University Microfilms. a XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

University Microfilms. a XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan POLE, Nelson, 1941- THE MEANING OF TERMS EMPLOYED IN SCIENTIFIC LANGUAGES AND THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1971 Philosophy University Microfilms. A XEROX Company, Ann Arbor, Michigan THIS DISSERTATION HAS BEEN MICROFILMED EXACTLY AS RECEIVED THE MEANING OF TERMS EMPLOYED IN SCIENTIFIC LANGUAGES AND THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Nelson Pole, B. Phil. ***** The Ohio State University 1971 Approved by Adviser Department of Philosophy PLEASE NOTE: Some pages have light and indistinct print. Film as received. UNIVERSITY MICROFILMS. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS A great debt is owed to my Professors at The Ohio State University but especially to my adviser Professor Charles F. Kielkopf. Their constant encouragement and good advice made my days as a graduate student both enjoyable and profitable. My gratitude is also owed to my colleagues in the Department of Philosophy at The Cleveland State University for reading parts of this work and especially for giving me the free time to complete it. Many thanks are due to the capable young ladies who typed the manuscript, Miss Linda Taus, Miss Cathy Stanley and Miss Naomi Cope. Finally, X can never fully express all that I owe to my wife for more things than I am able to mention here. Nelson Pole Cleveland, Ohio ii VITA October 13, 1941. Born— Detroit, Michigan 1963 B. Phil, Monteith College, Wayne State University, Detroit, Michigan 1964-1968 Teaching Assistant, Department of Philosophy, The Ohio State University 1968-1971 Instructor, Department of Philosophy The Cleveland State University PUBLICATIONS "'Self-Supporting* Inductive Arguments," Boston Studies in The Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII, (Boston: Boston University, 1971). FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy Studies in the History of Philosophy. Professors Marvin Fox and Robert Turnbull Studies in Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. Professors Alan Hausman and Virgil Hinshaw Studies in Logic. Professors Charles Kielkopf and John Steltzer ill TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS......................................... ii VITA ................................................. iii LIST OF TABLES .................................. vi INTRODUCTION ............................................ 1 Chapter I. SCIENTIFIC LAWS AND M O D E L S .................. 8 1.1 Scientific Laws and T h e o r i e s ........ 9 1.2 Self-Evidence and Conventions ........ 15 1.3 Models and Theories ................. 21 1.4 The Extensions of the Terms of Scientific Discourse .................. 35 1.5 Ontological Status of M o d e l s ......... 39 1.6 Peter Achinstein's Theory ........... 46 1.7 Opera ti o n a l i s m ........................ 55 1.8 Logical Positivism .................... 83 The Verifiability Criterion ........... 64 Reductionism ............ 65 Ultra Empiricism ...................... 66 Fictionallsm ........................... 67 1.9 Symbolic Language ...................... 69 1.10 S u m m a r y ................................. 72 II. COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS AND REFERENCE 74 2.1 The Problem of Counterfactuals .... 75 2.2 Truth Functionality .................... 78 2.3 Reference and Counterfactuals ........ 83 2.4 Nothing Wrong V i e w ................... 91 2.5 The Classical T h e o r y ................. 98 2.6 Extensional Logic ............. 104 III. THE PARADOX OF CONFIRMATION .................. 117 3.1 Paradox of Confirmation............... 117 3.2 The Paradox Dissolved ............... 121 3.3 Existential Import . ............. 130 3.4 Other Approaches .................... 142 3.5 Choosing A Language.................... 155 iv Chapter Page IV. THE PROBLEM OF INDUCTION AND ITS SOLUTION . 164 4.1 The Characterization of Induction . 165 4.2 Counter Examples to Induction .... 185 4.3 Inductive Support............... .. 202 4.4 Some Misconceptions Clarified.. 222 BIBLIOGRAPHY ........................................ 229 v LIST OF TABLES Table 1. The Incompatibility T a b l e ..................... Page 126 vi In Memorial William Pole 1904-1970 vii INTRODUCTION This is a work in the Philosophy of Science. It is about the central semantic problem in the Philosophy of Science: What is the extension of the terms employed in scientific discourse? The answer to this question is used to solve other important problems in the Philosophy of Science. Ultimately, the answer is used to attack the problem of induction. There are at least two main ways of doing the Philosophy of Science. The prescriptive approach to the subject matter lays out the ideal conditions under which science operates. The historical workings of the sciences are of no particular import to such an approach. If the actual workings of scientists do not reflect the findings of such a study, then so much the worse for the science. If procedure X is required for true science and actual science lacks procedure X, then actual science is not true science. For example, if the verifiability criterion was intended as a means of exorcising metaphysical entities from scientific theories, then it was an attempt, on the part of philosophers, to tell scientists how to do science.^- If actual science employed metaphysical entities and true science does not, then actual science is not true science. Prescriptive ^See A. J. Ayer, Language. Truth and Logic, 2nd ed., (New York: Dover, 1952), Introduction. 1 philosophy of science shall only be found in this work as the butt of criticism. Descriptive philosophy of science is an attempt to describe the actual working processes of the 2 scientist. Thomas Kuhn and others have pioneered this approach. It is not important to accept the judgements of scientists about what they are doing but it is important to refrain from telling them what to do. Scientists may be in the dark as to what they are doing; that is, they may make mistaken judgements about the importance of their activities or the nature of their activities. For example, in Chapter One some scientists will appear who claim to observe atomic particles. Philosophy of Science in the descriptive mode notes their claim but need only account for their making such judgements not for those judgements being true. The descriptivist may well disagree with the scientists who claim to observe atomic particles for the scientist in making such a judgement is being a philosopher of science. As a philosopher, the scientist has no special competency; his pronouncements are as challengeable as any other philosopher. The measure of descriptive philosophy of science is that the philosopher is always examining his findings to insure that the scientist can actually do science if the scientist follows the philosopher's findings. Since the only measure of what can be done is what is actually done, the ^See The Structure of Scientific Revelations.(Chicago: University of Chicago, 1962). 3 descriptivist always checks to see that his findings describe actual practice in the sciences. For him there is no difference between true science and actual science. The flavor of this work is descriptive. It will be an operating principle of analysis that any philosopher's view which has the consequence that science as practiced should not be done is to be rejected for that very reason. Further, any . scientific activity which seems to be necessary for the functioning of science shall be regarded with utmost seriousness for that very reason. Activities which have been important in science since the rise of contemporary science shall be considered central to the scientific enterprise. Philosophies of Science which discount historically important phenomena shall be themselves discounted here. For example, positivists, especially logical positivists, have always depreciated the role of models in the sciences. For them, the model is merely a heuristic device. But models have played a central role in the development of science by providing a stimulus to new research. Further, models seem to be needed for explanation to occur. Whatever logical problems there may be with models, they will have to be lived with since models have been so important for science and scientists show no sign of giving them up. The focus on models is the central innovation of this study. It is a study in what Kuhn has termed "normal" science, science during the period following a significant innovation, science principally concerned with getting the details straight after an intellectual revolution. Scientists attempt to discover laws which relate some properties of a system to other properties. In Newtonian Mechanics the properties related are acceleration, mass, distance, and force. Laws ignore most properties of the system. Hence there is a distinction, funda­ mental to science, between primary qualities and secondary qualities, between qualities necessary for the statement of laws and those which are analysed in terms of the properties mentioned in the laws. A model is a depiction of the world using only the primary qualities. Nevertheless, the model is no more a depiction of the real world than the world as phenomenally presented is real. Since the world can be under­ stood either through the model or through the phenomenal presentation of it, either way of understanding it is as good as the other. There is but one world, it may be described either scientifically or phenomenally, but it is the same world. The difficulty with constructing either description of the world
Recommended publications
  • Constructive Empiricism in the Social Sciences
    Constructive empiricism in the social sciences Abstract ‘What problems face the aspirant empiricist today?’ is the question Bas C. van Fraassen asks in his seminal work The Scientific Image (1980). In this thesis, I interpret this question as a challenge to develop constructive empiricism [CE] in a field of scientific inquiry other than the context of physics in which it was conceived. The first part of the thesis expounds CE with reference to classical empiricism, discloses some of its fundamental assumptions, and spells out in detail its account of science. In the second part of the thesis, CE is extended to social science. Since CE was developed in the context of natural science, I take an articulation of the alleged fundamental differences between natural and social science as indicating challenges a CE-outlook on social science must address. I also provide a brief history of the gap between the sciences. Then, in the bulk of this thesis, I argue that CE’s model view accommodates social science, that description, prediction and explanation in the light of CE are proper fruits of inquiry in social science, and that CE is able to make sense of the differences in the concepts used in natural and social science. In the discussion of the feasibility of CE for social science, I show concurrently that contemporary articulations of the differences between the natural and the social sciences pose no insuperable problems for the constructive empiricist. Bram van Dijk | 3691454 History & Philosophy of Science | Utrecht University Daily supervisors | dr. Guido Bacciagaluppi & dr. Ruud Abma Third examiner | dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Faculty of Humanities School of Social Sciences
    FACULTY OF HUMANITIES SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES PHILOSOPHY COURSE UNIT OUTLINE 2017-18 PHIL20021 Philosophy of Religion Semester: 1 Credits: 20 This course guide should be read in conjunction with the Philosophy Study Guide 2016-17, available from the Philosophy Intranet. Lecturer(s): Dr Michael Scott Office: Humanities Bridgeford Street 2.56 Telephone: 0161 275 3875 Email: [email protected] Office Hours: Tuesdays 10-11, Wednesdays 11-12. Please email to arrange an appointment outside of these hours. Tutors: Tutorials will be taken by Teaching Assistants – see below. Their office hours will be posted here: http://www.socialsciences.manchester.ac.uk/student- intranet/undergraduate/course-information/philosophy/office-hours/ Administrator: Christopher Ashworth, UG Office, G.001 Arthur Lewis Building Tel: 0161 275 7129, Email: [email protected] Lectures: Tues 11-1pm. Tutorials: Allocate yourself to a tutorial group using the Student System (this is compulsory and on a first come, first served basis) Assessment: 2 hour exam 67% 2,000 word essay 33% Reading Week: Monday 30th October 2017 – Friday 3rd November 2017 Philosophy Intranet: http://www.socialsciences.manchester.ac.uk/student- intranet/undergraduate/course-information/philosophy/ Please go to the intranet for staff and TA office hours, the Philosophy Study Guide, and advice on accessing online philosophy resources. ***IMPORTANT INFORMATION – PLEASE READ*** Pre-requisite(s): None Communication: Students must read their University e-mails regularly, as important information will be communicated in this way. Examination period: Monday 15 January – Friday 26 January 2018 1 Re-sit Examination period: Monday 20th August – Friday 31st August 2018 Please read this course outline through very carefully as it provides essential information needed by all students attending this course 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Study and Teaching of Philosophy of Science
    The Study and Teaching of Philosophy of Science An Academic Interview of Professor Peter Achinstein Liang: Could you please share some more details about the reason why you chose philosophy of science as a life-time business? It is said that you were motivated by Hempel when you were studying at Harvard. Is that true? Achinstein: Well, I didn’t choose it at the beginning as a life-time career, but philosophy was always fascinating to me, since it raises fundamental questions that I find very challenging. I chose to do my Ph.D. thesis on probability theory, particularly Carnap’s probability theory, and that got me interested in philosophy of science. The philosopher who had the greatest influence on me as a student was Carl G. Hempel, who came to visit Harvard one year when I was an undergraduate. He taught a course on probability, and one on philosophy of science. These were the most interesting philosophy courses I’d taken at Harvard. When I was a graduate student, I wrote my thesis in the area of probability and induction. This led me to the question: what is evidence, and can it be defined in terms of probability? At the same time, I began attending courses in physics at Harvard and later at Johns Hopkins, which got me further interested the philosophy of science. So, I didn’t start out by planning to work in the philosophy of science. When I became a graduate student, I was not like some graduate students who are sure what they want to focus on at the very beginning of their study.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of the Writings of Hilary Putnam
    PART THREE BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF HILARY PUTNAM Compiled and Edited by John R. ShooK with the assistance of Hilary Putnam anD Joseph PalenCIK Putnam Bibliography.indd 891 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM Putnam Bibliography.indd 892 1/24/2015 4:09:12 PM BIBLIOGRAPHY OF THE WRITINGS OF Hilary Putnam This bibliography lists books and then shorter writings, in chronological order of their first publication. Chapters of books are accompanied by a year of first publication; those chapters lacking a year were first published in that book. Only selected reprintings of shorter writings are mentioned, to clarify multiple versions. A translation of a shorter item is included if that was its first publication; any later publication in English is mentioned. BOOKS The Meaning of the Concept of Probability in Application to Finite Sequences. Ph.D. dis- sertation, University of California, Los Angeles, 1951. New York: Garland, 1990. The 1990 reprinting includes “Introduction Some Years Later,” 1–12. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings. Edited with Paul Benacerraf. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1964. Includes an “Introduction” with Paul Benacerraf, 1–27. The 2nd edition (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1983) adds two chapters by Putnam: “Mathematics without Foundations” (1967), 295–313; and “Models and Reality” (1980), 421–45. Philosophy of Logic. New York: Harper and Row, 1971. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1972. Translated into Italian (1975), Japanese (1975), Chinese (1984). Repr. in Math- ematics, Matter and Method, 2nd ed. (1985), 323–57. Repr., London: Routledge, 2010. CONTENTS Preface, vii 1. What Logic Is, 3–7 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Kelly
    Thomas Kelly Department of Philosophy https://www.princeton.edu/~tkelly/ Princeton University [email protected] 212 1879 Hall (609) 258-4294 (tel) Princeton, NJ 08544 Employment Princeton University, 2004- Professor of Philosophy, 2012- Associate Professor of Philosophy, 2007-2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, 2004-2007 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, 2003-2004. Junior Fellow, Harvard Society of Fellows, 2000-2003. Education Ph.D. in Philosophy, Harvard University, 2001. B.A. in Philosophy, summa cum laude, University of Notre Dame, 1994. Areas of Specialization Epistemology, Theory of Rationality, Philosophical Methodology Areas of Competence History of Analytic Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Ethics, Philosophy of Religion Publications Papers “Historical versus Current Time Slice Theories in Epistemology.” Forthcoming in Hilary Kornblith and Brian McLaughlin (eds.) Goldman and His Critics (Blackwell Publishers), along with a reply by Alvin Goldman. 2 “Disagreement in Philosophy.” Forthcoming in Herman Cappelen, Tamar Szabó Gendler, and John Hawthorne (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology (Oxford University Press). “Are There Any Successful Philosophical Arguments?” (co-authored with Sarah McGrath). Forthcoming in a festschrift for Peter van Inwagen, edited by John Keller for Oxford University Press, along with a reply from van Inwagen. “Religious Diversity and the Epistemology of Disagreement” (co-authored with Nathan King). Forthcoming in William Abraham and Fred Aquino (eds.). The Oxford Handbook to the Epistemology of Theology (Oxford University Press). “Soames and Moore on Method in Ethics and Epistemology” (co-authored with Sarah McGrath). Philosophical Studies Volume 172, Issue 6 (2015): 1661-1670. “Quine and Epistemology”. In Gilbert Harman and Ernest Lepore (eds.) The Blackwell Companion to Quine (Blackwell 2014): 17-37.
    [Show full text]
  • Subjective Views of Kuhn
    Subjective Views of Kuhn Peter Achinstein Johns Hopkins University In response to a charge of subjectivism, Kuhn in his Postscript emphasizes the importance of “values” (accuracy, simplicity, explanatory power, etc) that are shared by scientists generally. However, Kuhn adds, these values are applied differently by different scientists. By employing a comparison with partially subjective views of Carnap on conªrming evidence, this paper raises questions about Kuhn’s position on values by considering ways it might be interpreted as subjective and ways it may not. Many philosophers of science have wrestled with the question of whether there is a universal scientiªc method, i.e., a set of rules for discovering or testing scientiªc hypotheses. The rules are universal because they hold for all sciences and all times. Examples might include rules of the sort that Descartes proposed (his 21 rules) in Rules for the Direction of the Mind, or the 4 rules of reasoning that begin the third book of Newton’s Principia. Two major ªgures in 20th century philosophy of science, Karl Popper and Paul Feyerabend, whose deaths occurred within a year or two of Kuhn’s, offered strikingly different answers to the question of whether universal rules exist. Popper’s answer I take to be a resounding, “Yes,” at least to the question of whether there are such rules in the case of scientiªc testing or justiªcation. (Rules of discovery, he believed, are another mat- ter.) Popper’s method of corroboration—his version of hypothetico- deductivism—is, I believe, intended to be a universal scientiªc method for testing hypotheses.
    [Show full text]
  • Phd Reading Lists in Philosophy
    PhD Reading Lists in Philosophy [Version 2 (20 June, 2017)] We have not strived to encompass entire fields of philosophy in anything like an encyclopedic manner (that would anyway have been both impossible and undesirable), but to provide in each case a sensible selection whetting the PhD student’s appetite for a field not her own and introducing her to some of the central discussions. Since it is crucial that the Department of Philosophy has the resources to assist in updating the lists, supporting the PhD students in their work, and evaluating the essays, we have aimed to let the lists to a certain extent mirror what the department possesses in terms of competence. Contents Metaphysics ................................................................................................................................ 2 Philosophy of Mind .................................................................................................................... 4 Epistemology .............................................................................................................................. 6 Philosophy of Language ............................................................................................................. 8 Ethics ........................................................................................................................................ 10 Political Philosophy .................................................................................................................. 12 Philosophy of Science .............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Realism (Philosophy of Science ) Fall Term 2016 Instructor: Stathis Psillos Location: STVH 2150H Email: [email protected]; [email protected]
    THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOP 9225A: Scientific Realism (Philosophy of Science ) Fall Term 2016 Instructor: Stathis Psillos Location: STVH 2150H Email: [email protected]; [email protected] Course outline This course will be on scientific realism. We will use my books Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (Routledge 1999) (SRhSTT) and Knowing the Structure of Nature (Palgrave 2009) (KtSoN) as the basis for a thorough and detailed examination of the various aspects of the scientific realism debate, looking into epistemological, metaphysical and semantic issues. The focus will be recent developments and arguments. Emphasis will be given to the following issues: The historical development of the scientific realism debate in the twentieth century The explanationist defence of realism and the various criticisms. The structuralist turns in the early and late twentieth century Various forms of empiricism and their attitude towards scientific realism The role of the history of science in the scientific realism debate The atomism debate in the late nineteenth century TEXTS: Readings will be available through a dropbox folder. COURSE REQUIREMENTS: This is an intensive course. There will be nine sessions in the space of three weeks. Then there will be two or three more sessions over skype with student presentations. All those who take it for credit are required to write two essays. One short essay (about 2000 words) which will be delivered by the end of October and one standard size essay (about 4000 words) to be delivered by the end of November. They are also required to make a presentation of a paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Science, Explanation, and Rationality: Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel
    Science, Explanation, and Rationality: Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel JAMES H. FETZER, Editor OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS Science, Explanation, and Rationality Carl G. Hempel (1905–1997) Photograph by Jan Hempel (1985) Science, Explanation, and Rationality Aspects of the Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel Edited by JAMES H. FETZER 1 2000 3 Oxford New York Athens Auckland Bangkok Bogotá Buenos Aires Calcutta Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Florence Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi Paris São Paulo Shanghai Singapore Taipei Tokyo Toronto Warsaw and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Copyright © 2000 by Oxford University Press Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madsion Avenue, New York, New York 10016 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Science, explanation, and rationality : aspects of the philosophy of Carl G. Hempel/edited by James H. Fetzer. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 0-19-512137-6 1. Hempel, Carl Gustav, 1905– I. Fetzer, James H., 1940– B945.H454 S35 2000 191—dc21 99–087642 987654321 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper TO PETER in memoriam This page intentionally left blank Editor’s Preface Although Carl G. Hempel was not unusually prolific by some standards (his bibliography reports 112 publications, including a few short monographs and an anthology of twelve articles), his influence was immense.
    [Show full text]
  • Inventing Temperature General Editor: Paul Hnmnhrf'vs
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Science Inventing Temperature General Editor: Paul Hnmnhrf'vs. University of Virginia ~. Measurement and Scientific Progress The Book oj Evidence Peter Achinstein Science, Truth, and Democracv Philip Kitcher The Devil in the Details: Asymptotic Reasoning in Explanation, Reduction, and Emergence Robert W. Battertrtan Hasok Chang Science and Partial Truth: A Unitary Approach to Models and SCientific Reasoning Newton C. A. da Costa and Steven French Inventin5!. Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Pn)(7fP« Hasok Chang OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 2004 I \ x Acknowledgments Leverhulme Trust, whom I thank most sincerely. I would like to thank the helpful librarians, archivists, and curators at many places including the following, as well as the institutions themselves: the British Library, the London Science Museum and its Library, University College London, Harvard University, Yale University, the Royal Society. the University of Cambridge, and the National Maritime Museum. This book would not have come into being without crucial aJ;1d timely inter­ ventions from various people. The project originated in the course ofmy postdoctoral work with Gerald Holton. Peter Galison initially recommended ihe manuscript Contents for the Oxford Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Mary .10 Nye made a crucial structural suggestion. Three referees for Oxford University Press provided very helpful comments that reoriented the book substantially and productively, as well as helped me refine various details. Carl Hoefer and Jeremy Butterfield provided much-needed last-minute advice. Paul Humphreys, the series editor,'encouraged me along for several years and guided the improvement of the. manuscript with great patience and wisdom. Peter Ohlin and Bob Milks directed the process of reviewing, manuscript preparation, and production with kind and expert attention.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining Explanation
    Explaining Explanation David-Hillel Ruben offers a discussion of some of the main historical attempts to explain the concept of explanation, examining the works of Plato, Aristotle, John Stuart Mill, and Carl Hempel. Building on and developing the insights of these historical figures, he introduces an elaboration and defense of his own solution. In this volume, Ruben relates the concept of explanation to both epistemological and metaphysical issues. Not content to confine the concept to the realm of philosophy of science, he examines it within a far more broadly conceived theory of knowledge. He concludes with his own original and challenging explanation of explanation. Explaining Explanation will be read with interest by students of general philosophy as well as those specializing in the philosophy of science and scholars with a more advanced level of interest. The Problems of Philosophy Their Past and Present General Editor: Ted Honderich Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic University College, London Each book in this series is written to bring into view and to deal with a great or significant problem of philosophy. The books are intended to be accessible to undergraduates in philosophy, and to other readers, and to advance the subject, making a contribution to it. The first part of each book presents the history of the problem in question, in some cases its recent past. The second part, of a contemporary and analytic kind, defends and elaborates the author’s preferred solution. Private Ownership James O.Grunebaum Religious
    [Show full text]
  • Sherrilyn Roush
    Sherrilyn Roush Department of Philosophy [email protected] 314 Moses Hall, #2390 University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720-2390 Employment U.C., Berkeley Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, 2006- Faculty, Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science, 2006- Rice University Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, 1999-2006 Education Harvard University Ph.D., Philosophy, 1999 Pennsylvania State University B.S. degree with highest distinction, in Mathematics, 1988 B.A. degree with highest distinction and honors, in Philosophy, 1988 Areas of Specialization Philosophy of Science, Epistemology Areas of Competence Logic, Metaphysics, Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy Academic Honors Mellon Project Grant, UC Berkeley, “Rational Self-Doubt, 2013-14 Humanities Research Fellowship, UC Berkeley, “Rational Self-Doubt,” 2013-14 NSF grant award SES, 2008-2012, “Fallibility and Revision in Science and Society” Visiting Fellow, Dept. of Logic and Philosophy of Science, U.C.-Irvine, Spring 2004 Visiting Fellow, Center for Philosophy of Science, Univ. of Pittsburgh, Fall 2003 Woodrow Wilson Career Enhancement Fellowships, 2002, Honorable Mention Center for the Study of Cultures teaching leave fellowship, Fall 2001 American Association of University Women Dissertation Fellowship, 1995-96 National Science Foundation Fellowship, for Philosophy of Science, 1988-91 Mellon Fellow in the Humanities, 1988 cohort Dotterer Prize in Philosophy, Penn State, 1988 National Endowment for the Humanities Younger Scholars Award, summer 1987 1 Page 2 of 7 Publications “Sensitivity and Closure,” in The Sensitivity Principle, Kelly Becker and Tim Black, eds. Cambridge University Press, 2012. “Justification and the Growth of Error,” Philosophical Studies, June 2012. “Skepticism about Reasoning,” with Kelty Allen and Ian Herbert, in New Waves in Philosophical Logic, Gillian Russell and Greg Restall eds.
    [Show full text]