Strictly Platonic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Strictly Platonic preface Strictly Platonic n a 1903 short story by Mildred Champagne, Mrs. Judson asks the doc- Itor she visits: “Do you believe in platonic friendship between man and woman?”1 The plot of the story revolves around the idea that he is in love with her, so the question drops on him like a “bomb.” She is asking him, of course, if a man and woman can be friends without the involvement of sex or sexual desire. But the meaning of the phrase “platonic friendship,” which also happens to be the title of the story, is so well known that Mrs. Judson does not have to explain it. In fact, after asking the question, she adds: “By platonic, you know, I mean what is generally accepted by the term” (12). Today, in English, we use the term so widely that we, too, know what is generally accepted by “platonic.” We talk of “platonic love” or “platonic friendship,” or we say that a relationship is “platonic” or that two people love each other “platonically.” When we talk of a “platonic” relationship, we may imagine a man and a woman who are “just friends.” Pop cultural sources affirm this usage. On the website craigslist, a rubric for personal ads includes a section titled “strictly platonic.”2 Wikipedia defines the phrase “platonic love” as “a type of love that is chaste and non- sexual.”3 The on- line “Your Dictionary” defines this sense of the term as “designating or of a relationship, or love, between a man and a woman that is purely spiritual or intellectual and without sexual activity.”4 The OED provides the following as the relevant definition of “platonic”: “Of love, affection, or friendship: intimate and affectionate but not sexual; spiritual rather than physical.”5 This use of the term is not a recent invention. The OED’s list of ex- amples for “platonic” as not sexual begins with a series of seventeenth- century examples, the first occurring in Ben Jonson’s 1631 play The New Inn. William Davenant’s 1636 English play The Platonic Lovers is about two sets of male- female couples, one platonic and the other not platonic. vii viii preface The Dizionario etimologico della lingua italiana gives 1544 as the date of appearance of the Italian phrase amor platonico.6 Platonique enters into French in 1659 as part of the phrase amour à la platonique, transformed in the following century into amour platonique.7 The phrase amour pla­ tonique appears, for example, in a 1739 “Epistle to Thérèse about Platonic Love,” which concludes with a reference to “the laws of Platonic Love.”8 The 1762 edition of the Dictionnaire de l’Académie française defines amour platonique as “mutual affection between two people of different sexes, whose end is merit, with no relation to the senses.”9 But if there is a generally accepted meaning in these various time pe- riods, it is a historically inaccurate one. In Plato, love— or more precisely, eros— incorporates the senses and is not necessarily asexual. If fidelity to Plato were the goal, the phrase “Socratic love” would be better suited to describe the relation since Socrates appears as chaste in Plato. That Voltaire in the eighteenth century uses the phrase “Socratic love” to refer to peder- asty suggests that “platonic love” was already defined as an asexual relation between men and women.10 While the Platonic dialogues absolutely allow for the possibility of intimate, affectionate, and spiritual love, what we and early moderns call “platonic love” would likely seem somewhat strange to Plato. The scene from the story “Platonic Friendship” might have confused Plato, too, had he read it. Although Plato never used the phrase, the sense of “platonic love” for him would undoubtedly evoke the image of a man with a younger male. While male- female love is not always excluded in Plato, male- male eros was clearly the highest form of love and “platonic love” would certainly not be imagined by Plato as between two people of different sexes. Were the philosopher to read craigslist, he might take “strictly pla- tonic” as a category requiring a man and a boy of a fixed age and as discount- ing love between a man and a woman or between two grown men. Mrs. Judson’s notion of platonic, then, does not correspond to Plato on two counts: the sex of the two people involved and the possibility of sexual activity between them. How did this shift happen? How did Platonic eros turn into “platonic love”? How did it become heterosexual and purified of sex? This process of “setting Plato straight” is the subject of this book, which recounts the story of how and why these changes happened. Not a rapid or sudden shift, it takes place in the Renaissance over the course of ap- proximately a century and a half, particularly in Italy and France. While the fifteenth- century Florentine Platonist Marsilio Ficino is credited with coin- ing the Latin phrase “platonic love” [amor platonicus], he does not single- handedly transform Plato, but rather he is a part— albeit an important part— of a much larger cultural transformation.11 Setting Plato Straight dis- strictly platonic ix cusses a key moment in what Louis-Georges Tin calls “the invention of heterosexual culture.”12 By virtue of transforming Platonic same- sex sexu- ality, the Renaissance creates a type of heterosexuality, even if the term or concept is not yet articulated as such. This book is composed of a series of studies of important Western European texts in which this transformation occurs. While I do not treat the English context (that would require a second book), the texts studied here strongly influence what happens across the Channel as the English are reading many of these texts. I am told by native speakers of many languages (e.g., Arabic, Dutch, German, Hebrew, Polish, Portuguese, Romanian, Spanish, Turkish) that a version of “platonic love” in the modern sense exists in their languages, suggesting that this usage, whose origins I locate in the Renaissance, has become widespread around the globe and that the influence of the texts I study extends well beyond their specific cultural contexts. Despite this transformation of eros, some thinkers display an awareness of the anachronism of “platonic love.” In the play The Platonic Lovers, the physician- philosopher Buonateste remarks about Plato to Lord Sciolto: “I still beseech you not to wrong / My good old friend Plato, with this court calumnie; / They father on him a Fantastick Love / Hee never knew, poore Gentleman.”13 He is responding to the Lord who noted that his son is “very much Platonically given” (139). Soon after, another character asks the phi- losopher “Did not Plato write of Love?” to which the philosopher responds: “Divinely sir, but not such kind of Love / As Ladies would have now; they mistake him” (140). Part of the issue in the play is Sciolto’s son, who “mis- takes [Plato] too” since he “understands no Greeke” (140). The Lord thus plans to “give’t him straight” (140). The philosopher’s comic remarks sug- gest an awareness that the English of the time are seeing Platonic eros as straight instead of getting him straight, thus that the cultural process of set- ting Plato straight is in no way an even or linear process without hiccups. One of the key arguments of this book is that the Renaissance does not fully set Plato straight, and that the numerous and various attempts to do so never fully take hold. In this way, Setting Plato Straight is meant as a contribu- tion to a twenty- first- century sexual counterdiscourse that reveals how our assumptions about so- called platonic love cover up a series of normative sexual slippages and mutations. .
Recommended publications
  • Corrupted Platonism in Astrophil and Stella: the Expression of Desire
    Corrupted Platonism in Astrophil and Stella: The Expression of Desire Sonia Hernández Santano UNIVERSIDAD DE HUELVA [email protected] Astrophil’s love for Stella is not the conventional Platonic love of Petrarchist poems. We cannot fully consider him the romantic lover who aspires to a spiritual enjoying of his lady’s virtues and beauty for, though he attempts to represent his feelings according to the parameters of Platonism, he also makes his basest sexual desire flourish in many of the sonnets or songs of Astrophil and Stella. It is not that his begins by being a pure love that progressively degenerates into a blatant expression of his sexual needs due to an increase of his desire. The material nature of his love as opposed to spiritual love is obvious from the very beginning of the sequence. It is, however, a fact that Astrophil does frequently express his amorous feeling by means of Platonic topics such as the correspondence between physical beauty and spiritual virtue, as in sonnet 48 when he refers to Stella’s eyes as “where Virtue is made strong by Beautie’s might” (l. 2) or that he identifies himself with the agonizing lover of Petrarchist sequences who suffers the wounds of Cupid as in sonnet 20: “Fly, fly, my friends, I have my death wound” (l. 1) or with the slave of his beloved as in sonnet 47: “What, have I thus betrayed my libertie?” (l. 1). But the Platonic representation of his love is continually corrupted by frequent ironic allusions to it and to sexual desire.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Love for Persons Vlastos (1973) Raises a Famous Critique of Plato's Account of Love in the Symposium. the Highest
    Platonic Love for Persons Vlastos (1973) raises a famous critique of Plato’s account of love in the Symposium. The highest form of erōs, as it is described in Diotima’s scala amoris, is not for any particular individual but takes as its object the form of beauty itself (211a1-d1). Furthermore, erōs for an individual features in this account purely as stepping-stone to the philosopher’s comprehension of beauty. Not only is it difficult to understand what this impersonal erōs is, but it is difficult to understand why Plato thinks it is such an important part of a life well lived. So puzzled is Vlastos by the impersonality of erōs on this account that he ultimately finds it lacking in “kindness, tenderness, compassion,” and “respect for the integrity of the beloved” (30). What is missing, he claims, is an account of love for “persons who are themselves worthy of love for their own sake.” Since the publication of Vlastos’ critique, many have attempted to save Plato’s account by showing that love of particular individuals is consistent with or important to the philosopher’s pursuit of beauty (i.e. Price 1981, Nehamas 2007, Sheffield 2009, Urstad 2010). In other words, scholars have attempted to show that the impersonal love of the Symposium is not so impersonal after all. This paper takes a somewhat different approach; it argues that the impersonal nature of erōs in the Symposium is consistent with an overarching lack of esteem for personal relationships elsewhere in the dialogues. In the Crito, for example, Socrates appears largely unconcerned with the care of his sons, ranking his obligation to them well behind his duty to the laws (54b2-3).
    [Show full text]
  • Concepts of Love and Some Implications for Education
    CONCEPTS OF LOVE AND SOME IMPLICATIONS FOR EDUCATION Dina Andersen A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the Department of Theory and Policy Studies in Education, Ontario Institute for Studies in Education of the Universis. of Toronto Copyright 0 Dina Andersen 1998 National Library Bibliothèque nationale of Canada du Canada Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Ottawa ON K1A ON4 Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence allowing the exclusive permettant à la National Library of Canada to ~ibliothequenationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distribute or sell reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de rnicrofiche/fïlm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thèse. thesis nor substantial extracts fiom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otheMrise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimes reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS When 1 decided to undertake a study of love 1 did not realize that rnany would express hesitations and personal reservations about the topic. 1 am therefore doubly grateful to Dr. Clive Beck, chair, for his continuous support, and to Dr. Grace Feuerverger as well as Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Love in a Colorado Courtroom: Martha Nussbaum, John Finnis, and Plato's Laws in Evans V
    Articles Platonic Love in a Colorado Courtroom: Martha Nussbaum, John Finnis, and Plato's Laws in Evans v. Romer Randall Baldwin Clark* I. RELEVANT FOR FIFTEEN MINUTES-OR THIRTY CENTURIES? To the ridicule of the highbrow popular press' and the surprise of classical scholars,2 Plato's Laws,3 a work which was mocked, even in * University of Virginia School of Law, Class of 2002. Ph.D., University of Chicago, 1998. Research Associate, Dartmouth College Department of Government, 1997-99. Author, THE LAW MOST BEAUTIFUL AND BEST: MEDICAL ARGUMENT AND MAGICAL RHETORIC IN PLATO'S LAWS (Rowman & Littlefield - Lexington Books, forthcoming 2001). This article has benefited from the comments of many friends, colleagues, and teachers. For their assistance, I would like to thank Danielle Allen, Larry Arnhart, Richard 0. Brooks, Robert A. Burt, Allison D. Clark, Andrew P. Clark, Elizabeth A. Clark, Glenn W. Clark, Matthew Crawford, Richard Dougherty, Martha A. Field, Shawntel R. Fugate, Martin P. Golding, L. Kent Greenawalt, A.E. Dick Howard, Leon R. Kass, Matthew Kutcher, Melissa S. Lane, Mark J. Lutz, Roger D. Masters, Lynn Mather, Angelia K. Means, Ted H. Miller, S. Sarah Monoson, David Peritz, Richard A. Posner, Christopher Rohrbacher, Ariel C. Silver, Nathan Tarcov, Bradley A. Thayer, Elizabeth E. Theran, Paul Ulrich, Eduardo A. Velasquez, Lloyd L. Weinreb, Martin D. Yaffe, and the members of my edit team at the Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities. I only regret that I was unable to address all of their criticisms. Particularly profound appreciation is owed to my friend and colleague, James B. Murphy, whose queries helped me conceive this work and whose encouragement brought it to light: aneu gar phil6n oudeis heloit' an zen.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic Relationship” Basically Means a Super-Deep by Sara Gaynes Levy Jan 27, 2020 Connection
    enough value on platonic love,” says Jordana Jacobs, PhD, a psychologist in New York City. This strictly non-sexual SUBSCRIBE SIGN IN relationship “has the potential to be deep, intense, and life-altering,” she says. But how to make them work, How to Make a Platonic Friendship Work especially if you're married to someone else, is a question that many couples and friends grapple with. The key is to set boundaries. And, be honest with your spouse, if you have one. “Platonic relationship” basically means a super-deep By Sara Gaynes Levy Jan 27, 2020 connection. This type of friendship can exist between many pairs, though it’s most commonly associated with a connection between members of the opposite sex (think: When Harry Met Sally). Of course it can also occur between pals of all genders and orientation. It’s worth noting that not every friendship is a platonic one. “When you meet a person, there is a process by which you determine what kind of role they'll play in your life, including how close you are meant to be with them,” says Jacobs. If you ultimately end up feeling that deep connection, that’s platonic love. A healthy platonic friendship means no sexual feelings are involved. “I see platonic love as a special emotional and spiritual relationship between two people,” says Diana Raab, PhD, author of Writing for Bliss. “It does not involve any type of sexual interest, but there is deep caring, mutual respect, and loyalty,” she says. More from Oprah Daily Nathan Harris Discusses His Debut Novel with Oprah NBC Between love songs, romantic comedies, and will-they-won’t-they TV couples, the world has done a pretty good job convincing us that romantic love is paramount.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Love and Divine Love: the Platonic Matrix in C.S. Lewis
    Western Kentucky University TopSCHOLAR® Masters Theses & Specialist Projects Graduate School 7-1975 Human Love and Divine Love: The lP atonic Matrix in C.S. Lewis Laura Case Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/theses Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons, Christianity Commons, Literature in English, British Isles Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Case, Laura, "Human Love and Divine Love: The lP atonic Matrix in C.S. Lewis" (1975). Masters Theses & Specialist Projects. Paper 1379. http://digitalcommons.wku.edu/theses/1379 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by TopSCHOLAR®. It has been accepted for inclusion in Masters Theses & Specialist Projects by an authorized administrator of TopSCHOLAR®. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HUMAN LOVE AND DIVINE LOVE: THE PLATONIC MATRIX IN C. S. LEWIS A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of the Program in HUMANITIES Western Kentucky University Bowling Green, Kentucky In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts by Laura Ann Case July 1975 HUMAN LOVE AND DIVINE LOVE : THE PLATONIC MATRIX IN C. S. LEWIS -t, "')"': ..,,- Recommended ___~' __ '~'~=>~'.~------- (Date) Approved '1_.2 5 7~':J (Date) the Gra uate 0 lege ACKNO\'lLEDGEMENTS \iith deep appreciation I wish to express my gratitude to those persons who were influential in my undertaking of this thesis. First, I thank Dr. Ronald Nash who introduced me to the ideas of Plato and to the remarkable Dr. John T. Stahl . With his shared enthusiasm and knowledge of C. S.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Platonic Love and Internet Pornography
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Sussex Research Online Sexuality & Culture DOI 10.1007/s12119-017-9440-z ORIGINAL PAPER Between Platonic Love and Internet Pornography 1 2 Tanja Staehler • Alexander Kozin Ó The Author(s) 2017. This article is an open access publication Abstract The article sets out to show how an holistic approach in matters of sexuality is always more helpful than one-sided approaches. On the issue of internet pornography, the authors suggest that the recent anti-masturbation online movement ‘no fapping’ is based on wrong conclusions from insufficient evidence. We suggest that a holistic approach is called for, with emphasis on the embodied human. Abstinence or what is understood by ‘Platonic love’ is not a solution, according to Plato himself. From a phenomenological perspective, we suggest owning up to our strange bodies and habitualising sexual activity. Keywords Phenomenology Á Pornography Á Internet Á Internet porn Á Platonic love Á Plato Á Levinas Á Merleau-Ponty Á Nancy Á Eros Á Flirtation Á Body Á Corporeality Á Masters and Johnson Á Masters of Sex Á Desire Á Strangeness Á Dialogue At its heart, though, you might say that Masters of Sex—the book and the show—is a postmodernist parable about the limits of science; how modern medicine can never truly understand our deepest, most intimate feelings. Masters’ and Johnson’s study of hormones and electrocardiogram impulses could deepen our understanding of our own skin and corpuscles, but alone it could not touch the soul, the essence of the bond between two people.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. Editions Perna, Petrus. 1580. Plotini platonicorum facile coryphaei operum philosophicorum omnium libri LIV: in sex enneades distributi. Basileae: Ad Perneam Lecythum. Fabricius, Johann Albert. 1711. Bibliothecae graecae libri IV. Hamburgi: [Christiani Liebezeit]. Creuzer, Georg Friedrich, Georg Heinrich Moser, and Daniel Wyttenbach. 1835. Plotini opera omnia, Porphyrii liber de vita Plotini. 3 vols. Oxonii: e typographaeo Academico. Westermann, Anton. 1850. Porphyrius De vita Plotini apud Carel Gabriel Cobet, Diogenis Laertii de clarorum philosophorum vitis, dogmatibus et apophthegmatibus libri decem. Paris: Firmin Didot. Kirchhoff, Adolf. 1856. Plotini opera. 2 vols. Bibl. Teubneriana. Lipsiae: in aedibus B. G. Teubneri. Müller, Hermann Friedrich. 1878-80. Plotini Enneades. 2 vols. Berolini: apud Weidmannos. von Volkmann, Richard. 1883-4. Plotini Enneades, praemisso Porphyrii de vita Plotini deque ordine librorum eius libello. Bibl. Teubneriana. Lipsiae: in aedibus B. G. Teubneri. Bréhier, Émile. 1924-38. Plotin: Ennéades. 6 vols. in 7. Coll. Budé. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Pugliese Carratelli, Giovanni. 1946. Porfirio: Vita di Plotino ed ordine dei suoi libri. Napoli: G. Machiaroli. Faggin, Giuseppe. 1947-8. Plotino: Le Enneadi e Porfirio: Vita di Plotino. 3 vols. Milano: Istituto editoriale italiano. Rev. ed. 2000, Milano: Bompiani. Henry, Paul, and Hans-Rudolf Schwyzer. 1951-73. Plotini opera. (Editio maior.) 3 vols. Museum Lessianum Series Philosophica 33-5. Bruxelles: L’Édition Universelle and Paris: Desclée de Brouwer. ———. 1964-82. Plotini opera. (Editio minor.) 3 vols. OCT. Oxonii: e typographeo Clarendoniano.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysics of Eros in Plotinus, Proclus and the Pseudo-Dionysius
    This electronic thesis or dissertation has been downloaded from the King’s Research Portal at https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/ Neoplatonic Love The Metaphysics of Eros in Plotinus, Proclus and the Pseudo-Dionysius Vasilakis, Dimitrios Awarding institution: King's College London The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without proper acknowledgement. END USER LICENCE AGREEMENT Unless another licence is stated on the immediately following page this work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International licence. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ You are free to copy, distribute and transmit the work Under the following conditions: Attribution: You must attribute the work in the manner specified by the author (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Non Commercial: You may not use this work for commercial purposes. No Derivative Works - You may not alter, transform, or build upon this work. Any of these conditions can be waived if you receive permission from the author. Your fair dealings and other rights are in no way affected by the above. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 30. Sep. 2021 This electronic thesis or dissertation has been downloaded from the King’s Research Portal at https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/ Title: Neoplatonic Love: The Metaphysics of Eros in Plotinus, Proclus and the Pseudo-Dionysius Author: Dimitrios Vasilakis The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without proper acknowledgement.
    [Show full text]
  • An Exploration of the Symposium and Plato's Love Remy P
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2013 What's Love Got to Do with It? An Exploration of the Symposium and Plato's Love Remy P. Pinson Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Pinson, Remy P., "What's Love Got to Do with It? An Exploration of the Symposium and Plato's Love" (2013). CMC Senior Theses. Paper 740. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/740 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CLAREMONT MCKENNA COLLEGE What’s Love Got to Do with It? An Exploration of the Symposium and Plato’s Love SUBMITTED TO PROFESSOR SUZANNE OBDRZALEK AND DEAN NICHOLAS WARNER BY REMY PINSON For SENIOR THESIS FALL 2013 DECEMBER 2, 2013 Table of Contents Acknowledgements …………………………………………………………………………… ii Abstract ……………………………………………………………………………………….. iii 1. Introduction ……………………………………………………………………………. 1 2. Section One …………………………………………………………………………….. 5 3. Section Two …………………………………………………………………………… 15 4. Conclusion …………………………………………………………………………….. 22 Bibliography …………………………………………………………………………………... 24 Acknowledgements It is an onerous task, deciding who to thank. One must first decide how much help is worth acknowledging. The polite answer – and perhaps the right answer – would be to thank everyone for even the slightest bit of help received. But alas, if that were the case the list would be never-ending. I would need to thank strangers for the look I received in passing that lifted my spirits. I would need to thank Mr. Ryal for providing me with a computer lab to use. I would need to thank numerous people in the limited space I have here.
    [Show full text]
  • General Theories of Love
    01-Regan.qxd 10/30/02 4:44 PM Page 3 1 General Theories of Love Chapter Outline The Triangular Theory of Love Types of Love Relationship Measurement The Colors (Styles) of Love Primary and Secondary Love Styles Measurement Individual and Group Differences in Love Style The Prototype Approach: Mental Models of Love The Hierarchy of Love The Prototype of Love Summary hroughout history, scholars from a variety of disciplines have Tspeculated on the nature of love. For example, as early as 1886, the German physician and pioneering sexologist Richard von Krafft-Ebing (1886/1945) identified five types of love: true love, sentimental love, platonic love, friendship, and sensual love. Several decades later, psycho- therapist Albert Ellis (1954) proposed additional love varieties: “Love itself . includes many different types and degrees of affection, such as conjugal love, parental love, familial love, religious love, love of humanity, love of animals, love of things, self-love, sexual love, obsessive-compulsive love, etc.” (p. 101). 3 01-Regan.qxd 10/30/02 4:44 PM Page 4 4LOVE One of Ellis’s contemporaries, religious theoretician C. S. Lewis (1960/1988), devoted an entire book to a discussion of types of love. Drawing on earlier distinctions made by Greek philosophers, he pro- posed four main varieties. Affection (or Storge, pronounced “Stor-gay”) is based on familiarity and repeated contact and resembles the strong attachment seen between parents and children. This type of love is experienced for and by a wide variety of objects, including family members, pets, acquaintances, and lovers. Affectionate love has a “comfortable, quiet nature” (p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism
    Graeco-Latina Brunensia 25 / 2020 / 2 https://doi.org/10.5817/GLB2020-2-12 The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism José María Zamora Calvo (Autonomous University of Madrid) Abstract The stereotype of “Platonic love” that developed during the Renaissance implies a type of relationship, between two people of the opposite gender, which does not involve sexual activ- ity. A new examination of certain relevant texts by Neoplatonists such as Plotinus, Porphyry, / ARTICLES ČLÁNKY Hierocles, Hermias, Proclus and Olympiodorus, written during the period of Late Antiquity, establish that the question of sexuality is present in the very architecture of their systems, thus maintaining a coherent approach over time. “Mixed love”, tending towards the sexual union that enables the conception of children, is morally good. Through an exegesis of the Sympo- sium, Phaedrus and First Alcibiades, each of these Neoplatonic philosophers explores sexuality through the prisms of cosmology, ethics and political theory. Keywords sexuality; Neoplatonism; mixed love; Neoplatonic love; Neoplatonic ethic 163 José María Zamora Calvo The Status of Sexuality in Neoplatonism In the Life of Isidore, Damascius tells the story of the philosopher Theosebius (a disciple of Hierocles of Alexandria and an admirer of Epictetus),1 who was not able to have chil- dren and as a result, suggested to his wife that she should either swap her wedding ring for a chastity ring (i.e. become celibate), or marry another man. She chose a life of absti- nence, and so the couple lived out the days of their marriage (with the help of this “talis- man” (φυλακτήριον), which also acted as a “contraceptive”) without maintaining sexual relations (Fr.
    [Show full text]