The Contested Legacy of Ayn Rand
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Ayn Rand? Ayn Rand Ayn
Who Is Ayn Rand? Ayn Rand Few 20th century intellectuals have been as influential—and controversial— as the novelist and philosopher Ayn Rand. Her thinking still has a profound impact, particularly on those who come to it through her novels, Atlas Shrugged and The Fountainhead—with their core messages of individualism, self-worth, and the right to live without the impositions of others. Although ignored or scorned by some academics, traditionalists, pro- gressives, and public intellectuals, her thought remains a major influence on Ayn Rand many of the world’s leading legislators, policy advisers, economists, entre- preneurs, and investors. INTRODUCTION AN Why does Rand’s work remain so influential? Ayn Rand: An Introduction illuminates Rand’s importance, detailing her understanding of reality and human nature, and explores the ongoing fascination with and debates about her conclusions on knowledge, morality, politics, economics, government, AN INTRODUCTION public issues, aesthetics and literature. The book also places these in the context of her life and times, showing how revolutionary they were, and how they have influenced and continue to impact public policy debates. EAMONN BUTLER is director of the Adam Smith Institute, a leading think tank in the UK. He holds degrees in economics and psychology, a PhD in philosophy, and an honorary DLitt. A former winner of the Freedom Medal of Freedom’s Foundation at Valley Forge and the UK National Free Enterprise Award, Eamonn is currently secretary of the Mont Pelerin Society. Butler is the author of many books, including introductions on the pioneering economists Eamonn Butler Adam Smith, Milton Friedman, F. -
Reason Papers No
Editor: Tibor R. Machan Managbig Editor: Mark Turiano Executive Editor: Gregory R. Johnson Associate Editors: Walter Block/ Economics Douglas J. Den Uyl/ Philosophy Kelly Dean Jolley/ Philosophy Leonard Liggio/ History Eric Mack/ Philosophy John D. McCallie/ Economics H. Joachim Maitre/ Interrzational Relations Ralph Raico/ History Lynn Scarlett/ Political Science Advisory Board: D. T. Armentanol University ofHartford Yale Brazen/ University of Chicago Nicholas Capaldi/ Urziversity of Tulsa R.L. Cunningham/ University of Sun Francisco John Hospers/ Univmity of Southern Cdlifornia Isreal M. Kirzner/ Nm York University Kenneth G. Luce y/ SUNY College. Fredonia Fred D. Miller, Jr./ Bowling Green State University Herbert Morris/ University of California, Los Angeles Clifton Perry/ Auburn University Paul Craig Roberts/ Georgetown University Morton L. Schagrin/ SUNY College, Fredonia Thomas S. Szasz/ SUNYMedical Center, Syracuse Articles On the Fit between Egoism and Rights ......................Eric Mack 3 Resolving the Tension in Aristotle's Ethic: The Balance Between Naturalism and Responsibility ........ David E. W. Fenner 22 The Irrationality of the Extended Order: The Fatal Conceit of F. A . Hayek ....... Larry ]. Sechrest 38 Special Forum: Rand & Philosophy A Philosopher for the New Millennium? ........ Fred D. Miller. Jr. On Rand as Philosopher ............................... Dough J. Den Uyl Rand and Philosophy (and Capitalism) ..... Douglas B. Rasmussen Ayn Rand's Contribution to Philosophy ....... Neera K. Badhwar What is Living in the Philosophy of AynRand ... Lester H . Hunt Rand and Objectivity ............................................... David Kelly Rand Revisited ...................................... .. ................]. Roger Lee Ayn Rand's Philosophical Significance .................... John Hospers Ayn Rand as Moral & Political Philosopher ..........la n Narveson Discussion Notes Kamhi and Torres on Meaning in Ayn Rand's Esthetics .............................................. -
Libertarians in Bush's World
ESSAY ON LIBERTY+ LIBERTARIANS IN BUSH’S WORLD Todd Seavey* Imagine ordinary, non-ideological people hearing about an obscure politi- cal sect called libertarianism, which emphasizes self-ownership, property rights, resistance to tyranny and violence, the reduction of taxation and regulation, control over one’s own investments, and the de-emphasizing of litigation as a primary means of dispute resolution. Since this philosophy has very few adherents in the general population and is very much a minority position among intellectuals, one might expect proponents of the creed to count themselves lucky, given the likely alternatives, if the president of the country in which most of them live increasingly emphasized the themes of freedom and ownership in his major speeches; toppled brutal totalitarian regimes in two countries while hounding democracy-hating theocratic terrorists around the globe; cut taxes (despite howls even from some in the free-market camp that the cuts were too deep); called for simplification of the tax code; appointed relatively industry-friendly officials to major regulatory bodies such as the Environmental Protection Agency and the Food and Drug Administration despite frequent criti- cism by the media; proposed partially privatizing Social Security (America’s largest socialist boondoggle but one long regarded as sacrosanct by political analysts); and pushed tort reform to combat the chilling effect of lawsuits on doctors and manu- facturers. + Essays on Liberty is a continuing series of the Journal of Law & Liberty, dedicated to explorations of freedom and law from perspectives outside the legal academy. * Director of Publications for the American Council on Science and Health (ACSH.org, HealthFactsAnd- Fears.com), which does not necessarily endorse the views expressed here. -
Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: a Positive Contribution?
Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Response to Eyal Mozes, “Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution?” Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College Irfan Khawaja Felician College 1. Introduction In this discussion note, we respond to Eyal Mozes’s critique of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics via his criticism of Carrie-Ann Biondi’s review of that book in Reason Papers.1 We take issue with Mozes’s discussion of Ayn Rand’s non-conflicts-of-interest principle (NCIP) along with his discussion of the nature of moral virtue. We end by taking issue with his inappropriately moralized conception of philosophical discourse. Since we agree with many (though not all) of Mozes’s claims about emergencies and the scope of morality, we leave those topics undiscussed. 2. Conflicts of Interest Mozes offers two objections to Smith’s discussion of the NCIP: For any book that purports to be a presentation of Rand’s normative ethics, a crucial part of its task is to give an elaborate explanation and defense of Rand’s no-conflicts-of-interest-principle, filling in the details of Rand’s own cursory discussion. In evaluating such a book, I don’t think there’s any question more important than how well it succeeds in explaining and defending this principle. Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics disgracefully fails in this task.2 We reject every element of this criticism. 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), hereafter ARNE; Carrie-Ann Biondi, “Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Reason Papers 30 (Fall 2008), pp. -
John Dewey, Maria Montessori, and Objectivist Educational Philosophy During the Postwar Years
73 Historical Studies in Education / Revue d’histoire de l’éducation ARTICLES / ARTICLES “The Ayn Rand School for Tots”: John Dewey, Maria Montessori, and Objectivist Educational Philosophy during the Postwar Years Jason Reid ABSTRACT Objectivism, the libertarian philosophy established by Ayn Rand during the postwar years, has attracted a great deal of attention from philosophers, political scientists, economists, and English professors alike in recent years, but has not received much notice from historians with an interest in education. This article will address that problem by discussing how Rand and her followers established a philosophy of education during the 1960s and 1970s that was based, in part, on vilifying the so-called collectivist ideas of John Dewey and lionizing the so-called individualist ideas of Maria Montessori. Unfortunately, the narrative that emerged during this time seriously misrepresented the ideas of both Dewey and Montessori, resulting in a some- what distorted view of both educators. RÉSUMÉ L’objectivisme, philosophie libertaire conçue par Ayn Rand dans la période de l’après-guerre, a suscitée beaucoup d’attention de la part des philosophes, politologues, économistes et profes- seurs de littérature anglaise, mais rien de tel chez les historiens de l’éducation. Cet article cor- rige cette lacune, en montrant comment durant les années 1960 et 1970 Rand et ses partisans ont établi une philosophie de l’éducation qui s’appuyait, en partie, sur la diffamation des idées prétendues collectivistes de John Dewey et l’idolâtrie de l’individualisme de Maria Montessori. Malheureusement, leurs travaux ont donné une fausse image des idées de Dewey et Montessori et conséquemment ont déformé les théories ces deux éducateurs. -
A Reply to Tibor Machan
LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 2, ART. NO. 9 (2010) WHEN IS A MONOPOLY NOT A MONOPOLY? A REPLY TO TIBOR MACHAN * NICHOLAS DYKES IN A LENGTHY FOOTNOTE to his essay “Reconciling Anarchism and Minarchism”1 (henceforth RAM) Tibor Machan accuses me of engaging in equivocation, and also of psychologising, in my essay “The Facts of Reality: Logic and History in Objectivist Debates about Government”2 (henceforth TFOR). Machan writes: … Dykes doesn’t seem to realise that monopoly in the use of retaliatory force is not the same as a legal or coercive monopoly in that use. He persists in this equivocation. Yet, one can have a monopoly that comes about naturally, because it is freely granted to one by people—as, say, they effectively granted the Beatles monopoly status in rock music or Fred Astaire in dancing or IBM in computers and Microsoft in software … without keeping anyone out by force. Furthermore, if people freely select a group of specialists to protect them by way of a long-term binding contract [or compact] that’s not to establish an objectionable, coercive monopoly, merely an exclusive but binding relationship …. It is along such lines that Rand’s notion of the “monopoly” of retaliatory force needs to be understood (RAM 61). Machan adds further on that equivocation is a “serious flaw” in my essay. To begin with, let’s be clear about what the term ‘equivocation’ means. I hardly need to point out that it is a fallacy in logic, one which involves *Nicholas Dykes ([email protected]), a British-Canadian writer currently living in England, is author of Old Nick’s Guide to Happiness: A Philosophical Novel (Ledbury, UK: Lathé Biosas Publishing, 2008). -
Objectivist Calendar, P
TABLE OF CONTENTS VOLUME 1-JANUARY TO DECEMBER, 1962 Books: NINETY-THREE by Victor Hugo, reviewed by Ayn Rand. THE GIRL HUNTERS by Mickey Spillane, reviewed by Ayn Rand. January LA.D. Does man possess instincts?-by Nathaniel Branden. War and Peace-by Ayn Rand. Choose Your Issues-by Ayn Rand. "Through Your Most Grievous Fault" -by Ayn Rand. Books: PLANNED CHAOS by Ludwig von Mises, reviewed by Barbara Branden. November Intellectual Ammunition Department: Reason and Emotion - by Nathaniel Branden. Social Metaphysics-by Nathaniel Branden. The Crisis Over Berlin-by Alan Greenspan. Books: EAST MINUS WEST = ZERO by Werner Keller, reviewed by Edith Efron. February The Esthetic Vacuum of Our Age-by Ayn Rand. Women and the Industrial Revolution-by Robert Hessen. Antitrust: The Rule of Unreason-by Ayn Rand. Books: ECONOMICS IN ONE LESSON by Henry Hazlitt, reviewed by December Robert Hessen. LA.D. Ethical hedonism-by Leonard Peikoff. The Monument Builders-by Ayn Rand. LA.D. Individual rights versus society-by Nathaniel Branden. Books: THE ROOSEVELT MYTH by John T. Flynn, reviewed by LA.D. Property rights-by Nathaniel Branden. Barbara Branden. LA.D. The obligations of parents and children-by Nathaniel March Branden. "Have Gun, Wi/J Nudge"-by Ayn Rand. Books: PROSPERITY THROUGH FREEDOM by Lawrence Fertig, re VOLUME 2 -JANUARY TO DECEMBER, 1963 viewed by Edith Efron. LA.D. Capitalism and religion-by Barbara Branden. LA.D. The psychological meaning of man's "need" of approval January by Nathaniel Branden. Collectivized Ethics-by Ayn Rand. April "The Stolen Concept" -by Nathaniel Branden. LA.D. Capital punishment-by Nathaniel Branden. -
A VETERAN RECONNOITERS AYN RAND's PHILOSOPHY Robert L
A VETERAN RECONNOITERS AYN RAND’S PHILOSOPHY Robert L. Campbell Ayn Rand Tibor R. Machan New York: Peter Lang, 1999 xii + 163 pp., index Tibor Machan’s new book is the latest sign of accelerated growth in the academic coverage of Ayn Rand’s philosophy. Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand, edited by Mimi Reisel Gladstein and Chris Matthew Sciabarra, has joined a series of volumes on Plato, Hegel, and Sartre, among others. Douglas Den Uyl’s monograph, The Fountainhead: An American Novel, in the Twayne’s Masterworks series, sits alongside critical essays on Daisy Miller and War and Peace. Now Machan’s volume takes position number 5 in a series titled “Masterworks in the Western Tradition.” It is intended as an overview and introduction to Rand’s philosophical system. Machan was eminently prepared to write this book. He has been actively promoting Randian ideas since the late 1960’s. Because he was excommunicated during the days of the Nathaniel Branden Institute for asking the wrong questions, he never got close to Rand’s inner circle and has never had to shoulder the weight of Objectivist orthodoxy. Along with Robert Poole and Manuel Klausner, he took over a new, obscure magazine called Reason in 1969 and nurtured it into a cultural force. He has published in every outlet from the academic philosophy journals to the dittoed page allotments of Libertarian Connection to the editorial columns of the daily newspapers; his output of books has grown especially prodigious over the past decade. Readers who know a little of Machan’s previous work will recognize this presentation of Rand as his most recent contribution to a continuing conversation. -
L:~. · : · Pa~E·2
. r·~ \ . " • • · ....... 1... .- ; ..... Pa e 1 ' . ._. •'; t Ill • : • ., 'Y • It a, lftt_~,f , "• , , t •~<r.~'J. ·-•~~~,-•Jff ••1 ,, •••, ... ' .,.• ••••, ,r ,_.,,I... l:~... ·, . , ......:.. ·. .. Pa~e·2 ,,.. ,r• • J •ir ~ , ,'f,' • 'to\ .,. ~-.,: .~ . ~ ,/_!;,: ,,, '11,,l ~ ,;. ' , ;; r ~· -. ", ,..::;.r,. 1-. •~,l ·····"' ··,·~·•~~ •.. , -~••::-;r,. ~ ••·;, ,. ..., •,1, .. , d . ..... ... nager •,~ ~-'' , .....,(':""'' •• -., I '►I 1 ,, ·~~ • ...it • .......~ ··t ... ••t \ VI, 1 OPEN LECTURES The tuition for all Open Lectures is included in the basic registration fee. If you are registered for one week, you may_ attend every open lecture through July 23rd, at no additional cliarge. If you are registered Tor two weeks, you may attend every open 1ecture. Your name tag w111 be your admission ticket. All Open Lectures conVffle in the 13allroom. FAch of the four lectures by Dr. Peikoff is from 10:30 am-12:30 pm; all other Open Lectures are from 10:30am-12 pm. Announaments will be made fiveminutes1Jefore the lectures begin at 10:25 am. READING AND WRITING Leonard Peikoff Tiris mini-course offers an Objectivist version of two of the three "R"s. It discusses how to read fiction (specifically, how to analy~~ great plays)-and how to write non-fiction (specifically, how to present great ideas). ~e wnting segment (sessions one and three) focuses on achieving clarity in ideological speeches, letters to the ed!tor, etc. F~r most topics (e.g., establishing context, selecting essentials, creating a structure), students will be assigned_ a bnef paragraph to write in class. Dr. Peikoff's own answer to the assignment (photocopied in advance) will~ handed out as part of the ensuing analysis. 1be rea~hng segm~nt (sessions two and four) focuses on the method of identifying the essential events and the metaphysical value-JUdgments of two twentieth-century Romantic dramas, one now virtually unknown, the other famo~s. -
The “Objectivists”: a Website Dedicated to the “Objectivist” Poets by Steel Wagstaff a Dissertation Submitted in Partial
The “Objectivists”: A Website Dedicated to the “Objectivist” Poets By Steel Wagstaff A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (English) at the UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN‐MADISON 2018 Date of final oral examination: 5/4/2018 The dissertation is approved by the following members of the Final Oral Committee: Lynn Keller, Professor, English Tim Yu, Associate Professor, English Mark Vareschi, Assistant Professor, English David Pavelich, Director of Special Collections, UW-Madison Libraries © Copyright by Steel Wagstaff 2018 Original portions of this project licensed under a CC BY-SA 4.0 license. All Louis Zukofsky materials copyright © Musical Observations, Inc. Used by permission. i TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ..................................................................................... vi Abstract ................................................................................................... vii Introduction ............................................................................................... 1 The Lives ................................................................................................ 31 Who were the “Objectivists”? .............................................................................................................................. 31 Core “Objectivists” .............................................................................................................................................. 31 The Formation of the “Objectivist” -
On Kelley on Kant Fred Seddon, Wheelingjesuit College
Reason Papers Discussions On Kelley on Kant Fred Seddon, WheelingJesuit College Randall Dipert, in a review of David Kelley's The Evidence ofthe Senses: A Realist Theory of Perception (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986 [henceforth: ES]) appearing in the Spring 1987 issue of Reason Papers, characterized it as "an important book," citing among his reasons the fact that ES is "a professionally competent defense of epistemoiogical theses originating with Ayn Rand" (57). Dipert also, however, found Kelley's treatment of Kant "most bizarre" and "profoundly uninformed" and recom- mended that Kelley "should bow out of historical criticism" (60-61). In the Spring 1988 issue of Reason Papers, Robert E. Knapp attempted a defense of Kelley's interpretation of Kant. For reasons of my own, however, I find myself in agreement with the general thrust of Dipert's characterizations, both positive and negative.' In this paper I propose to submit Kelley's analysis of Rand's and Kant's views of the activity and passivity of mind to a close and critical examination. Rand claimed that "[oln every fundamental issue, Kant's philosophy is the exact opposite of ~bjectivism."~Even discounting for Rand's usual hyperbole; this statement seems to be glaringly false in light both of Kelley's book and Rand's own Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology (New York: New American Library, 1979 [Henceforth: IOE]). To see that a universal affirm- ative proposition is false only one counterexample is necessary. That is, we need to find a fundamental issue upon which Rand and Kant agree (against the background of another philosopher who disagrees with both of them). -
David Kelley, the Evidence of the Senses Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986, 262 Pp
David Kelley, The Evidence of the Senses Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1986, 262 pp. Reviewed by Stephen R. C. Hicks, Indiana University Review published in Auslegung 15:2 (1989), pp. 193-196 The Evidence of the Senses offers a highly original exposition and defense of direct realism. This book should be required reading for any professional with an interest in human cognition, but especially so for philosophers and psychologists with interests in perception and the bases of knowledge. Because of its comprehensiveness in covering the vast literature of the epistemology of perception and because of the clarity of its prose, The Evidence of the Senses should also be attractive to instructors looking for a text for graduate or upper-level undergraduate courses. The major theses of Part I of Kelley’s book can be summarized as follows: Perception is a direct, preconceptual, non-inferential mode of awareness of physical objects and their properties. A chapter or two is devoted to detailed expositions and defenses of each of this statement's constituent theses. Chapter 1 lays out the basic assumptions of Kelley's realism, his main arguments for the directness of perception, and his polemic against the basic assumptions and arguments of its rivals, representationalism and idealism. The chapter is more historical than the rest, discussing the major sources of the contemporary debate: Descartes’ representationalism (10-16), Kant’s idealism (16-27), and the traditional “mirror of nature”1 realisms. Chapter 1 is also the heart of the book, for it is here that Kelley sets the tone for what follows by laying out his guiding principles.