Unconscious Cognition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Unconscious Cognition Author's personal copy Unconscious Cognition J F Kihlstrom, University of California, Berkeley, CA, USA ã 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Glossary Inattentional blindness – Failure to consciously perceive an object in the visual Automaticity – The label given to cognitive field because one’s attention is directed and other mental operations that are elsewhere. In various forms of ‘attentional executed outside phenomenal awareness blindness,’ such as repetition blindness, the and voluntary control. Automatic processes attentional blink, and change blindness, contrast with controlled processes in terms of the subject fails to perceive an object (or a four canonical features: they are inevitably change in an object) despite the fact that evoked by the presence of a particular attention is properly directed to the stimulus; incorrigibly executed, in a ballistic appropriate portion of the visual field. fashion, once evoked; effortless, meaning Learning – A relatively permanent change in that they consume little or no cognitive knowledge which occurs as a result of capacity; and efficient, in that they create little experience. ‘Explicit learning’ covers cases or no interference with other cognitive where the subject is consciously aware of this activities. new knowledge. ‘Implicit learning’ refers to Conscious shyness – The resistance of any effect of acquired knowledge affects psychology and other cognitive sciences to experience, thought, or action in the absence making consciousness a focus of inquiry. As of conscious awareness of what has been described by Owen Flanagan, conscious learned. shyness has four facets: ‘positivistic reserve,’ Limen – In classical psychophysics, the or a preference for publicly verifiable ‘threshold,’ or minimum amount of stimulus behavioral data over introspective self-reports; energy needed for an observer to ‘piecemeal approach,’ the assumption that an consciously detect the presence of, or understanding of consciousness will emerge change in, a stimulus. In ‘subliminal from more narrowly defined studies of perception’ the stimulus is too weak to be perception, memory, and the like; ‘conscious consciously perceived, or has been inessentialism,’ the view that consciousness is degraded by virtue of brief presentation, not necessary for certain cognitive functions, a masking stimulus, or the deployment of such as perceiving and remembering; and attention elsewhere. ‘epiphenomenalism,’ the view that consciousness plays no causal role in Memory – The mental representation of mentallife. some past event. ‘Explicit memory’ entails conscious recollection of some past event, as Dissociation – An experimental outcome in which one independent variable, such as in recall or recognition. ‘Implicit memory’ refers to any effect on experience, thought, or brain damage, has different (e.g., opposite) effects on two or more dependent variables. action of a past event, in the absence of Many studies of unconscious cognition conscious recollection of that event. indicate that some variable (such as brain Perception – The mental representation of damage or the direction of attention) an event in the current stimulus environment, or that of the very recent past. ‘Explicit dissociates, or has different effects on, explicit and implicit expressions of perception’ is indicated by the observer’s perception, memory, and the like. conscious awareness of the size, shape, 411 Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421 Author's personal copy 412 Unconscious Cognition Unconscious Cognition distance, motion, and identity of some stimulus. ‘Implicit perception’ refers to any As psychology developed as an empirical science, effect on experience, thought, or action of theory and research focused on those mental such an event, in the absence of conscious states that were accessible to consciousness, as perception of that event. represented by classical psychophysics (with its Preattentive processes – Perceptual and interest in sensory thresholds), the structuralists’ cognitive operations that occur before method of introspection, and William James’ clas- attention has been paid to a stimulus. sic essay, in the Principles of Psychology, on the Priming – The facilitation (or impairment) of stream of consciousness. Following the onslaught processing of a stimulus (the target) by prior of radical behaviorism, interest in consciousness presentation of another stimulus (the prime). declined precipitously in the years after World In ‘repetition priming,’ the prime physically War I. Woodworth’s work on the span of appre- resembles the target; in ‘semantic priming,’ hension was an exception, and consciousness was the prime and target are related in terms of the subtext of the Gestalt approach to perception. meaning. But serious scientific interest in consciousness had Process-dissociation procedure – to await the cognitive revolution, with its interest A method, invented by Jacoby, for in attention, short-term memory, and mental imag- quantifying the contributions of automatic ery. The widespread current interest in conscious- and controlled processes to task ness is illustrated by the very existence of performance by pitting the one against the encyclopedias like the present one. other. In the ‘Inclusion’ condition, automatic Even in the nineteenth century, however, psy- and controlled processes are allowed to work chologists recognized that the mental structures in the same direction; in the ‘Exclusion’ and processes underlying experience, thought, condition, automatic processes are placed in and action were not completely encompassed opposition to controlled processes. within the span of conscious awareness. Herbart’s Thought – As a verb, thinking refers to ‘limen’ made room for Leibniz’s ‘petites perceptions,’ various cognitive operations, such as and of course Helmholtz argued that conscious reasoning, problem-solving, judgment, and perception was based on unconscious inferences. decision-making. As a noun, thought refers to Perhaps the most forceful advocate of noncon- any mental representation, such as the idea scious mental life was William James, who (again or an image of a thing, which is itself neither a in the Principles) held that mental states could be percept (a mental representation of a unconscious in at least two different senses. First, a stimulus in the current environment) nor a mental event can be deliberately excluded from memory (a mental representation of a past attention or consciousness: ‘‘We can neglect to stimulus). attend to that which we nevertheless feel’’ (p. 201). Unconscious inference – As described by These unattended, unconscious thoughts and feel- Helmholtz, the inferences or thought ings are themselves mental states. Second, and processes that, automatically and more important, James drew on clinical observa- unconsciously, generate conscious tions of cases of hysteria and multiple personality perception from stimulus information. For to argue for a division of consciousness into pri- example, perceivers unconsciously apply the mary and secondary (and, for that matter, tertiary size–distance rule to take information about and more) consciousnesses (sic), only one of which size into account when judging the distance is accessible to phenomenal awareness at any point of an object, and vice-versa, to create the in time. To avoid possible oxymoron in the nega- ‘moon illusion’ and other perceptual effects. tion of consciousness, James preferred to speak of ‘co-conscious’ or ‘subconscious’ mental states, Encyclopedia of Consciousness (2009), vol. 2, pp. 411-421 Author's personal copy Unconscious Cognition 413 rather than ‘unconscious’ ones. There, was, in fact, make it past the filter was not. This same atten- considerable interest in unconscious mental life in tional filter was also the threshold which had to be the early twentieth century – even setting aside the crossed for information to be represented in phe- work of Sigmund Freud. But, as with conscious- nomenal awareness. The filter theories of attention, ness, the entire topic was banished from serious in turn, raised questions about how permeable the discourse by behaviorism. attentional filter was, and how much information History repeated itself in the latter half of the processing could occur preattentively. Was preat- twentieth century, as the ‘consciousness revolu- tentive – preconscious – processing limited to ele- tion’ which followed on the cognitive revolution mentary physical features of the stimulus, or could spun off an interest in unconscious mental life as it extend to the meaning of the stimulus as well? well. This happened slowly. For a long time, if the In part to solve these problems, the notion of an unconscious was discussed at all, it was construed attentional filter was replaced by the notion of merely as a repository for unattended percepts attentional capacity. Capacity theories, such as and forgotten memories. But in addition to this the one proposed by Kahneman in the early wastebasket view of the unconscious, the classic 1970s, began with the assumption that human multistore model of information processing made information-processing capacity is limited, and room for the unconscious by identifying uncon- proposed that the ability to perform one or more scious mental life with early, ‘preattentive’ mental task(s) depended both on the resources available processes that occur prior to the formation of and the resources required by the task(s) them- a mental representation of an event in primary
Recommended publications
  • The Unconscious Mind: Kinder and Gentler Than That
    3/20/2013 The Freudian 20th Century “Freud in 21st-Century America” The Unconscious Mind: Kinder and Gentler Than That John F. Kihlstrom Forbidden Planet (1956) Department of Psychology University of California, Berkeley 1 2 The Discovery of the Unconscious Petites Perceptions Ellenberger (1970) Leibniz (1704/1981); Ellenberger (1970) • At every moment there is in us an infinity of perceptions, unaccompanied by awareness or reflection…. That is why we are never indifferent, even when we appear to be most so…. The choice that we make arises from these insensible stimuli, which… make us find one direction of movement more comfortable than the 3 other. 4 The Limen Unconscious Inferences Herbart (1819) Helmholtz (1866/1968) • One of the older ideas can… be • The psychic activities that lead us to infer that completely driven out of consciousness by there in front of us at a certain place there is a a new much weaker idea. On the other certain object of a certain character, are generally hand its pressure there is not to be not conscious activities, but unconscious ones. In regarded as without effect; rather it works their result they are the equivalent to conclusion…. with full power against the ideas which are But what seems to differentiate them from a conclusion, in the ordinary sense of that word, is present in consciousness. It thus causes that a conclusion is an act of conscious thought…. a particular state of consciousness, though Still it may be permissible to speak of the psychic its object is in no sense really imagined. acts of ordinary perception as unconscious 5 conclusions….
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit and Explicit Knowledge About Language
    Comp. by: TPrasath Date:27/12/06 Time:22:59:29 Stage:First Proof File Path:// spiina1001z/womat/production/PRODENV/0000000005/0000001817/0000000016/ 0000233189.3D Proof by: QC by: NICK ELLIS IMPLICIT AND EXPLICIT KNOWLEDGE ABOUT LANGUAGE INTRODUCTION Children acquire their first language (L1) by engaging with their caretakers in natural meaningful communication. From this “evidence” they automatically acquire complex knowledge of the structure of their language. Yet paradoxically they cannot describe this knowledge, the discovery of which forms the object of the disciplines of theoretical lin- guistics, psycholinguistics, and child language acquisition. This is a difference between explicit and implicit knowledge—ask a young child how to form a plural and she says she does not know; ask her “here is a wug, here is another wug, what have you got?” and she is able to reply, “two wugs.” The acquisition of L1 grammar is implicit and is extracted from experience of usage rather than from explicit rules—simple expo- sure o normal linguistic input suffices and no explicit instruction is needed. Adult acquisition of second language (L2) is a different matter in that what can be acquired implicitly from communicative contexts is typically quite limited in comparison to native speaker norms, and adult attainment of L2 accuracy usually requires additional resources of explicit learning. The various roles of consciousness in second language acquisi- tion (SLA) include: the learner noticing negative evidence; their attending to language form, their perception focused by social scaffolding or explicit instruction; their voluntary use of pedagogical grammatical descriptions and analogical reasoning; their reflective induction of metalinguistic insights about language; and their consciously guided practice which results, eventually, in unconscious, automatized skill.
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit and Explicit Learning of Languages Patrick Rebuschat
    Introduction: Implicit and explicit learning of languages Patrick Rebuschat (Lancaster University) Introduction to the forthcoming volume: Rebuschat, P. (Ed.) (in press, 2015). Implicit and explicit learning of languages. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Implicit learning, essentially the process of acquiring unconscious (implicit) knowledge, is a fundamental feature of human cognition (Cleeremans, Destrebecqz, & Boyer, 1998; Dienes, 2012; Perruchet, 2008; Shanks, 2005; Reber, 1993). Many complex behaviors, including language comprehension and production (Berry & Dienes, 1993; Winter & Reber, 1994), music cognition (Rohrmeier & Rebuschat, 2012), intuitive decision making (Plessner, Betsch, & Betsch, 2008), and social interaction (Lewicki, 1986), are thought to be largely dependent on implicit knowledge. The term implicit learning was first used by Arthur Reber (1967) to describe a process during which subjects acquire knowledge about a complex, rule-governed stimulus environment without intending to and without becoming aware of the knowledge they have acquired. In contrast, the term explicit learning refers to a process during which participants acquire conscious (explicit) knowledge; this is generally associated with intentional learning conditions, e.g., when participants are instructed to look for rules or patterns. In his seminal study, Reber (1967) exposed subjects to letter sequences (e.g., TPTS, VXXVPS and TPTXXVS) by means of a memorization task. In experiment 1, subjects were presented with letter sequences and simply asked to commit them to memory. One group of subjects was given sequences that were generated by means of a finite-state grammar (Chomsky, 1956, 1957; Chomsky & Miller, 1958), while the other group received randomly 1 constructed sequences. The results showed that grammatical letter sequences were learned more rapidly than random letter sequences.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence of Automatic Processing in Sequence Learning Using Process-Dissociation
    RESEARCH ARTICLE ADVANCES IN COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY Evidence of automatic processing in sequence learning using process-dissociation Heather M. Mong, David P. McCabe, and Benjamin A. Clegg Department of Psychology, Colorado State University, Fort Collins, CO, USA ABSTRACT This paper proposes a way to apply process-dissociation to sequence learning in addition and ex- tension to the approach used by Destrebecqz and Cleeremans (2001). Participants were trained on two sequences separated from each other by a short break. Following training, participants self-reported their knowledge of the sequences. A recognition test was then performed which re- quired discrimination of two trained sequences, either under the instructions to call any sequence encountered in the experiment “old” (the inclusion condition), or only sequence fragments from one half of the experiment “old” (the exclusion condition). The recognition test elicited automatic KEYWORDS and controlled process estimates using the process dissociation procedure, and suggested both implicit learning, sequence processes were involved. Examining the underlying processes supporting performance may pro- learning, process- vide more information on the fundamental aspects of the implicit and explicit constructs than has dissociation, consciousness been attainable through awareness testing. INTRODUCTION Shanks, 2005), and numerous definitions of the term itself have been offered (Dienes & Perner, 1999; Frensch, 1998). This variety is further The serial reaction time task (SRTT) has become an extremely pro- reflected in an array of methods for assessing the presence or absence ductive method for studying sequence learning (for reviews, see of explicit knowledge. Issues raised have included whether explicit Abrahamse, Jimenez, Verwey, & Clegg, 2010; Clegg, DiGirolamo, knowledge is necessary for learning, what awareness tests should be & Keele, 1998).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Personality and Cognitions Underlying Entrepreneurial Intentions Benjamin R. Walker a Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment O
    1 Personality and Cognitions underlying Entrepreneurial Intentions Benjamin R. Walker A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of Management UNSW Business School March 30, 2015 2 Table of Contents Acknowledgements .................................................................................................................... 6 Originality statement .................................................................................................................. 7 Publications and conference presentations arising from this thesis ........................................... 8 List of abbreviations .................................................................................................................. 9 Thesis Abstract......................................................................................................................... 10 Chapter 1: Introduction ............................................................................................................ 11 Chapter 2: Assessing the impact of revised Reinforcement Sensitivity Theory ...................... 20 Table 1: Articles with original Reinforcement Sensitivity Theory (o-RST) and revised Reinforcement Sensitivity Theory (r-RST) measures .......................................................... 26 Table 2: Categorization of original Reinforcement Sensitivity Theory (o-RST) and revised Reinforcement Sensitivity Theory (r-RST) studies in the five years from 2010-2014 ........ 29 Chapter 3: How
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: General Copyrighl 1989 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 1989, Vol. 118, No. 3, 219-235 0096-3445/89/500,75 Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge Arthur S. Reber Brooklyn College and the Graduate Center City University of New York I examine the phenomenon of implicit learning, the process by which knowledge about the rale- governed complexities of the stimulus environment is acquired independently of conscious attempts to do so. Our research with the two, seemingly disparate experimental paradigms of synthetic grammar learning and probability learning is reviewed and integrated with other approaches to the general problem of unconscious cognition. The conclusions reached are as follows: (a) Implicit learning produces a tacit knowledge base that is abstract and representative of the structure of the environment; (b) such knowledge is optimally acquired independently of conscious efforts to learn; and (c) it can be used implicitly to solve problems and make accurate decisions about novel stimulus circumstances. Various epistemological issues and related prob- 1 lems such as intuition, neuroclinical disorders of learning and memory, and the relationship of evolutionary processes to cognitive science are also discussed. Some two decades ago the term implicit learning was first lined, and analyzed, but virtually no attention was paid to the used to characterize how one develops intuitive knowledge processes by which these implicit memories "got there." This about the underlying structure of a complex stimulus envi- general lack of attention to the acquisition problem may be ronment (Reber, 1965, 1967). In those early writings, I argued one of the reasons why much recent theorizing has been that implicit learning is characterized by two critical features: oriented toward a nativist position (e.g., Chomsky, 1980; (a) It is an unconscious process and (b) it yields abstract Fodor, 1975, 1983; Gleitman & Wanner, 1982).
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit Learning, Development, and Education
    Implicit learning, development, and education A. Vinter, S. Pacton, A. Witt and P. Perruchet Introduction The present chapter focuses on implicit learning processes, and aims at showing that these processes could be used to design new methods of education or reeducation. After a brief definition of what we intend by implicit learning, we will show that these proc- esses operate efficiently in development, from infancy to aging. Then, we will discuss the question of their resistance to neurological or psychiatric diseases. Finally, in a last section, we will comment on their potential use within an applied perspective. The fundamental role of learning, once neglected by cognitive psychologists a few decades ago, is now acknowledged in most areas of research, including language, cate- gorization and object perception (2). Of course, nobody has ever claimed that language development is independent of infants’ experience. However, the dominant Chom- skian tradition has confined learning to subsidiary functions, such as setting the values of parameters in a hardwired system. Recent work shows that fundamental components of language such as word segmentation (69) can be learned in an incidental way similar to that involved in the acquisition of other human abilities. Likewise, it has never been denied that learning plays a role in categorization and object perception, but acquisition processes were thought to be limited to new combinations of preestablished features (7). However, Schyns and Rodet (77) have shown that elementary features can them- selves be created with experience (for a review, see 74, 75). The type of learning process that receives the most attention in the current literature relates to implicit learning.
    [Show full text]
  • Implicit Learning in Children Is Not Related to Age: Evidence from Drawing Behavior
    Child Development, September/October 2000, Volume 71, Number 5, Pages 1223–1240 Implicit Learning in Children Is Not Related to Age: Evidence from Drawing Behavior Annie Vinter and Pierre Perruchet Three experiments are reported on implicit learning in 432 children between the ages of 4 and 10 years, using a new paradigm (“the neutral parameter procedure”) based on drawing behavior. The first two experiments demonstrated that children modified their drawing behavior following specially devised practice in such a way that these modifications could not be viewed as the result of deliberate adaptive strategies. The third ex- periment showed that these behavioral modifications lasted for at least 1 hr after the training phase. No age- related differences appeared in the experiments. A comparison of children’s data with similar adults’ data also failed to reveal any age differences. These results provide compelling evidence that implicit learning processes are age independent. Some implications of these results for developmental issues are discussed, notably the hypothesis of the formation of implicit knowledge in the course of learning. INTRODUCTION in which children’s behavior becomes sensitive to the structural features of an experienced situation, with- The fundamental role of learning, neglected by cogni- out the adaptation being due to an intentional exploi- tive psychologists a few decades ago, is now ac- tation of some pieces of explicit knowledge about knowledged in most areas of research, including lan- these features (Perruchet & Vinter, 1998). The two im- guage, categorization, and object perception (Bates & portant components of implicit learning are thus the Elman, 1996). Of course, nobody has ever claimed behavioral sensitivity to the structure of the situation that language development is independent of infants’ and the lack of intentional causes for this sensitivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Effects of Mindfulness Meditation on Conscious and Non-Conscious Components of the Mind
    applied sciences Review Effects of Mindfulness Meditation on Conscious and Non-Conscious Components of the Mind Anastasia Fabbro 1,5,*, Cristiano Crescentini 2, Alessio Matiz 3, Andrea Clarici 4 and Franco Fabbro 5 1 Department of Psychology, University of Rome La Sapienza, 00185 Rome, Italy 2 Department of Languages and Literatures, Communication, Education and Society, University of Udine, 33100 Udine, Italy; [email protected] 3 Perceptual Robotics (PERCRO) Laboratory, Scuola Superiore Sant’Anna, 56010 Pisa, Italy; [email protected] 4 Psychiatric Clinic, Department of Medical, Surgical and Health Sciences, University of Trieste, 34149 Trieste, Italy; [email protected] 5 Department of Medicine, University of Udine, 33100 Udine, Italy; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Academic Editor: Peter Walla Received: 31 January 2017; Accepted: 30 March 2017; Published: 1 April 2017 Abstract: The aim of the present review is to investigate previous studies concerning the effects of meditation and dispositional mindfulness on conscious and implicit or non-conscious attitudes. First we present a brief perspective on conscious and non-conscious states of mind. Then we introduce the fundamental bases of mindfulness meditation. Third we review studies on dispositional mindfulness and meditation that employed either direct or indirect measures to assess explicit and implicit attitudes. Finally, we briefly present how meditation has been associated with the psychotherapeutic practice of psychoanalysis and, hence, as a therapeutic technique to access the unconscious. Until now, few studies have investigated the impact of meditation on non-conscious states of mind and personality; nevertheless, both scientific studies involving implicit measures and reflections from psychotherapy have underlined the importance of meditation in promoting psychological well-being, leading to de-automatization of automatic patterns of responding and to higher levels of self-awareness.
    [Show full text]
  • Seven Implicit Considerations to Be Explicitly Addressed in Empirically Based Psychotherapies
    Revista Interamericana de Psicologia/Interamerican Journal of Psychology (IJP) 2017, Vol., 51, No. 2, pp. 226-238 SEVEN IMPLICIT CONSIDERATIONS TO BE EXPLICITLY ADDRESSED IN EMPIRICALLY BASED PSYCHOTHERAPIES Martin J. La Roche1 Harvard Medical School and Boston Children’s Hospital, USA Hector Y. Adames Nayeli Y. Chavez-Dueñas The Chicago School of Professional Psychology, USA Abstract The psychological literature on implicit processes (IPs), which encompasses an individual’s thoughts, actions, and feelings that occur independently of conscious awareness, has expanded in the last two decades. During this same period, the proliferation of empirically based psychotherapies (EBPs), with emphasis on conscious processes, has gained momentum among many mental health practitioners. However, the literature on the role of IPs in empirically based psychotherapies (EBPs) is sparse. The main goal of this paper is to suggest IP findings that can be used to enhance EBP’s efficacy and effectiveness. Seven IP findings that can have important applications for EBPs are highlighted. Within each of these seven considerations, the impact of IPs on the psychotherapeutic process is discussed. Keywords: implicit processes, empirically based psychotherapies, neuroscience, psychotherapy, culture Resumen La literatura psicológica sobre procesos implícitos (IP), que abarca los pensamientos, acciones y sentimientos de un individuo que ocurren independientemente de la conciencia, se ha expandido en las últimas dos décadas. Durante este mismo período, la proliferación de psicoterapias con base empírica (PBE), con énfasis en los procesos conscientes, ha cobrado impulso entre muchos profesionales de la salud mental. Sin embargo, la literatura sobre el papel de los IP en psicoterapias basadas empíricamente (EBP) es escasa.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness: a Connectionist Perspective
    Consciousness: A Connectionist Perspective Jonathan Opie Department of Philosophy University of Adelaide Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy February 1998 Contact me at: Department of Philosophy University of Adelaide South Australia 5005 DEDICATION To my father, who got me thinking, and to Tricia, who provided the love, support, and encouragement that enabled me to see this through. TABLE OF CONTENTS 1 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................1 2 TWO COMPUTATIONAL THEORIES OF MIND..................................................6 2.1 Folk Psychology and Cognition ........................................................................................6 2.2 The Classical Computational Theory of Mind................................................................10 2.3 The Connectionist Computational Theory of Mind........................................................15 3 PHENOMENAL EXPERIENCE: A BRIEF SURVEY ..............................................25 3.1 Some Forms of Conscious Experience.............................................................................25 3.2 Consciousness and Thought ...........................................................................................32 3.3 The Nature of Phenomenal Experience...........................................................................42 4 THE UNITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS ....................................................................43 4.1 Monophonic Consciousness............................................................................................44
    [Show full text]
  • The Emotional Unconscious
    Retrieved on 21 September 2011 from http://ist-socrates.berkeley.edu/~kihlstrm/Eich2000.htm The Emotional Unconscious John F. Kihlstrom Shelagh Mulvaney University of California, Berkeley University of Arizona Betsy A. Tobias Irene P. Tobis University of Arizona University of Wisconsin Note: An edited version of this article appeared in E. Eich, J.F. Kihlstrom, G.H. Bower, J.P. Forgas, & P.M. Niedenthal (2000) Counterpoints: Cognition and Emotion (pp. 30-86), New York: Oxford University. The webpage is last modified by author(s) 07/10/2007 10:36:19 AM . This document is created and corrected from typos 22/09/2011 10:18:12 PM. One of the earliest marks of the cognitive revolution in psychology was a re- vival of interest in consciousness, as opposed to behavior. To a large degree, the cognitive psychology which emerged immediately after World War II to replace functional behaviorism was marked by an interest in the span of ap- prehension, primary memory, attention, and imagery. Now, as we approach the 21st century, cognitive psychology has begun to deal seriously with un- conscious mental life, and the notion of the psychological unconscious: the idea that conscious experience, thought, and action is influenced by per- cepts, memories, and other mental states which are inaccessible to pheno- menal awareness and somehow independent of voluntary control. The Cognitive Unconscious and Beyond In the modern history of cognitive psychology, one can discern four early stages in our conceptualization of the psychological unconscious (Kihlstrom, 1995b, 1998a). (1) The first of these might be called the wastebasket view: 1 | Page Retrieved on 21 September 2011 from http://ist-socrates.berkeley.edu/~kihlstrm/Eich2000.htm that the unconscious is comprised of events that are unattended and unre- hearsed, and memories that have been lost through decay or displacement.
    [Show full text]