Darwinism Renewed: Contemporary Studies of Plant Adaptation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Darwinism Renewed: Contemporary Studies of Plant Adaptation Forum EditorialBlackwellOxford,NPHNew0028-646X1469-8137©297410.1111/j.1469-8137.2009.02974.xJune0497???501???Commentary The 2009Phytologist Authors UK Publishing (2009). Ltd Journal compilation © New Phytologist (2009) Darwinism renewed: Co-evolutionary interactions contemporary studies of The interactions of plants with their pathogens, parasites and pollinators can generate reciprocal selection pressures and plant adaptation consequently a distinctive co-evolutionary process. L. G. Barrett et al. (this issue, pp. 513–529) analyze this process for the complex spectrum of associations between plants and their One hundred fifty years after On the origin of species was microbial pathogens. In contrast to the specific, highly virulent first published (Darwin, 1859), biologists continue to share pairwise interactions that have been emphasized to date in co- Darwin’s fascination with the adaptive traits of organisms, evolutionary models, they argue that host-pathogen associations and to theoretically and empirically expand his initial form a continuum from specialists to generalists, with widely formulation of natural selection as the process that shapes varying fitness effects (and therefore selective outcomes) those traits. In this special issue of the journal, New Phytologist depending on environmental and genetic factors that jointly recognizes this continuing legacy by bringing together current influence the expression of both microbial virulence and host ideas and findings about plant adaptation from an accom- resistance genes. These factors can interact at several levels to plished, multi-national group of researchers studying a wide affect selection pressures, for instance in the case of co-infection array of plant systems. Many of these studies make use of the by multiple pathogens that interact within the host to modify formidable set of research tools now available to examine the its defence gene expression. Godsoe et al. (pp. 589–599) focus molecular and genomic bases of adaptive traits and their on a very different aspect of plant co-evolutionary dynamics, selective dynamics, and these tools have certainly provided a well-studied pollination mutualism. Using GIS-based niche critical insights. But the most exciting aspect of contemporary modeling and well-resolved phylogenetic data, they determine work on adaptation is not these new techniques per se, but that the specialized biotic interaction between Yucca brevifolia rather the way researchers are combining diverse tools in and its moth pollinators, rather than climatic variables, have robust, richly informative interdisciplinary approaches. led to evolutionary divergence in this system. Genomic data from model organisms are being used in new ways to inform studies of naturally evolved systems, and a Floral and mating system evolution rigorous phylogenetic context has become standard across sub-disciplines to refine population, species, and higher-level Floral features such as pollination syndromes and organ place- comparisons. ment provide clear examples of adaptation. Harder & Johnson The studies presented here address questions at all levels (pp. 530–545) comprehensively review evidence as to whether from the molecular to the macroevolutionary, drawing on floral and inflorescence traits fit a Darwinian model of gradual, information ranging from transgenic functional assays, tran- consistent selective change. Although data from manipulation scriptomics, and quantitative genetics trait matrices to GIS- experiments generally confirm that these ‘beautiful contrivances’ based niche modeling, field explant studies of recombinant are indeed adaptations that evolved for pollen transfer, the inbred lines, and distribution data from herbarium sheets. results of phenotypic selection analyses indicate that directional This new work makes clear how these sophisticated interdis- selection on these traits may be relatively weak and inconsistent ciplinary approaches are illuminating some of the most fund- in natural populations. Instead, adaptive floral features may amental and long-standing questions about plant adaptation be shaped largely during episodes of strong selection rather and the process of selective change. It also reflects an increas- than by continual gradual selection as Darwin envisioned. This ing awareness that the study of adaptation has important meta-analysis reveals limits to phenotypic selection analysis bearing on biodiversity conservation, invasion biology, and as a definitive test for adaptive function. Armbruster et al. potential constraints on adaptive evolution in the face of (pp. 600–617) pose a complementary question about the rapidly changing environments. Here, a brief overview of the evolution of floral adaptations: does floral diversification at feature points to some of the key findings with respect to the macroevolutionary level reflect adaptation to pollinators? several areas of shared focus: co-evolutionary interactions; They determine an optimal-fitness ‘adaptive surface’ relating floral and mating system evolution; geographic patterns of pollination performance to anther and stigma position, and adaptive evolution; genetic architecture of adaptation; and test against this prediction the realized distribution of floral evolution of functional traits. traits in three phylogenetically diverse genera. Their analysis © The Author (2009) New Phytologist (2009) 183: 497–501 497 Journal compilation © New Phytologist (2009) www.newphytologist.org 497 498 Forum Editorial reveals clade-specific departures from the optimum reflecting plasticity and adaptive divergence of populations. (The paper both lack of floral integration and conflicting selection pressures is graciously dedicated to the late Fakhri A. Bazzaz, whose for other outcrossing features. Fenster et al. (pp. 502–506) draw work deeply enhanced our understanding of plasticity and its our attention to vertical versus horizontal floral orientation as ecological implications.) Levin reviews the evolutionary ecology a significant influence on pollinator effectiveness that has been literature to establish that individuals encountering novel largely ignored for the past century. Their initial dataset shows conditions often displace the timing of flowering. He argues that hummingbird approach behavior and floral contact vary that, when a population colonizes a new habitat, such an in response to differently oriented artificial flowers, a result environmentally-induced phenological shift will lead to that argues for future pollination studies to include this aspect temporally assortative mating that effectively isolates the of floral adaptation. colonizing population from its source. As a result, phenological Gender expression and the evolution of plant mating systems plasticity will facilitate local adaptation to the new habitat that have long been a focus of theoretical and empirical interest. would otherwise be impeded by gene flow from the source S. C. H. Barrett et al. (pp. 546–556) present a well-developed population. Along with intriguing implications for ecological case study on the evolution of selfing based on phylogeo- range expansion, this paper adds a new dimension to contem- graphic analysis of multilocus nuclear DNA sequences (SNPs) porary ideas about the possible role of individual plasticity in from populations sampled across the Neotropical range of the evolutionary diversification. sexually polymorphic species Eichornia paniculata. Their data Questions of dispersal and range also hold immediate reveal multiple independent transitions from outcrossing to implications for extinction risks as natural habitats are increas- selfing in populations of this colonizing species. Preliminary ingly disrupted. For instance, effective dispersal can contribute results also suggest that both genetic factors and environmental to species persistence in fragmented landscapes by allowing stress contribute to developmental instability in the early stages re-colonization of habitat patches and outcrossing. However, if of selfing, which may facilitate this evolutionary transition. habitat fragmentation in itself imposes selection for reduced Randle et al. (pp. 618–629) investigate the ecological impli- dispersal ability (as occurs in island populations), this evolu- cations of self-fertilization: does selfing promote colonization tionary feedback will worsen its negative impact on species’ and hence range expansion, or does the lower genetic diversity distributions and persistence. Riba et al. (pp. 667–677) find a of selfing species instead restrict range size? They test the rela- negative correlation between the degree of landscape fragmen- tion of selfing ability to size of realized geographic range in tation and achene dispersal ability at both local and regional Collinsia, combining a phylogenetically controlled species-pair spatial scales in the wind-dispersed European herb Mycelis comparison with precise measures of floral form and self- muralis. Together with a common garden experiment con- fertilization activity. This elegant study establishes empirically firming a partial genetic basis to this trait, these results indicate that species with the highest proficiency for autonomous selfing that fragmentation may have negative evolutionary as well as also have significantly larger ranges, linking an individual ecological consequences. reproductive trait with ecological distribution including, Geographic patterns of variation can also provide insights as predicted by Herbert Baker, the spread
Recommended publications
  • Aristotle's Essentialism Revisited
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 4-15-2013 Accommodating Species Evolution: Aristotle’s Essentialism Revisited Yin Zhang University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Zhang, Yin, "Accommodating Species Evolution: Aristotle’s Essentialism Revisited" (2013). Theses. 192. http://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/192 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Accommodating Species Evolution: Aristotle’s Essentialism Revisited by Yin Zhang B.A., Philosophy, Peking University, 2010 A Thesis Submitted to The Graduate School at the University of Missouri – St. Louis in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts in Philosophy May 2013 Advisory Committee Jon D. McGinnis, Ph.D. Chairperson Andrew G. Black, Ph.D. Berit O. Brogaard, Ph.D. Zhang, Yin, UMSL, 2013, p. i PREFACE In the fall of 2008 when I was a junior at Peking University, I attended a lecture series directed by Dr. Melville Y. Stewart on science and religion. Guest lecturers Dr. Alvin Plantinga, Dr. William L. Craig and Dr. Bruce Reichenbach have influenced my thinking on the relation between evolution and faith. In the fall of 2010 when I became a one-year visiting student at Calvin College in Michigan, I took a seminar directed by Dr. Kelly J. Clark on evolution and ethics. Having thought about evolution/faith and evolution/ethics, I signed up for Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting the History of Evolutionary Biology Through a Kuhnian Prism: Sense Or Nonsense?
    Interpreting the History of Evolutionary Biology through a Kuhnian Prism: Sense or Nonsense? Koen B. Tanghe Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Universiteit Gent, Belgium Lieven Pauwels Department of Criminology, Criminal Law and Social Law, Universiteit Gent, Belgium Alexis De Tiège Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Universiteit Gent, Belgium Johan Braeckman Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Universiteit Gent, Belgium Traditionally, Thomas S. Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) is largely identified with his analysis of the structure of scientific revo- lutions. Here, we contribute to a minority tradition in the Kuhn literature by interpreting the history of evolutionary biology through the prism of the entire historical developmental model of sciences that he elaborates in The Structure. This research not only reveals a certain match between this model and the history of evolutionary biology but, more importantly, also sheds new light on several episodes in that history, and particularly on the publication of Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of Species (1859), the construction of the modern evolutionary synthesis, the chronic discontent with it, and the latest expression of that discon- tent, called the extended evolutionary synthesis. Lastly, we also explain why this kind of analysis hasn’t been done before. We would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their constructive review, as well as the editor Alex Levine. Perspectives on Science 2021, vol. 29, no. 1 © 2021 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00359 1 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00359 by guest on 30 September 2021 2 Evolutionary Biology through a Kuhnian Prism 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Origins of the Myth of Social Darwinism: the Ambiguous Legacy of Richard Hofstadter’S Social Darwinism in American Thought
    Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 71 (2009) 37–51 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jebo Origins of the myth of social Darwinism: The ambiguous legacy of Richard Hofstadter’s Social Darwinism in American Thought Thomas C. Leonard Department of Economics, Princeton University, Fisher Hall, Princeton, NJ 08544, United States article info abstract Article history: The term “social Darwinism” owes its currency and many of its connotations to Richard Received 19 February 2007 Hofstadter’s influential Social Darwinism in American Thought, 1860–1915 (SDAT). The post- Accepted 8 November 2007 SDAT meanings of “social Darwinism” are the product of an unresolved Whiggish tension in Available online 6 March 2009 SDAT: Hofstadter championed economic reform over free markets, but he also condemned biology in social science, this while many progressive social scientists surveyed in SDAT JEL classification: offered biological justifications for economic reform. As a consequence, there are, in effect, B15 B31 two Hofstadters in SDAT. The first (call him Hofstadter1) disparaged as “social Darwinism” B12 biological justification of laissez-faire, for this was, in his view, doubly wrong. The sec- ond Hofstadter (call him Hofstadter2) documented, however incompletely, the underside Keywords: of progressive reform: racism, eugenics and imperialism, and even devised a term for it, Social Darwinism “Darwinian collectivism.” This essay documents and explains Hofstadter’s ambivalence in Evolution SDAT, especially where, as with Progressive Era eugenics, the “two Hofstadters” were at odds Progressive Era economics Malthus with each other. It explores the historiographic and semantic consequences of Hofstadter’s ambivalence, including its connection with the Left’s longstanding mistrust of Darwinism as apology for Malthusian political economy.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwin's Influence on Mendel: Evidence from a New Translation Of
    | PERSPECTIVES Darwin’sInfluence on Mendel: Evidence from a New Translation of Mendel’s Paper Daniel J. Fairbanks*,1 and Scott Abbott† *Department of Biology and †Department of Integrated Studies, Utah Valley University, Orem, Utah 84058 ORCID ID: 0000-0001-7422-0549 (D.J.F.) ABSTRACT Gregor Mendel’s classic paper, Versuche über Pflanzen-Hybriden (Experiments on Plant Hybrids), was published in 1866, hence 2016 is its sesquicentennial. Mendel completed his experiments in 1863 and shortly thereafter began compiling the results and writing his paper, which he presented in meetings of the Natural Science Society in Brünn in February and March of 1865. Mendel owned a personal copy of Darwin’s Origin of Species, a German translation published in 1863, and it contains his marginalia. Its publication date indicates that Mendel’s study of Darwin’s book could have had no influence while he was conducting his experiments but its publication date coincided with the period of time when he was preparing his paper, making it possible that Darwin’s writings influenced Mendel’s interpretations and theory. Based on this premise, we prepared a Darwinized English translation of Mendel’s paper by comparing German terms Mendel employed with the same terms in the German translation of Origin of Species in his possession, then using Darwin’s counterpart English words and phrases as much as possible in our translation. We found a substantially higher use of these terms in the final two (10th and 11th) sections of Mendel’s paper, particularly in one key paragraph, where Mendel reflects on evolutionary issues, providing strong evidence of Darwin’sinfluence on Mendel.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwinism and the Law: Can Non-Naturalistic Scientific Theories Survive Constitutional Challenge?
    DARWINISM AND THE LAW: CAN NON-NATURALISTIC SCIENTIFIC THEORIES SURVIVE CONSTITUTIONAL CHALLENGE? H. Wayne House* The entrance of Charles Darwin’s1 The Origin of Species2 changed the world. This is not because belief in evolution was a new and exciting theory unconsidered before this time, for indeed a variation of the view existed in many ancient cultures.3 In addition, several scientists already *H. Wayne House is distinguished professor of biblical studies and apologetics at Faith Seminary, Tacoma, WA, and a professor of law at Trinity Law School, California campus, of Trinity International University. He holds a J.D. from Regent University School of Law; Th.D., Concordia Seminary, St. Louis; M.Div., Th.M., Western Seminary; M.A., Abilene Christian University; B.A., Hardin-Simmons University. He has published over twenty books and scores of articles in the subjects of theology, law and ethics. I wish to thank James Stambaugh, librarian at Michigan Theological Seminary, for providing documentation. Also much appreciation to Eddie Colanter, Eric Rice, and Sean Choi, for their assistance in checking footnotes and/or providing sources for this article. 1 Charles Robert Darwin (1809-1882) was a British scientist who laid the foundation for modern evolutionary theory through his concept of the development of all forms of life through the gradual process of natural selection. He was born in Shrewsbury, Shropshire, England on February 12, 1809. Darwin originally went to study medicine at the University of Edinburgh but then dropped out in 1827 to prepare for becoming a clergyman in the Church of England by studying at the University of Cambridge.
    [Show full text]
  • “The Natural History of My Inward Self”: Sensing Character in George Eliot’S Impressions of Theophrastus Such S
    129.1 ] “The Natural History of My Inward Self”: Sensing Character in George Eliot’s Impressions of Theophrastus Such s. pearl brilmyer Attempts at description are stupid: who can all at once describe a human be- ing? Even when he is presented to us we only begin that knowledge of his ap- pearance which must be completed by innumerable impressions under differing circumstances. We recognize the alphabet; we are not sure of the language. —George Eliot, Daniel Deronda (160) ILL NOT A TINY spECK VERY CLOSE TO OUR VISION BLOT Out “ the glory of the world, and leave only a margin by Wwhich we see the blot?” asks the narrator of Middle- march (1874). Indeed it will, comes the answer, and in this regard there is “no speck so troublesome as self” (392). Metaphors of sen- sory failure in Eliot seem to capture the self- absorption of characters who discount empirical knowledge in favor of their own straitened worldviews. In Middlemarch Casaubon’s shortsightedness is tied to his egocentric attempts to “understand the higher inward life” (21). Dorothea, who marries Casaubon in an effort to attain this kind of understanding, is correspondingly “unable to see” the right con- clusion (29), can “never see what is quite plain” (34), “does not see things” (52), and is “no judge” of visual art, which is composed in “a language [she does] not understand” (73). When Eliot describes obstacles to sensation, however, she does more than provide a critique of egoism in which the corrective is sympathetic exchange. More basically, Eliot’s fascination with the S.
    [Show full text]
  • Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design
    Signature in the Cell DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design Stephen C. Meyer 1 DNA, Darwin, and the Appearance of Design When James Watson and Francis Crick elucidated the structure of DNA in 1953, they solved one mystery, but created another. For almost a hundred years after the publication of On the Origin of Species by Charles Darwin in 1859, the science of biology rested secure in the knowledge that it had explained one of humankind’s most enduring enigmas. From ancient times, observers of living organisms had noted that living things display organized structures that give the appearance of having been deliberately arranged or designed for a purpose, for example, the elegant form and protective covering of the coiled nautilus, the interdependent parts of the eye, the interlocking bones, muscles, and feathers of a bird wing. For the most part, observers took these appearances of design as genuine. Observations of such structures led thinkers as diverse as Plato and Aristotle, Cicero and Maimonides, Boyle and Newton to conclude that behind the exquisite structures of the living world was a designing intelligence. As Newton wrote in his masterpiece The Opticks: “How came the Bodies of Animals to be contrived with so much Art, and for what ends were their several parts? Was the Eye contrived without Skill in Opticks, and the Ear without Knowledge of Sounds?…And these things being rightly dispatch’d, does it not appear from Phænomena that there is a Being incorporeal, living, intelligent…?”1 But with the advent of Darwin, modern science seemed able to explain this appearance of design as the product of a purely undirected process.
    [Show full text]
  • The Physics–Biology Continuum Refutes Darwinism: Evolution Is Directed by the Homeostasis-Dependent Bidirectional Relation B
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 6 January 2021 1 The Physics–Biology Continuum Refutes Darwinism: Evolution is Directed 2 by the Homeostasis-Dependent Bidirectional Relation between Genome and Phenotype 3 Didier Auboeuf 4 ENS de Lyon, Univ Claude Bernard, CNRS UMR 5239, INSERM U1210, Laboratory of Biology and Modelling of the 5 Cell, 46 Allée d'Italie, Site Jacques Monod, F-69007, Lyon, France; Mail: [email protected] 6 Abstract 7 The physics–biology continuum relies on the fact that life emerged from prebiotic molecules. Here, I argue that 8 life emerged from the physical coupling between the synthesis of nucleic acids and the synthesis of amino acid 9 polymers. Owing to this physical coupling, amino acid polymers (or proto-phenotypes) maintained the 10 physicochemical parameter equilibria (proto-homeostasis) in the immediate environment of their encoding 11 nucleic acids (or proto-genomes). This protected the proto-genome physicochemical integrity (i.e., atomic 12 composition) from environmental physicochemical stresses, and therefore increased the probability of 13 reproducing the proto-genome without variation. From there, genomes evolved depending on the biological 14 activities they generated in response to environmental fluctuations. Thus, a genome generating an internal 15 environment whose physicochemical parameters guarantee homeostasis and genome integrity has a higher 16 probability to be reproduced without variation and therefore to reproduce the same phenotype in offspring. 17 Otherwise, the genome is modified by the imbalances of the internal physicochemical parameters it generates, 18 until new emerging biological activities maintain homeostasis. In sum, evolution depends on feedforward and 19 feedback loops between genome and phenotype, since the internal physicochemical conditions that a genome 20 generates in response to environmental fluctuations in turn either guarantee the stability or direct the variation 21 of the genome.
    [Show full text]
  • Asa Gray and Charles Darwin: Corresponding Naturalists
    Asa Gray and Charles Darwin: Corresponding Naturalists The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Browne, Janet. 2010. Asa Gray and Charles Darwin: Corresponding naturalists. Harvard Papers in Botany 15(2): 209-220. Published Version doi:10.3100/025.015.0204 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:10459023 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Open Access Policy Articles, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#OAP 1 Asa Gray and Charles Darwin: Corresponding Naturalist Janet Browne Department of the History of Science Harvard University Science Center 371 Cambridge MA 02138 Abstract Recent work on the rise of science in the nineteenth century has encouraged historians to look again at the role of correspondence. Naturalists relied extensively on this form of contact and correspondence was a major element in generating a community of experts who agreed on what comprised valid knowledge. As a leading figure in the development of North American botany, Asa Gray found that letters with botanists and collectors all over the world greatly expanded his areas of influence. Lasting friendships were made and the collections at Harvard were materially advanced. Letters also brought Gray into contact with Charles Darwin, who became a close friend. After publication of Darwin’s Origin of Species Gray defended Darwinism in the United States and corresponded with him about evolution.
    [Show full text]
  • Darwinism, Mendelism, and Biometrics
    Paper Number: 300494 History of Science and Statistical Education: Examples from Fisherian and Pearsonian schools Paper presented at the 2004 Joint Statistical Meeting, Toronto, Canada Chong Ho Yu, Ph.D. [email protected] Website: http://www.creative-wisdom/pub/pub.html Abstract Many students share a popular misconception that statistics is a subject-free methodology derived from invariant and timeless mathematical axioms. It is proposed that statistical education should include the aspect of history/philosophy of science. This article will discuss how statistical methods developed by Karl Pearson and R. A. Fisher are driven by biological themes and philosophical presumptions. Pearson was pre-occupied with between-group speciation and thus his statistical methods, such as the Chi-squared test, are categorical in nature. On the other hand, variation within species plays a central role in Fisher’s framework, and therefore, Fisher’s approach, such as partitioning variance, is concerned with interval-scaled data. In addition, Fisher adopted a philosophy of embracing causal inferences and theoretical entities, such as infinite population and gene, while Pearson disregarded unobservable and insisted upon description of the data at hand. These differences lead to the subsequent divergence of two hypothesis testing methods, developed by R. A. Fisher and Neyman/E .S. Pearson, son of Karl Pearson, respectively. Students will appreciate the meanings of Fisherian and Pearsonian methods if they are exposed to history and philosophy of science. R. A. Fisher and Karl Pearson are considered the two most important figures in statistics as well as influential scholars in evolutionary biology and genetics. While statistical procedures are widely applied by scholars in various disciplines, including the natural and social sciences, statistics is mistakenly regarded as Fisher and Pearson 2 a subject-neutral methodology.
    [Show full text]
  • Modernizing George Eliot: the Writer As Artist, Intellectual, Proto-Modernist, Cultural Critic
    Newton, K.M. "Eliot's Critique of Darwinism." Modernizing George Eliot: The Writer as Artist, Intellectual, Proto-Modernist, Cultural Critic. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2010. 7–26. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 25 Sep. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781849665155.ch-001>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 25 September 2021, 23:20 UTC. Copyright © K.M. Newton 2011. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 1 Eliot’s Critique of Darwinism I Darwin’s theory of natural selection was the most explosive idea to emerge in the modern era. Not only did it undermine fundamentally such powerful justifi cations for religious belief as the argument from design, but secular or humanist alternatives to religion were equally threatened since the human species was no longer privileged and was the product of a struggle for existence that not only had no ethical dimension but also such a dimension would have been positively disadvantageous in that struggle. Also concepts of order that shape human thought and perception such as purpose or proportionality in the relation between cause and effect were called into question by Darwinian theory. Darwinism was of course roundly condemned from many different points of view and that continues, but most of the attacks on it have been along the lines that it could not be true because if it were life would be meaningless or there would be no justifi cation for morality. 1 Even defenders of it, such as Social Darwinists, could do so only by projecting teleology onto the theory and rejecting the idea that chance played a signifi cant role in which species survive, the ‘fi ttest’ being identifi ed with the best and so deserving to thrive in the struggle for existence.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Darwinism Science and Myth in Anglo-American Social Thought
    Social Darwinism Science and Myth in Anglo-American Social Thought 'With a new preface ROBERT C. BANNISTER Temple University Press Philadelphia 1979 Contents Acknowledgments ix Introduction: The Idea of Social Darwinism 3 1 The Scientific Background 14 2 Hushing Up Death 34 3 Philanthropic Energy and Philosophic Calm 57 4 Amending the Faith 79 5 William Graham Sumner 97 6 The Survival of the Fittest Is Our Doctrine 114 7 Neo-Darwinism and the Crisis of the 1890s 137 8 A Pigeon Fanciers' Polity 164 9 The Scaffolding of Progress 180 10 The Nietzsche Vogue 201 11 Beyond the Battle: The Literary Naturalists 212 12 Imperialism and the Warriar Critique 226 Epilogue: From Histrionics to History 245 Notes 252 Index 285 Preface 1. Social Darwinism: Science and Myth asks readers to do two things more difficult than they may initially appear: first, to recon­ sider debates over social and public policy issues from the 1870s through the 1910s with an openness and sensitivity they would wish for their own statements; and second, to reconceptualize the issue of social Darwinism 1 so as to ask, not what individuals or groups were social Darwinists, but how the label itself functioned in debates in the six decades following the publication of the Origin of Species. A reconsideration alone yields two conclusions, both important al­ though neither ground-breaking. One is that Gilded Age defenders of free market mechanisms, individualism, and laissez faire (so-called "conservatives" but in reality liberals by mid-nineteenth-century stan­ dards) rarely laced their prose with appeals to Darwinism and virtually never in the way described in conventional accounts.
    [Show full text]