc testing or justiªcation. (Rules of discovery, he believed, are another mat- ter.) Popper’s method of corroboration—his version of hypothetico- deductivism—is, I believe, intended to be a universal scientiªc method for testing hypotheses. Feyerabend, although a student of Popper, offered a very different an- swer: There are no universal rules of discovery or testing. Doing science, Feyerabend said in one of his typically provocative moments, is like mak- ing love or waging war. There are some useful hints, some rules of thumb, Perspectives on Science 2001, vol. 9, no. 4 ©2002 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 423 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375811 by guest on 30 September 2021 424 Subjective Views of Kuhn but in general, to quote his most notorious principle, “anything goes.” Anarchism, while it may not be a workable political strategy, yields the best science, and is the best philosophy of science, he used to say. With Popper on the extreme right and Feyerabend on the extreme left, where does Kuhn ªt on this spectrum? One might be tempted to say that Kuhn acknowledges the existence of methodological rules, but they are not universal. They are paradigm-speciªc. The paradigm supplies rather speciªc rules for what sort of hypotheses are worth testing, e.g., ones that do not violate conservation of energy, or that do not postulate action at a distance or velocities greater than that of light. And the paradigm sup- plies speciªc rules for how to test such hypotheses. On the other hand, in his Postscript written for the second edition of The Structure of Scientiªc Revolutions, Kuhn emphasizes the importance of what he calls scientiªc values as an essential part of the “disciplinary matrix,” a term that replaces “paradigm” (Kuhn 1970a, p. 182ff.). Kuhn mentions values such as accuracy, consistency, scope, simplicity, fruitfulness, explan- atory power, and plausibility. These are values employed in determining what theory or hypothesis to accept, or to promote, or at least to take seri- ously and explore. There are passages in Kuhn suggesting that these val- ues are shared by very different scientiªc communities, that they are shared over time, and indeed that this is the reason why all scientists can, in an important sense, be thought of as forming a single community (Kuhn 1970a, “Postscript,” p. 184). So is Kuhn here allied with Popper? Is he a universalist? I don’t think so. Nor is he an anarchist either. Instead, he is delightfully paradoxical. He speaks of values shared within a scientiªc community and shared even by different communities. But he also says that these shared values are frequently applied differently even by scientists within the same community. Although the criterion of “accuracy” is pretty stable from one application to another, “judgments of simplicity, consistency, plausibility, and so on often vary greatly from individual to individual” (Kuhn 1970a, “Postscript,” p. 185). “In short,” Kuhn writes, “though values are widely shared by scientists and though commitment to them is both deep and constitutive of science, the application of values is sometimes considerably affected by the features of individual personality and biography that dif- ferentiate the members of the group” (Kuhn 1970a, p. 185). So while you and I may both agree that the simplest hypothesis is to be preferred, pro- moted, tested ªrst, or whatever, we may disagree substantially over what counts as simple. And this disagreement, I take it, may be unresolvable by argumentation, but only explainable by reference to causal features of temperament, training, and so forth. Moreover, to complicate matters fur- ther, in determining which of two theories to prefer, promote, or pursue, Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375811 by guest on 30 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 425 it may turn out that each has some virtues the other lacks, and that scien- tists, even from the same community, weight these virtues differently. Kuhn emphasizes that the criteria for selecting theories “function not as rules, which determine choice, but as values which inºuence them” (Kuhn 1977, p. 331). The idea seems to be that rules, at least if clearly for- mulated, are, or are supposed to be, applied by different people in the same way under the same circumstances. It wouldn’t do if the rule that you must stop your car at a red light could be interpreted by different peo- ple in a very different manner. But for Kuhn, values can be variably ap- plied, and that is ªne and dandy. Moreover, Kuhn thinks this is sufªcient to avoid the charge of subjectivity levelled against him by a number of critics. Responding to Schefºer, e.g., Kuhn writes, “it is emphatically not my view that ‘adoption of a new scientiªc theory is an intuitive or mysti- cal affair, a matter for psychological description rather than logical or methodological codiªcation’” (Kuhn 1970b, “Reºections on My Critics,” p. 261). Kuhn insists that there are good reasons for adopting one theory over another, and these reasons are of the sort philosophers of science typi- cally describe involving accuracy, scope, simplicity, explanatory power, and so on. So where does Kuhn end up on the spectrum between Popper, the uni- versalist, and Feyerabend, the anarchist. Like Popper, he wants to promote certain values common to scientists generally, from one period to another. He wants to say that scientists generally favor theories satisfying these val- ues. Appeals to these values constitute good reasons for preferring the the- ories. And it is the acceptance of such values that is at least part of what it is to be a scientist. Like Feyerabend, however, he wants to reject the idea that scientists proceed in accordance with some ªxed and universal set of rules which determine what hypothesis it is reasonable to accept. Let me put this another way which may be more helpful. All three of the philosophers I have mentioned talk about values such as simplicity, consistency, explanatory power, and empirical conªrmation (even though Feyerabend at one point calls them “verbal ornaments”). Now there are several views about such values. On one, there are objective rational con- straints on how they are to be interpreted and applied in particular cir- cumstances. On another, opposing view, there are no objective rational constraints. What one takes to be simple, consistent, explanatory, or conªrmatory, is a personal matter, or perhaps is decided by voting or power politics. I will attribute that view to Feyerabend, at least in his more provocative moments. As for the rational constraint view, I see two versions: one is a strict constraint view. This is the idea that how a value is applied is strictly con- strained by usage, or deªnition, or practice, so that in accordance with this Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/106361401760375811 by guest on 30 September 2021 426 Subjective Views of Kuhn usage or deªnition or practice, although there might be borderline cases, what counts, or is to count, as simple, consistent, explanatory, or empiri- cally conªrmed, is quite generally determined in individual applications. I think that is Popper’s view, or something close to it. The second rational constraint view is weaker. It is that usage or deªnition or practice furnish at least some constraints on how scientiªc values are to be interpreted and applied. Not just any theory a scientist or a community calls simple or conªrmed is really so. But these constraints, however universal, do not completely determine how scientiªc values are to be interpreted and applied. Scientists associated with the same practice can still differ considerably over whether, or to what extent, some theory is simple, conªrmed, explanatory, etc. I suspect this weak constraint view is Kuhn’s view, or something close to it. If this is Kuhn’s view, there is an interesting similarity between this and the view of someone most people take to be one of Kuhn’s major op- ponents, viz. Rudolf Carnap, the arch-logical positivist. In his Continuum of Inductive Methods published in 1952, 10 years before Kuhn’s most fa- mous work, Carnap sought to explicate the idea of the degree to which a theory is conªrmed or supported by the evidence. He began by setting down all the objective, rational, universal constraints he could think of for this concept, resulting in 11 axioms.
Recommended publications
  • Constructive Empiricism in the Social Sciences
    Constructive empiricism in the social sciences Abstract ‘What problems face the aspirant empiricist today?’ is the question Bas C. van Fraassen asks in his seminal work The Scientific Image (1980). In this thesis, I interpret this question as a challenge to develop constructive empiricism [CE] in a field of scientific inquiry other than the context of physics in which it was conceived. The first part of the thesis expounds CE with reference to classical empiricism, discloses some of its fundamental assumptions, and spells out in detail its account of science. In the second part of the thesis, CE is extended to social science. Since CE was developed in the context of natural science, I take an articulation of the alleged fundamental differences between natural and social science as indicating challenges a CE-outlook on social science must address. I also provide a brief history of the gap between the sciences. Then, in the bulk of this thesis, I argue that CE’s model view accommodates social science, that description, prediction and explanation in the light of CE are proper fruits of inquiry in social science, and that CE is able to make sense of the differences in the concepts used in natural and social science. In the discussion of the feasibility of CE for social science, I show concurrently that contemporary articulations of the differences between the natural and the social sciences pose no insuperable problems for the constructive empiricist. Bram van Dijk | 3691454 History & Philosophy of Science | Utrecht University Daily supervisors | dr. Guido Bacciagaluppi & dr. Ruud Abma Third examiner | dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Faculty of Humanities School of Social Sciences
    FACULTY OF HUMANITIES SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES PHILOSOPHY COURSE UNIT OUTLINE 2017-18 PHIL20021 Philosophy of Religion Semester: 1 Credits: 20 This course guide should be read in conjunction with the Philosophy Study Guide 2016-17, available from the Philosophy Intranet. Lecturer(s): Dr Michael Scott Office: Humanities Bridgeford Street 2.56 Telephone: 0161 275 3875 Email: [email protected] Office Hours: Tuesdays 10-11, Wednesdays 11-12. Please email to arrange an appointment outside of these hours. Tutors: Tutorials will be taken by Teaching Assistants – see below. Their office hours will be posted here: http://www.socialsciences.manchester.ac.uk/student- intranet/undergraduate/course-information/philosophy/office-hours/ Administrator: Christopher Ashworth, UG Office, G.001 Arthur Lewis Building Tel: 0161 275 7129, Email: [email protected] Lectures: Tues 11-1pm. Tutorials: Allocate yourself to a tutorial group using the Student System (this is compulsory and on a first come, first served basis) Assessment: 2 hour exam 67% 2,000 word essay 33% Reading Week: Monday 30th October 2017 – Friday 3rd November 2017 Philosophy Intranet: http://www.socialsciences.manchester.ac.uk/student- intranet/undergraduate/course-information/philosophy/ Please go to the intranet for staff and TA office hours, the Philosophy Study Guide, and advice on accessing online philosophy resources. ***IMPORTANT INFORMATION – PLEASE READ*** Pre-requisite(s): None Communication: Students must read their University e-mails regularly, as important information will be communicated in this way. Examination period: Monday 15 January – Friday 26 January 2018 1 Re-sit Examination period: Monday 20th August – Friday 31st August 2018 Please read this course outline through very carefully as it provides essential information needed by all students attending this course 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Study and Teaching of Philosophy of Science
    The Study and Teaching of Philosophy of Science An Academic Interview of Professor Peter Achinstein Liang: Could you please share some more details about the reason why you chose philosophy of science as a life-time business? It is said that you were motivated by Hempel when you were studying at Harvard. Is that true? Achinstein: Well, I didn’t choose it at the beginning as a life-time career, but philosophy was always fascinating to me, since it raises fundamental questions that I find very challenging. I chose to do my Ph.D. thesis on probability theory, particularly Carnap’s probability theory, and that got me interested in philosophy of science. The philosopher who had the greatest influence on me as a student was Carl G. Hempel, who came to visit Harvard one year when I was an undergraduate. He taught a course on probability, and one on philosophy of science. These were the most interesting philosophy courses I’d taken at Harvard. When I was a graduate student, I wrote my thesis in the area of probability and induction. This led me to the question: what is evidence, and can it be defined in terms of probability? At the same time, I began attending courses in physics at Harvard and later at Johns Hopkins, which got me further interested the philosophy of science. So, I didn’t start out by planning to work in the philosophy of science. When I became a graduate student, I was not like some graduate students who are sure what they want to focus on at the very beginning of their study.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of the Writings of Hilary Putnam
    PART THREE BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF HILARY PUTNAM Compiled and Edited by John R. ShooK with the assistance of Hilary Putnam anD Joseph PalenCIK Putnam Bibliography.indd 891 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM Putnam Bibliography.indd 892 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF Hilary Putnam This bibliography lists books and then shorter writings, in chronological order of their first publication. Chapters of books are accompanied by a year of first publication; those chapters lacking a year were first published in that book. Only selected reprintings of shorter writings are mentioned, to clarify multiple versions. A translation of a shorter item is included if that was its first publication; any later publication in English is mentioned. BOOKS The Meaning of the Concept of Probability in Application to Finite Sequences. Ph.D. dis- sertation, University of California, Los Angeles, 1951. New York: Garland, 1990. The 1990 reprinting includes “Introduction Some Years Later,” 1–12. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Edited with Paul Benacerraf. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1964. Includes an “Introduction” with Paul Benacerraf, 1–27. The 2nd edition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983) adds two chapters by Putnam: “Mathematics without Foundations” (1967), 295–313; and “Models and Reality” (1980), 421–45. Philosophy of Logic. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1972. Translated into Italian (1975), Japanese (1975), Chinese (1984). Repr. in Math- ematics, Matter and Method, 2nd ed. (1985), 323–57. Repr., London: Routledge, 2010. CONTENTS Preface, vii 1. What Logic Is, 3–7 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Kelly
    Thomas Kelly Department of Philosophy https://www.princeton.edu/~tkelly/ Princeton University [email protected] 212 1879 Hall (609) 258-4294 (tel) Princeton, NJ 08544 Employment Princeton University, 2004- Professor of Philosophy, 2012- Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2007-2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 2004-2007 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, 2003-2004. Junior Fellow, Harvard Society of Fellows, 2000-2003. Education Ph.D. in Philosophy, Harvard University, 2001. B.A. in Philosophy, summa cum laude, University of Notre Dame, 1994. Areas of Specialization Epistemology, Theory of Rationality, Philosophical Methodology Areas of Competence History of Analytic Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Ethics, Philosophy of Religion Publications Papers “Historical versus Current Time Slice Theories in Epistemology.” Forthcoming in Hilary Kornblith and Brian McLaughlin (eds.) Goldman and His Critics (Blackwell Publishers), along with a reply by Alvin Goldman. 2 “Disagreement in Philosophy.” Forthcoming in Herman Cappelen, Tamar Szabó Gendler, and John Hawthorne (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology (Oxford University Press). “Are There Any Successful Philosophical Arguments?” (co-authored with Sarah McGrath). Forthcoming in a festschrift for Peter van Inwagen, edited by John Keller for Oxford University Press, along with a reply from van Inwagen. “Religious Diversity and the Epistemology of Disagreement” (co-authored with Nathan King). Forthcoming in William Abraham and Fred Aquino (eds.). The Oxford Handbook to the Epistemology of Theology (Oxford University Press). “Soames and Moore on Method in Ethics and Epistemology” (co-authored with Sarah McGrath). Philosophical Studies Volume 172, Issue 6 (2015): 1661-1670. “Quine and Epistemology”. In Gilbert Harman and Ernest Lepore (eds.) The Blackwell Companion to Quine (Blackwell 2014): 17-37.
    [Show full text]
  • Phd Reading Lists in Philosophy
    PhD Reading Lists in Philosophy [Version 2 (20 June, 2017)] We have not strived to encompass entire fields of philosophy in anything like an encyclopedic manner (that would anyway have been both impossible and undesirable), but to provide in each case a sensible selection whetting the PhD student’s appetite for a field not her own and introducing her to some of the central discussions. Since it is crucial that the Department of Philosophy has the resources to assist in updating the lists, supporting the PhD students in their work, and evaluating the essays, we have aimed to let the lists to a certain extent mirror what the department possesses in terms of competence. Contents Metaphysics ................................................................................................................................ 2 Philosophy of Mind .................................................................................................................... 4 Epistemology .............................................................................................................................. 6 Philosophy of Language ............................................................................................................. 8 Ethics ........................................................................................................................................ 10 Political Philosophy .................................................................................................................. 12 Philosophy of Science .............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Realism (Philosophy of Science ) Fall Term 2016 Instructor: Stathis Psillos Location: STVH 2150H Email: [email protected]; [email protected]
    THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOP 9225A: Scientific Realism (Philosophy of Science ) Fall Term 2016 Instructor: Stathis Psillos Location: STVH 2150H Email: [email protected]; [email protected] Course outline This course will be on scientific realism. We will use my books Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (Routledge 1999) (SRhSTT) and Knowing the Structure of Nature (Palgrave 2009) (KtSoN) as the basis for a thorough and detailed examination of the various aspects of the scientific realism debate, looking into epistemological, metaphysical and semantic issues. The focus will be recent developments and arguments. Emphasis will be given to the following issues: The historical development of the scientific realism debate in the twentieth century The explanationist defence of realism and the various criticisms. The structuralist turns in the early and late twentieth century Various forms of empiricism and their attitude towards scientific realism The role of the history of science in the scientific realism debate The atomism debate in the late nineteenth century TEXTS: Readings will be available through a dropbox folder. COURSE REQUIREMENTS: This is an intensive course. There will be nine sessions in the space of three weeks. Then there will be two or three more sessions over skype with student presentations. All those who take it for credit are required to write two essays. One short essay (about 2000 words) which will be delivered by the end of October and one standard size essay (about 4000 words) to be delivered by the end of November. They are also required to make a presentation of a paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Science, Explanation, and Rationality: Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel
    Science, Explanation, and Rationality: Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel JAMES H. FETZER, Editor OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Science, Explanation, and Rationality Carl G. Hempel (1905–1997) Photograph by Jan Hempel (1985) Science, Explanation, and Rationality Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel Edited by JAMES H. FETZER 1 2000 3 Oxford New York Athens Auckland Bangkok Bogotá Buenos Aires Calcutta Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Florence Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Paris São Paulo Shanghai Singapore Taipei Tokyo Toronto Warsaw and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Copyright © 2000 by Oxford University Press Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madsion Avenue, New York, New York 10016 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Science, explanation, and rationality : aspects of the philosophy of Carl G. Hempel/edited by James H. Fetzer. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 0-19-512137-6 1. Hempel, Carl Gustav, 1905– I. Fetzer, James H., 1940– B945.H454 S35 2000 191—dc21 99–087642 987654321 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper TO PETER in memoriam This page intentionally left blank Editor’s Preface Although Carl G. Hempel was not unusually prolific by some standards (his bibliography reports 112 publications, including a few short monographs and an anthology of twelve articles), his influence was immense.
    [Show full text]
  • University Microfilms. a XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan
    POLE, Nelson, 1941- THE MEANING OF TERMS EMPLOYED IN SCIENTIFIC LANGUAGES AND THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1971 Philosophy University Microfilms. A XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan THIS DISSERTATION HAS BEEN MICROFILMED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED THE MEANING OF TERMS EMPLOYED IN SCIENTIFIC LANGUAGES AND THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Nelson Pole, B. Phil. ***** The Ohio State University 1971 Approved by Adviser Department of Philosophy PLEASE NOTE: Some pages have light and indistinct print. Film as received. UNIVERSITY MICROFILMS. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS A great debt is owed to my Professors at The Ohio State University but especially to my adviser Professor Charles F. Kielkopf. Their constant encouragement and good advice made my days as a graduate student both enjoyable and profitable. My gratitude is also owed to my colleagues in the Department of Philosophy at The Cleveland State University for reading parts of this work and especially for giving me the free time to complete it. Many thanks are due to the capable young ladies who typed the manuscript, Miss Linda Taus, Miss Cathy Stanley and Miss Naomi Cope. Finally, X can never fully express all that I owe to my wife for more things than I am able to mention here. Nelson Pole Cleveland, Ohio ii VITA October 13, 1941. Born— Detroit, Michigan 1963 B. Phil, Monteith College, Wayne State University, Detroit, Michigan 1964-1968 Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, The Ohio State University 1968-1971 Instructor, Department of Philosophy The Cleveland State University PUBLICATIONS "'Self-Supporting* Inductive Arguments," Boston Studies in The Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII, (Boston: Boston University, 1971).
    [Show full text]
  • Inventing Temperature General Editor: Paul Hnmnhrf'vs
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science Inventing Temperature General Editor: Paul Hnmnhrf'vs. University of Virginia ~. Measurement and Scientific Progress The Book oj Evidence Peter Achinstein Science, Truth, and Democracv Philip Kitcher The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction, and Emergence Robert W. Battertrtan Hasok Chang Science and Partial Truth: A Unitary Approach to Models and SCientific Reasoning Newton C. A. da Costa and Steven French Inventin5!. Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Pn)(7fP« Hasok Chang OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 2004 I \ x Acknowledgments Leverhulme Trust, whom I thank most sincerely. I would like to thank the helpful librarians, archivists, and curators at many places including the following, as well as the institutions themselves: the British Library, the London Science Museum and its Library, University College London, Harvard University, Yale University, the Royal Society. the University of Cambridge, and the National Maritime Museum. This book would not have come into being without crucial aJ;1d timely inter­ ventions from various people. The project originated in the course ofmy postdoctoral work with Gerald Holton. Peter Galison initially recommended ihe manuscript Contents for the Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Mary .10 Nye made a crucial structural suggestion. Three referees for Oxford University Press provided very helpful comments that reoriented the book substantially and productively, as well as helped me refine various details. Carl Hoefer and Jeremy Butterfield provided much-needed last-minute advice. Paul Humphreys, the series editor,'encouraged me along for several years and guided the improvement of the. manuscript with great patience and wisdom. Peter Ohlin and Bob Milks directed the process of reviewing, manuscript preparation, and production with kind and expert attention.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining Explanation
    Explaining Explanation David-Hillel Ruben offers a discussion of some of the main historical attempts to explain the concept of explanation, examining the works of Plato, Aristotle, John Stuart Mill, and Carl Hempel. Building on and developing the insights of these historical figures, he introduces an elaboration and defense of his own solution. In this volume, Ruben relates the concept of explanation to both epistemological and metaphysical issues. Not content to confine the concept to the realm of philosophy of science, he examines it within a far more broadly conceived theory of knowledge. He concludes with his own original and challenging explanation of explanation. Explaining Explanation will be read with interest by students of general philosophy as well as those specializing in the philosophy of science and scholars with a more advanced level of interest. The Problems of Philosophy Their Past and Present General Editor: Ted Honderich Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic University College, London Each book in this series is written to bring into view and to deal with a great or significant problem of philosophy. The books are intended to be accessible to undergraduates in philosophy, and to other readers, and to advance the subject, making a contribution to it. The first part of each book presents the history of the problem in question, in some cases its recent past. The second part, of a contemporary and analytic kind, defends and elaborates the author’s preferred solution. Private Ownership James O.Grunebaum Religious
    [Show full text]
  • Sherrilyn Roush
    Sherrilyn Roush Department of Philosophy [email protected] 314 Moses Hall, #2390 University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Employment U.C., Berkeley Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, 2006- Faculty, Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science, 2006- Rice University Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, 1999-2006 Education Harvard University Ph.D., Philosophy, 1999 Pennsylvania State University B.S. degree with highest distinction, in Mathematics, 1988 B.A. degree with highest distinction and honors, in Philosophy, 1988 Areas of Specialization Philosophy of Science, Epistemology Areas of Competence Logic, Metaphysics, Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy Academic Honors Mellon Project Grant, UC Berkeley, “Rational Self-Doubt, 2013-14 Humanities Research Fellowship, UC Berkeley, “Rational Self-Doubt,” 2013-14 NSF grant award SES, 2008-2012, “Fallibility and Revision in Science and Society” Visiting Fellow, Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science, U.C.-Irvine, Spring 2004 Visiting Fellow, Center for Philosophy of Science, Univ. of Pittsburgh, Fall 2003 Woodrow Wilson Career Enhancement Fellowships, 2002, Honorable Mention Center for the Study of Cultures teaching leave fellowship, Fall 2001 American Association of University Women Dissertation Fellowship, 1995-96 National Science Foundation Fellowship, for Philosophy of Science, 1988-91 Mellon Fellow in the Humanities, 1988 cohort Dotterer Prize in Philosophy, Penn State, 1988 National Endowment for the Humanities Younger Scholars Award, summer 1987 1 Page 2 of 7 Publications “Sensitivity and Closure,” in The Sensitivity Principle, Kelly Becker and Tim Black, eds. Cambridge University Press, 2012. “Justification and the Growth of Error,” Philosophical Studies, June 2012. “Skepticism about Reasoning,” with Kelty Allen and Ian Herbert, in New Waves in Philosophical Logic, Gillian Russell and Greg Restall eds.
    [Show full text]