APA Freebook

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

APA Freebook R O U T L E D G E . TAYLOR & FRANCIS Epistemology A Routledge Collection for APA Members www.routledge.com/philosophy Contents Epistemology: Current Controversies 2 Current Controversies in Epistemology ed. by Ram Neta Introduction 10 Don't Be Fooled: A Philosophy of Common Sense by Jan Bransen The Power of Power 27 Power and Capacities in Philosophy: The New Aristotelian ed. by John Greco and Ruth Groff 20% Discount Available Enjoy a 20% discount across our entire range of Philosophy books. Simply add the discount code APA17 at the checkout. Please note: This discount code cannot be combined with any other discount or offer and is only valid on print titles purchased directly from www.routledge.com. This discount is valid until 31/12/2017. www.routledge.com/philosophy Epistemology Current Controversies RAM NETA Introduction If you are reading this book, then it is very likely that you are either affi liated with an institution of tertiary education (a college or university), or that you have had some such affi liation in the past. 1 Such institutions describe their missions in different ways, but one thing that their various descriptions have in common is a focus on the acquisition and dissemination of knowledge. To the extent, then, that we care (as many of us increasingly do) to understand and evaluate the mission of such institutions, we should be concerned to understand what knowledge is and why it is worth acquiring or disseminating. Epistemology is the attempt to answer such questions. And while epistemol- ogy is much older than any current institution of tertiary education, it arose in response to the systematic attempt to acquire and disseminate knowledge. Early work in Greek epistemology arose in refl ecting on Meno’s question whether virtue could be taught, or in refl ecting on Theaetetus’ dedication to acquire knowledge. But, as so often happens in philosophy, refl ection on these issues has led to controversy on several other, closely related issues. Four of these controversies have been especially important in the history of episte- mology over the past three centuries at least: the nature and extent of a priori knowledge, the nature and extent of a posteriori justifi cation, the solution to the problem of the regress of justifi cation, and the question of whether skep- ticism can be refuted. The current state of these four controversies is repre- sented in each of the four parts of this volume. 3 • Ram Neta You will notice that the term “justifi cation” occurs in the title of the fi rst three of these four parts of the volume, but the term “knowledge” does not. Why? For at least the past century, epistemology has proceeded under the assumption that the very same procedures or capacities or grounds that some- times give us knowledge do on other occasions fail to give us knowledge, but fail in such a way as to leave us rationally permitted—perhaps even rationally obligated—to believe something that we (unbeknownst to ourselves) don’t know to be true. The evidence all strongly indicates that the patient will die within 6 months, and so we are rationally permitted, perhaps obligated, to believe that the patient will die within 6 months—but what if, nonetheless, the patient were to live longer? Then we would have been rationally permitted or obligated to believe something that turns out to be false, and so that we could not have known to be true. The controversies discussed in the fi rst three parts of this volume are controversies concerning the kind of permission or obliga- tion that rationality can issue us with respect to a proposition, even when we fail to know that proposition to be true. This kind of permission or obligation is what I, following at least some common parlance in epistemology, call “jus- tifi cation.” Though different epistemologists use the term “justifi cation” in dif- ferent ways, and even when they use it the same way they often end up having very different theories of what constitutes possession of the relevant deontic status, the controversies discussed in the fi rst three parts of this volume tend to proceed on the assumption that we can fi x our attention in common on a single deontic status and engage in a fruitful dispute concerning the nature or extent of that status. Since it is that deontic status that is of distinctive concern to epistemologists—the deontic status that is involved in knowing, but can on occasion occur without it—the fi rst three parts of the volume are framed as controversies concerning justifi cation, rather than knowledge. 1. The A Priori: Can We Gain Justifi cation Independently of Experience? Throughout much of its history, epistemology has been interested in under- standing whether—and if so, then how—it is possible for us to know not merely what happens to be the case, but what must be the case. (Indeed, many philosophers interpret Plato as having Socrates advance the view, in the Republic, that knowledge is possible only with respect to what must be the case, and not with respect to what merely happens to be the case.) If we know what happens to be the case (e.g., that the clouds are now hiding the sun from view, or that the automobile behind us just honked its horn), then we know these things by means of what we currently see, or hear. Perception is thought to be the source of our knowledge of what happens to be the case ( Part II of this volume is devoted to examining how this is possible, and Part IV to whether we can prove that it is possible). But can perception tell us about not 4 Epistemology: Current Controversies • merely what happens to be the case, but rather what must be the case? Many philosophers 2 have thought that it could not do so. But if perception cannot tell us what must be the case, then how, if at all, is it possible for us to know what must be the case? Descartes devotes much of his Meditations on First Philosophy 3 to answer- ing this question. He attempts to identify the source of our knowledge of what must be the case by supposing that all of the information that we receive by means of sensory perception is false. On this supposition, what, if anything, is it still possible for us to know? Descartes argues that, even on this supposi- tion, it is possible to know of one’s own existence as a thinking thing, it is pos- sible to identify the source of this knowledge as a faculty of clear and distinct perception (or what Descartes sometimes calls “the natural light”), and it is possible to articulate the knowledge provided by this source as knowledge of the nature of extended substance, knowledge of the nature of thinking sub- stance, and knowledge of the nature of perfect substance. All such knowledge, on Descartes’ view, is fully precise, even if very incomplete. Whatever exactly this faculty of clear and distinct perception amounts to, for Descartes, it must be distinct from sensory perception, because we gain knowledge by means of it even on the supposition that all of the information acquired by means of sensory perception is false. This sort of knowledge is what philosophers since Kant have called “a priori.” Notice that, as I just defi ned a priori knowledge, it is knowledge of what must be the case, it is knowledge acquired by means of a faculty that is distinct from sensory perception, and it is, fi nally, knowledge acquired by means of a faculty that could give us knowledge even on the supposition that sensory perception fails to do so. But it is a substantive commitment that there is some kind of knowledge that bears all of these properties. A number of Descartes’ successors may be understood as criticizing this commitment in different ways. David Hume, for instance, thinks that claims about what must be the case, to the extent that they are not confused, are claims that concern only relations of ideas, viz., relations among the various combinations of traces left on our minds by impressions. 4 The faculty by means of which we know such claims to be true is simply the faculty that preserves traces of our impressions and combines them in various ways. But this is the same faculty by which we gain knowledge of such contingent features of the world as that the clouds are now hiding the sun, and so the faculty that delivers knowledge for necessity is the same, for Hume, as that which delivers knowledge of contingency. Immanuel Kant thinks that our knowledge of what must be the case arises not from one but rather from two distinct sources: the form of our intuition, and the cat- egories of the understanding, and the ability of these sources to give us knowl- edge is not entirely independent of the ability of sensory perception to give us knowledge. 5 In particular, for Kant, we gain knowledge of the necessary by abstracting away from particular features of our knowledge of the contingent. 5 • Ram Neta The question of whether there is a priori knowledge is the question of whether our knowledge of what must be the case—our knowledge of such necessary truths as those of mathematics and logic, for example—is knowl- edge that is furnished by means of a faculty that is distinct from sensory per- ception, or not. In Chapter 1 , C.S.I. Jenkins defends the fi rst option. In the Chapter 2 , Michael Devitt defends the second option.
Recommended publications
  • LAWS and LAWLESSNESS Are There Laws of Nature of the Sort Discussed in Much Recent Metaphysics?
    STEPHEN MUMFORD LAWS AND LAWLESSNESS ABSTRACT. I develop a metaphysical position that is both lawless and anti-Humean. The position is called realist lawlessness and contrasts with both Humean lawlessness and nomological realism – the claim that there are laws in nature. While the Humean view also allows no laws, realist lawlessness is not Humean because it accepts some necessary connections in nature between distinct properties. Realism about laws, on the other hand, faces a central dilemma. Either laws govern the behaviour of properties from the outside or from the inside. If the former, an unacceptable quidditist view of properties follows. But no plausible account of laws within properties can be developed that permits a governing role specifically for laws. I conclude in favour of eliminativism about laws. At the conceptual core, the notion of a law in nature is misleading. It is suggestive of an otherwise static world in need of animation. 1. INTRODUCTION: PRIMITIVISM, REDUCTIONISM AND ELIMINATIVISM Are there laws of nature of the sort discussed in much recent metaphysics?1 While these discussions tend to disagree over the nature of such laws, they have in common a commitment to laws being an ineliminable part of an adequate metaphysics for our world. In this paper, I challenge that assumption. The question with which I began can be recast in ways that puts emphasis on the issue of eliminability. Do laws of nature deliver some feature to the world that would otherwise be lacking? Could a world be just like ours if it didn’t have laws? Did God have to create laws once he had created all the other things, such as particulars and universals? And so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Academic CV Vero
    Giacomo Giannini Department of Philosophy, Durham University, 50 Old Elvet, DH1 3HN, United Kingdom [email protected], [email protected] Areas of Specialisation: Metaphysics. Areas of Competence: Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Logic and Language, Modern Philsosophy. EDUCATION PhD 2016-2020 Durham University Title of Dissertation: ‘Powers for Dispositionalism: A Metaphysical Ground for New Actualism’. Supervisors: Matthew Tugby, Stephen Mumford, and Anna Marmodoro. Viva passed with Minor Corrections. Examiners: Barbara Vetter (FU Berlin), Robin Hendry (Durham). MA Philosophy (Distinction) 2016 Università di Bologna. Title of Dissertation: ‘Truthmakers for Modal Claims’. Supervisors: Walter Cavini and Fabrice Correia (Université de Neuchâtel). BA Philosophy (Distinction) 2014 Università di Bologna Supervisor: Eva Picardi. PUBLICATIONS 2020 “Actualism minus Naturalism Equals Platonism?” co-authored with Matthew Tugby, Philosophical In- quiries, S.I. on Barbara Vetter’s Potentiality (OUP, 2015), 2020. Forthcoming “Formal Causes for Powers” co-authored with Stephen Mumford, to appear in Sandstad & Jansen (eds.) Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives on Formal Causation, Routledge, 2020. Under Review “Powers, Processes, and Eternalism” (R&R, Erkenntnis) “New Powers for Dispositionalism” (R&R, Synthese) Work in Progress “Universals Cannot Be Manifestations of Powers” 1 “The Source of Independence and the Source of Necessity” “Can There Be a Fundamental Level in a Powerful World?” SCHOLARSHIPS AND AWARDS 2019 Royal Institute of Philosophy Bursary. 2019 Durham Excellence in Learning and Teaching Award. 2016 ARHC - Northern Bridge Doctoral Training Partnership Doctoral Scholarship. 2015 University Award for Academic Excellence (Borsa di studio per merito) for the year 2013/14. 2014 University Award for Academic Excellence (Borsa di studio per merito) for the year 2012/13.
    [Show full text]
  • Essentiality Without Necessity
    Essentiality without Necessity Petter Sandstad Abstract It is widely accepted that if a property is essential then it is necessary. Against this I present numerous counterexamples from biology and chemistry, which fall into two groups: (I) A property is essential to a genus or species, yet some instances of this genus or species do not have this essential property. (II) A property is essential to a genus, yet some species of this genus do not have this essential property. I discuss and reject four minor objections. Then I discuss in depth whether a distinction between constitutive essence and consequential essence is able to handle these counterexamples. I conclude that this distinction is better put as one between (1) the essence, which is necessary, and (2) the essential properties, which are not formally necessary. An essence of an object X is the substantial universal expressed by its real definition. An object X has a property P essentially iff the property P is explanatory and non-trivial, and P follows from the essence of X. Keywords: essential properties, necessary properties, essence, exceptions Kripke, Putnam, and others defended the tenability of essentiality as de re necessity, orthodoxly analysed as something that is true of a thing in all possible worlds where it exists (cf. [27] for a historical survey). According to this modal view, a property is predicated essentially if and only if it is (physically) necessary. If an object X essentially has a property P, then it must have P in all possible worlds where X exists (i.e. it must be necessary).
    [Show full text]
  • References Indrek Reiland Institut Jean Nicod Stephen Mumford And
    Philosophical Review BOOK REVIEWS References Pautz, Adam. Forthcoming. “Propositions and Properties.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Reiland, Indrek. 2013. “Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts.” Thought 1: 239–45. ———. n.d. “Predication and the Frege-Geach Problem.” Unpublished manuscript. Soames, Scott. 2014. “Cognitive Propositions.” In New Thinking about Propositions, ed. J. King, S. Soames, and J. Speaks, 91–126. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Indrek Reiland Institut Jean Nicod Philosophical Review, Vol. 126, No. 1, 2017 DOI 10.1215/00318108-3683712 Stephen Mumford and Matthew Tugby, eds., Metaphysics and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013. ix þ244 pp. Metaphysics of science, according to Stephen Mumford and Matthew Tugby, is “the metaphysical study of the aspects of reality, such as kindhood, lawhood, causal power, and causation, which impose order on the world and make our scientific disciplines possible ...and also the study of the metaphysical relation- ship between the various scientific disciplines” (14). The editors explicitly rule out such studies as the metaphysics of space, for instance, as mere “specific metaphysical debates as they arise within specific scientific sub-disciplines” (6), such as physics in this case. The core of the metaphysics of science, as they insist, consists solely of those Kantian issues of extreme generality that concern the very possibility of science. The editors seem to suggest that the consideration of these points, as a truly first philosophy, prior to any scientific work, does not require any detailed competence in actual science. And they appear confident that work on kindhood, lawhood, and the relation among the sciences by the first philosopher will not suffer the embarrassing fate of Kant’s a priori pronouncements on the metaphysics of space.1 It is from the armchair, then, that “core” metaphysicians of science proceed to divine the fundamental order of things.
    [Show full text]
  • Cvii (7): 333–359
    L.A. Paul [email protected] Appointments 2021–. Millstone Family Professor of Philosophy and Professor of Cognitive Science, Yale University. 2020–. Professor of Psychology (secondary appointment), Yale University. 2018–2020. Professor of Philosophy and Cognitive Science, Yale University. 2014–2018. Professorial Fellow, Arché Philosophical Research Centre, University of St Andrews. 2016–2018. Eugene Falk Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. 2012–2016. Professor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. 2008–2012. Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. 2007–2008. Associate Professor of Philosophy, University of Arizona. 2001–2007. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Arizona. 2001–2005. Institute for Advanced Studies Research Fellow, Philosophy, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University. 1999–2001. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Yale University. Education Ph.D., 1999, Philosophy, Princeton University. M.A., 1996, Philosophy, Princeton University. M.A., 1996, Philosophy, Antioch University. B.A., 1990, Biology and Chemistry, Antioch College. Areas of Specialization: Metaphysics, Philosophy of Mind, Cognitive Science, Formal Epistemology, Philosophy of Science. 1 Publications Books In Progress. Who will I Become? (provisional title) Under contract with Farrar, Straus and Giroux. 2020. Was können wir wissen, bevor wir uns entscheiden?, German translation of “What you can’t expect when you’re expecting”,
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    JOHN HAWTHORNE Updated October 2018 PERSONAL DETAILS: BORN: Birmingham, England May 25, 1964 ADDRESS: USC School of Philosophy 3709 Trousdale Parkway, Los Angeles CA 90089 EMAIL: [email protected] AWARDS AND FELLOWSHIPS Part of three person Templeton Award (with Yoaav Isaacs and Aron Wall) for two year project on fine-tuning. Fellow of British Academy (elected 2013) Visiting Fellowship, Australian National University (for Summer 2014) Project Leader of New Insights In Religious Epistemology, a three year project at Oxford funded by the Templeton Foundation (since 2012). Visiting Lecturership, University of Helsinki, 2012. Nelson Visiting Fellow, Michigan University, 2011. Centre for Study of Mind and Language Project at University of Oslo. Project Associate since 2009. Visting Fellowship at University of Oxford 2005. Visiting Astor Lecturer, Oxford 2004. Research Fellowship at Australian National University (1993-1995) Grant from Australian Research Council for work on Grammar of Meaning book, 1991- 1993. Dissertation Prize for best Dissertation at Syracuse University (1991) First Class Honors, University of Manchester (1985) ACADEMIC POSITIONS: 1 Professor of Philosophy, University of Southern California, Los Angeles, USA (part-time 2013-July 2015, full time from July 2015). Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy, Magdalen College, Oxford, UK (2006 to July 2015) Professor of Philosophy (part-time), Princeton University (2009-2012) Professor, Rutgers University (2001-2006) Professor, Syracuse University (1996-2001) Assistant Professor, Arizona State University (1995-1996) Assistant Professor, University of New South Wales (1991-1995) EDUCATION: PhD. Syracuse University (1991) B.A. in Philosophy and Politics, University of Manchester (1985) 2 PUBLICATIONS: BOOKS Monographs Narrow Content (with Juhani Yli-Vakkuri, Oxford University Press, 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • Ebook-Mumford-Laws-In-Nature.Pdf
    Laws in Nature What are the laws of nature? Do they control the actions and movements of the other things that exist in our world? Is there a sense in which such laws are real things? Both scientists and philosophers have been attracted by the view that the world contains laws of nature. It is such laws that dictate the behaviour of particulars, rather than any of those things’ intrinsic or internal forces. In this book Stephen Mumford argues against this popular view. He shows that no adequate account has been produced of what such laws in nature would be, or how they would perform the work that has been required of them. In their place, he argues that there are other necessary connections in nature that can do all the work for which we thought laws were needed. This book offers a holistic and connected account of reality in which the world’s elements do not need to be activated or controlled by laws. It is not possible that these elements behave other than they do. The world is more of a jigsaw than a mosaic: its pieces can form only one picture, and laws are no part of it. Stephen Mumford is Reader in Metaphysics in the Department of Philo- sophy at the University of Nottingham. He is the author of Dispositions (1998) and various papers in metaphysics. He is editor of Russell on Meta- physics (2003) and Powers by the late George Molnar (2003). Routledge studies in twentieth-century philosophy 1 The Story of Analytic Philosophy Plot and heroes Edited by Anat Biletzki and Anat Matar 2 Donald Davidson Truth, meaning and knowledge Edited by Urszula M.
    [Show full text]
  • Natures Metaphysics.Pdf
    NATURE’S METAPHYSICS This page intentionally left blank Nature’s Metaphysics Laws and Properties by ALEXANDER BIRD CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York Alexander Bird 2007 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2007 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
    [Show full text]
  • 2Nd Annual Meeting
    2nd Annual Meeting, 12-14th May 2005 Derwentside District Council, Leisure Services Division Louisa Centre, Stanley, Co Durham, UK http://www.philosophyofsport.org.uk ! Book of Abstracts Sports’ contribution to well-being........................................................................................3 Andrew Bloodworth.........................................................................................................3 Moral Education and Physical Education: a virtue-theoretical approach .............................4 Rona Brodie, University of Gloucestershire, 1.2.05 .........................................................4 ‘Dehumanisation’ and Performance-Enhancement..............................................................5 Leon Culbertson ...............................................................................................................5 Critical (Realist) Reflection on Policy Enquiry in Sports .......................................................6 Paul Downward, Loughborough University .....................................................................6 The State of Scottish Climbing: bolt or not? .........................................................................6 Philip Ebert and Simon Robertson....................................................................................6 The missing art of sport........................................................................................................7 Andrew Edgar...................................................................................................................7
    [Show full text]
  • Changing Software Through Metaphysics 1
    Impact case study (REF3b) Institution: University of Nottingham Unit of Assessment: UoA32 Title of case study: Changing Software Through Metaphysics 1. Summary of the impact Mumford and Tallant engaged in consultancy work for IT companies, with both interactions leading to substantial positive benefits for commercial partners. Though ‘early stage impacts’, each consultancy has generated both commercial value and a change in software design of a key product. Through Mumford’s consultancy, research led to significant changes to the development of a database tool developed by a national IT company, FACE Recording and Measurement Systems. This, in turn, has led to a patent application. FACE recently received an offer of $5m (US) for a product based upon the tool. Through Tallant’s consultancy, research led to important changes to the development of an online calendar/event planner tool, developed by a Canadian software company—Time.ly. It also led to Time.ly being able to engage a wider audience. The financial value of such a company depends upon the number of users they can engage. Time.ly were recently valued at $8.4m (CAN). Between them, Mumford and Tallant have made significant contributions to companies or products valued at over £8m. 2. Underpinning research Work carried out between 2005 and 2012 (and published between 2007 and 2013), produced by Professor Stephen Mumford (Nottingham 1995-present) and Dr. Jonathan Tallant (2007-present), has two common strands. The first is that it is perfectly coherent (desirable, even) to treat at least some properties as being irreducibly directed towards some particular state. For instance, Mumford [3.2] has argued that it is central to our best theory of properties that we treat them as dispositions for some state.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Getting Causes from Powers by Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Jennifer Mckitrick University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected]
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 4-2013 Review of Getting Causes from Powers by Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Jennifer McKitrick University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub Part of the Metaphysics Commons McKitrick, Jennifer, "Review of Getting Causes from Powers by Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum" (2013). Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy. 50. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosfacpub/50 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. McKitrick in Analysis Reviews 73 (2013) 1 Published in Analysis, Vol 73, Number 2 (April 2013), pp 402–404. digitalcommons.unl.edu doi 10.1093/analys/ant016 Copyright © 2013 Jennifer McKitrick. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Trust. Used by permission. Book Review Getting Causes from Powers Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Oxford University Press, 2012. xvi+254 pp. £35.00 reviewed by Jennifer McKitrick University of Nebraska – Lincoln Lincoln, NE, USA [email protected] Some philosophers have suggested that having powers in one’s ontol- ogy has the advantage of providing resources for an account of causa- tion (see Cartwright 1999; Harré 1970; Mill 1843; Whitehead 1929). But what would a theory of causation look like if we assume that powers are real? In Getting Causes from Powers, Mumford and An- jum make what is perhaps the first sustained attempt to answer that question.
    [Show full text]
  • Powers and Causation
    Printed in Anna Marmodoro (ed.) The Metaphysics of Powers, Routledge 2010: 143-59 A Powerful Theory of Causation Rani Lill Anjum Department of Philosophy, University of Tromsø and Nottingham Stephen Mumford Department of Philosophy, University of Nottingham Abstract Hume thought that if you believed in powers, you believed in necessary connections in nature. He was then able to argue that there were none such because anything could follow anything else. But Hume wrong-footed his opponents. A power does not necessitate its manifestations: rather, it disposes towards them in a way that is less than necessary but more than purely contingent. In this paper a dispositional theory of causation is offered. Causes dispose towards their effects and often produce them. But a set of causes, even though they may succeed in producing an effect, cannot necessitate it since the effect could have been counteracted by some additional power. This would require a separation of our concepts of causal production and causal necessitation. The most conspicuous cases of causation are those where powers accumulate and pass a requisite threshold for an effect to occur. We develop a model for representing powers as constituent vectors within an n-dimensional quality space, where composition of causes appears as vector addition. Even our resultant vector, however, has to be understood as having dispositional force only. This model throws new light on causal modality and cases of prevention, causation by absence and probabilistic causation. 1. The dispositionality of causation When it comes to causation, we should think less of necessity and more of dispositionality. Others have already suggested that it should be possible to get a theory of causation from an ontology of real dispositions or powers (Harré and Madden 1975, Bhaskar 1975, Cartwright 1989, Ellis 2001, Molnar 2003: ch.
    [Show full text]