Infinitesimals, a Relationship That Stretches Back Thousands of Years

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Infinitesimals, a Relationship That Stretches Back Thousands of Years J.M. HENLE Non-nonstandard Analysis: Real Infinitcsimals ~n athematics has had a troubled relationship with infinitesimals, a relationship that stretches back thousands of years. On the one ,hand, infinitesimals make intuitive sense. They're easy to deal with algebraically. They make calculus a lot of fun. On the other hand, they seem impossible to nail down. They're hard to deal "standard." Nor is it "nonstandard," however, as this term with intellectually. They can mask a fundamental lack of now has a well-def'med meaning. In what follows, we ma- understanding of analysis. nipulate sequences of real numbers. We treat them (mostly) There was hope, when Abraham Robinson developed as numbers. We add them, subtract them, and put them nonstandard analysis [R], that intuition and rigor had at last into functions. They aren't numbers, however. Trichotomy joined hands. His work indeed gave infinitesimals a foun- fails, for example. dation as members of the set of hyperreai numbers. But it The central construction in this article is a rediscovery. was an awkward foundation, dependent on the Axiom of Its first discoverer probably was D. Laugwitz. More on this Choice. Unlike standard number systems, there is no later. canonical set of hyperreal numbers. There is a way, however, of constructing infinitesimals Notation. We denote a sequence {an}nE ~ by a boldface naturally. Ironically, the seeds can be found in any calcu- a. We permit as to be undefined for fmitely many n. The lus book of sufficient age. At the turn of the century, it was key idea throughout is that of "from some point on." An typical of texts to define an infinitesimal as a "variable equation or inequality involving sequences will be in- whose limit is zero" [C]. That is the inspiration for the terpreted as being true or false, depending on whether present approach to calculus. Its infmitesimals are se- the associated equation or inequality involving the terms quences tending to 0. of the sequences is true or false from some point on. I call the system "non-nonstandard analysis" to draw at- For example, tention to its misfit nature. Having infinitesimals, it is not a>2 @ 1999 SPRINGERWERLAG NEW YORK, VOLUME 21, NUMBER 1, 1999 67 simply means "an > 2 from some point on," that is, that Proposition 1. Suppose a, b ~ 0. Then for some k, n -> k implies that an > 2. We use ordinary (1) a + b ~ 0. letters for real numbers. Note that a real number r can (2) a - b ~ 0. be viewed as the sequence a, with an = r for all n. (3) If e is finite, then ac ~ 0. (4) If Icl < lal, then e ~ O. Equations and inequalities involving sequences are inter- preted in the same way; that is, a + b = c means an § bn = PROOF. Given any positive d, we know that lal < d/2 and Cn from some point on, and sin(a) = b means sin(an) = bn Ibt < d/2. Then, la + b I -< lal + Ibl < d. Thisproves Part (1). from some point on. Note that forf(a) to be defined, it is Part (2) is proved similarly. only necessary that f(an) be defined from some point on. For Part (3), because Icl < r for some real r, and lal < The sequence b: 0, 0, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4,..., for example, does d/r for all positive d, we have lacl < d. have a reciprocal, I/b, because, as noted, finitely many For Part (4), observe that because lel < lal < d, Icl terms of a sequence may be undefined. <d. 9 If a statement P is true from some point on and state- ment Q is also true from some point on, then "P and Q" is Note that reals are finite, so that any result concerning fi- true from some point on. This fact allows us to do algebra nite sequences applies to reals too. Part (3) of Proposition l, on sequences. for example, tells us that if a ~ 0, then ra ~ 0 for any real r. Suppose, for example, we have a+4=3b Definition. For sequences a and b, we say that a and b are infinitely close, or a ~ b, iff a - b ~ 0. and c <45. Proposition 2. If a ~- r and b ~- s, then (1) a+b~r+s. Then, (2) a- b ~ r- s. (3) ab ~ rs. an + 4 = 3bn, from some point on, (4) If a -< s, then r -< s. and (5) a + b ~ r/s, if s r O. Cn < 45, from some point on. PROOF. Parts (1) and (2) follow easily from Proposition 1. Because the two are true together from some point on, For Part (3), note that (a-r)s, (b-s)r, and we can add them to get (a - r)(b - s) are all ~ 0. Adding these gives us ab - rs ~ O. an + 4 + Cn < 3bn + 45, from some point on. For Part (4), if r > s, then we would have both an -< s from some pont on and lan- r I < (r- s)/2 from some In other words, point on, which is impossible. a+4+c<3b+45. In view of Part (3), we need only show lfo ~ 1/s to establish Part (5). From s ~ b, we get Is~21 ~ Ib/21 < Ibl, so What we are doing, with this construction, is taking the by Part (4), Is~21 -< Ibl. Then I1/b - 1/s I = I(s - b)/bs I -< equivalence classes of sequences under the relation "equal- (1/Is/21)(1/Isb]s- b I. By Proposition 1, this is infinitesi- ity from some point on." To present it in that way, how- mal. 9 ever, would entail excessive formalism. One of my pur- This is all we need to get started. poses is to demonstrate that there is a fairly simple approach to infmitesimals, one that can reasonably be pre- Elementary Calculus sented to ordinary calculus students. Definition 1. A function f is continuous at x = r, r real, Infinitely Small and Infinitely Close iff Definition. A sequence a is infinitely small if lal < d a~rimpliesf(a)~f(r). for all positive real numbers d. For infinitely small a, we write a ~ 0. If lal < r for some real r, we say a is finite Equivalently, f is continuous at r if Ax ~ 0 implies or bounded. A sequence a is infinitesimal if a r 0 and f(r + Ax) -f(r) ~ O. a~0. We can also discuss continuity at a sequence a, as op- These definitions hide quantifiers. When we say that a r posed to a real r, but continuity on a set X corresponds to 0, we are actually saying that there is a k such that an r 0 continuity at all real numbers in X. As in nonstandard analy- for all n --> k. Similarly, this defmition of a ~ 0 is, in real- sis, continuity at all points (real numbers and sequences) ity, the more familiar and complicated Ve > 0 3k, n ~ k in a set X is equivalent to uniform continuity. I will prove lanl < e. this later. (}8 THE MATHEMATICAL INTELLIGENCER Proposition 3. The sum, difference, product, and quo- Definition 3. a is a subsequence of b (written a C b) if tient (when the divisor is nonzero) of functions contin- every term of a is a term of b; more precisely, if there is uous at x = r are continuous at x = r. an increasing function, k : N ~ N such that a n = bk(n). This follows easily from Proposition 2. Proposition 6. Let a C b be given. (1) Ifb is infinitesimal, then so is a. (2) If b ~ r, then a ~ r. Definition 2. For a functionfand a real r, we sayf'(r) = d iff for all infinitesimal Ax, (3) Ifb satisfies a given equation or inequality, then so does a. f(r + Ax) -f(r) ~ d. Ax The proof of this is routine. Here is what the computation looks like of the standard Proposition 7. (The Chain Rule). If y =fix) and z = first example: f(x) = x 2. g(y), then dz/dx = (dz/dy) 9(dy/dx). (x + Ax) 2 - x 2 x 2 - 2xAx + Ax 2 - x 2 Ax Ax PROOF. For Ax infinitesimal, dy/dx ~ Ay/Ax, where Ay = 2xAx + AX 2 f(x + Ax)-fix). By Proposition 4, Ay ~0, so seemingly Ax Az/Ay --~ dz/dy, where Az = g(y + Ay) -- g(y). But there is = 2x + Ax another way to write Az, since g(y + Ay) - g(y) = g(f(x) + ~2X. Ay) - g(f(x)) = g(f(x + Ax)) - g(f(x)), so dz/dx ~ Az/h,x. Proposition 4. If f is differentiable at r, it is continuous Putting this together, at r. dz Az Az Ay ~ dz dy PROOF. Just multiply dx Ax Ay Ax dy dx" The only difficulty with this is that Ay, while infinitely close f(r + Ax) - f(r) ~ d and Ax --~ O to 0, may not be infinitesimal because it may equal 0 infi- Ax nitely often. In that case, we can't claim that dz/dy .~ to get Az/Ay, because the definition of derivative requires Aye 0. f(r + Ax) -f(r) ~ 0. 9 But then, let Ax* C Ax be the subsequence such that The proofs of the differentiation rules are simple. The the corresponding Ay* is a sequence entirely composed of product rule is typical: O's. Then, dy/dx ~ Ay*/Ax* = 0. And, because Ay* = 0, the corresponding Az* = g(y + Ay*)- g(y) is also 0, so Proposition 5.
Recommended publications
  • An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis 11
    AN INTRODUCTION TO NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS ISAAC DAVIS Abstract. In this paper we give an introduction to nonstandard analysis, starting with an ultrapower construction of the hyperreals. We then demon- strate how theorems in standard analysis \transfer over" to nonstandard anal- ysis, and how theorems in standard analysis can be proven using theorems in nonstandard analysis. 1. Introduction For many centuries, early mathematicians and physicists would solve problems by considering infinitesimally small pieces of a shape, or movement along a path by an infinitesimal amount. Archimedes derived the formula for the area of a circle by thinking of a circle as a polygon with infinitely many infinitesimal sides [1]. In particular, the construction of calculus was first motivated by this intuitive notion of infinitesimal change. G.W. Leibniz's derivation of calculus made extensive use of “infinitesimal” numbers, which were both nonzero but small enough to add to any real number without changing it noticeably. Although intuitively clear, infinitesi- mals were ultimately rejected as mathematically unsound, and were replaced with the common -δ method of computing limits and derivatives. However, in 1960 Abraham Robinson developed nonstandard analysis, in which the reals are rigor- ously extended to include infinitesimal numbers and infinite numbers; this new extended field is called the field of hyperreal numbers. The goal was to create a system of analysis that was more intuitively appealing than standard analysis but without losing any of the rigor of standard analysis. In this paper, we will explore the construction and various uses of nonstandard analysis. In section 2 we will introduce the notion of an ultrafilter, which will allow us to do a typical ultrapower construction of the hyperreal numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Managing Editor
    Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Managing Editor: M. HAZEWINKEL Centre for Mathematics and Computer Science, Amsterdam, The Netherlands Volume 525 Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Edited by S.S. Kutateladze Sobolev Institute of Mathematics. Siberian Division of the Russian Academy of Sciences. Novosibirsk. Russia SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B. V. A C.LP. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-94-010-5863-6 ISBN 978-94-011-4305-9 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-4305-9 This is an updated translation of the original Russian work. Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices, A.E. Gutman, \'E.Yu. Emelyanov, A.G. Kusraev and S.S. Kutateladze. Novosibirsk, Sobolev Institute Press, 1999. The book was typeset using AMS-TeX. Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved ©2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2000 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. Contents Foreword ix Chapter 1. Nonstandard Methods and Kantorovich Spaces (A. G. Kusraev and S. S. Kutateladze) 1 § 1.l. Zermelo-Fraenkel Set·Theory 5 § l.2. Boolean Valued Set Theory 7 § l.3. Internal and External Set Theories 12 § 1.4. Relative Internal Set Theory 18 § l.5. Kantorovich Spaces 23 § l.6. Reals Inside Boolean Valued Models 26 § l.7. Functional Calculus in Kantorovich Spaces 30 § l.8.
    [Show full text]
  • Infinitesimal Methods in Mathematical Economics
    Infinitesimal Methods in Mathematical Economics Robert M. Anderson1 Department of Economics and Department of Mathematics University of California at Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720, U.S.A. and Department of Economics Johns Hopkins University Baltimore, MD 21218, U.S.A. January 20, 2008 1The author is grateful to Marc Bettz¨uge, Don Brown, Hung- Wen Chang, G´erard Debreu, Eddie Dekel-Tabak, Greg Engl, Dmitri Ivanov, Jerry Keisler, Peter Loeb, Paul MacMillan, Mike Magill, Andreu Mas-Colell, Max Stinchcombe, Cathy Wein- berger and Bill Zame for their helpful comments. Financial sup- port from Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, Gottfried-Wilhelm- Leibniz-F¨orderpreis is gratefully acknowledged. Contents 0Preface v 1 Nonstandard Analysis Lite 1 1.1 When is Nonstandard Analysis Useful? . 1 1.1.1 Large Economies . 2 1.1.2 Continuum of Random Variables . 4 1.1.3 Searching For Elementary Proofs . 4 1.2IdealElements................. 5 1.3Ultraproducts.................. 6 1.4InternalandExternalSets........... 9 1.5NotationalConventions............. 11 1.6StandardModels................ 12 1.7 Superstructure Embeddings . 14 1.8AFormalLanguage............... 16 1.9TransferPrinciple................ 16 1.10Saturation.................... 18 1.11InternalDefinitionPrinciple.......... 19 1.12 Nonstandard Extensions, or Enough Already with the Ultraproducts . 20 1.13HyperfiniteSets................. 21 1.14 Nonstandard Theorems Have Standard Proofs 22 2 Nonstandard Analysis Regular 23 2.1 Warning: Do Not Read this Chapter . 23 i ii CONTENTS 2.2AFormalLanguage............... 23 2.3 Extensions of L ................. 25 2.4 Assigning Truth Value to Formulas . 28 2.5 Interpreting Formulas in Superstructure Em- beddings..................... 32 2.6TransferPrinciple................ 33 2.7InternalDefinitionPrinciple.......... 34 2.8NonstandardExtensions............ 35 2.9TheExternalLanguage............. 36 2.10TheConservationPrinciple.......... 37 3RealAnalysis 39 3.1Monads..................... 39 3.2OpenandClosedSets............. 44 3.3Compactness.................
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis
    Nonstandard Analysis Armin Straub Technische Universität Darmstadt Dec 10, 2007 Contents 1 Introduction........................ ............ 2 1.1 Approaches to Getting Infinitesimals . 2 1.2 The Use of Infinitesimals . ... 5 2 Diving In....................... ............... 6 2.1 Limits and Ultrafilters ........................ .... 6 2.2 A First Nonstandard Peak . ...... 9 2.3 An Axiomatic Approach . ..... 11 2.4 Basic Usage . ............. 12 2.5 The Source of Nonstandard Strength . 16 2.6 Stronger Nonstandard Models . .. 17 2.7 Studying Z in its Own Right . .. 19 3 Conclusions....................... ............ 20 References....................... ............... 21 Abstract These notes complement a seminar talk I gave as a student at TU Darm- stadt as part of the StuVo (Studentische Vortragsreihe), Dec 10, 2007. While this text is meant to be informal in nature, any corrections as well as suggestions are very welcome. We discuss some ways to add infinitesimals to our usual numbers, get acquainted with ultrafilters and how they can be used to construct nonstandard extensions, and then provide an axiomatic framework for nonstandard analysis. As basic working examples we present nonstan- dard characterizations of continuity and uniform continuity. We close with a short external look at the nonstandard integers and point out connections withp-adic integers. 1 2 Nonstandard Analysis 1 Introduction 1.1 Approaches to Getting Infinitesimals One aspect of nonstandard analysis is that it introduces a new kind of numbers, namely infinitely large numbers (and hence infinitesimally small ones as well). This is something that may be philosophically challenging to a Platonist. It's not just that we are talking about infinity but its quality here is of a particular kind.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1210.7750V1 [Math.HO] 29 Oct 2012 Tsml Ehdo Aiaadmnm;Rfato;Selslaw
    ALMOST EQUAL: THE METHOD OF ADEQUALITY FROM DIOPHANTUS TO FERMAT AND BEYOND MIKHAIL G. KATZ, DAVID M. SCHAPS, AND STEVEN SHNIDER Abstract. We analyze some of the main approaches in the liter- ature to the method of ‘adequality’ with which Fermat approached the problems of the calculus, as well as its source in the παρισoτης´ of Diophantus, and propose a novel reading thereof. Adequality is a crucial step in Fermat’s method of finding max- ima, minima, tangents, and solving other problems that a mod- ern mathematician would solve using infinitesimal calculus. The method is presented in a series of short articles in Fermat’s col- lected works [66, p. 133-172]. We show that at least some of the manifestations of adequality amount to variational techniques ex- ploiting a small, or infinitesimal, variation e. Fermat’s treatment of geometric and physical applications sug- gests that an aspect of approximation is inherent in adequality, as well as an aspect of smallness on the part of e. We question the rel- evance to understanding Fermat of 19th century dictionary defini- tions of παρισoτης´ and adaequare, cited by Breger, and take issue with his interpretation of adequality, including his novel reading of Diophantus, and his hypothesis concerning alleged tampering with Fermat’s texts by Carcavy. We argue that Fermat relied on Bachet’s reading of Diophantus. Diophantus coined the term παρισoτης´ for mathematical pur- poses and used it to refer to the way in which 1321/711 is ap- proximately equal to 11/6. Bachet performed a semantic calque in passing from pariso¯o to adaequo.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructive Nonstandard Analysis Without Actual Infinity
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto CONSTRUCTIVE NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS WITHOUT ACTUAL INFINITY JUHA RUOKOLAINEN Academic dissertation To be presented, with the permission of the Faculty of Science of the University of Helsinki, for public criticism in Auditorium III, Porthania, on May 15th, 2004, at 10 a.m. UNIVERSITY OF HELSINKI FACULTY OF SCIENCE DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS AND STATISTICS HELSINKI 2004 ISBN 952-91-7140-4 (paperback) ISBN 952-10-1822-4 (PDF) YLIOPISTOPAINO HELSINKI 2004 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Framework 5 2.1 Formal Systems HA and HA∗ . 5 2.2 Conversion of Proofs of HA∗ into Proofs of HA . 6 2.3 Finite Sets . 9 3 Finite Elementary Analysis in HA∗ 13 3.1 On Notation . 13 3.2 Real Numbers . 13 3.3 Finite Sequences and Series of Real Numbers . 17 3.4 Subsets and Functions . 26 3.5 Differentiation . 32 3.6 Riemann Integration . 38 3.7 Finite Sequences of Functions . 42 3.8 Taylor’s Theorem . 44 3.9 Some Elementary Functions . 46 3.10 Ordinary First Order Differential Equations . 51 p 4 Finite L -Spaces in HA∗ 55 5 Finite Probability Spaces in HA∗ 67 5.1 Basic Notions . 67 5.2 On Laws of Large Numbers . 72 5.3 A Derivation of the Black-Scholes Formula . 77 6 Examples of the Conversion Algorithm 85 References 89 1 Introduction At least from the computational point of view we can only possess and process a finite amount of finitely precise information in a finitely long period of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Student Conceptions About Infinitesimals
    Journal for Research in Mathematics Education 2010, Vol. 41, No. 2, 117–146 Nonstandard Student Conceptions About Infinitesimals Robert Ely University of Idaho This is a case study of an undergraduate calculus student’s nonstandard conceptions of the real number line. Interviews with the student reveal robust conceptions of the real number line that include infinitesimal and infinite quantities and distances. Similarities between these conceptions and those of G. W. Leibniz are discussed and illuminated by the formalization of infinitesimals in A. Robinson’s nonstandard analysis. These similarities suggest that these student conceptions are not mere misconceptions, but are nonstandard conceptions, pieces of knowledge that could be built into a system of real numbers proven to be as mathematically consistent and powerful as the standard system. This provides a new perspective on students’ “strug- gles” with the real numbers, and adds to the discussion about the relationship between student conceptions and historical conceptions by focusing on mechanisms for main- taining cognitive and mathematical consistency. Key words: Advanced mathematical thinking; College/university; Constructivism; Historical analysis; Learning theories The conclusions we reach when we research student thinking are highly influ- enced by the way we regard a conception that differs from the standard ones held by communities of mathematicians. If we treat such a conception as a mere miscon- ception, as a simple lack of knowledge or as an incorrect idea that should be eradicated, then we may miss some important aspects of how that conception func- tions within a student’s understanding. This article offers an extreme example of how examining the functionality and structure of a student’s conceptions, rather than dismissing these conceptions as misconceptions, reveals a meaningful struc- ture to the student’s conceptions that otherwise might have been overlooked.
    [Show full text]
  • NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS and TOPOLOGY 1. a Little History
    NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS AND TOPOLOGY MIHAIL HURMUZOV Abstract. In this survey we present the machinery of nonstandard analysis. We introduce the axiomatic approach and develop the classi- cal construction of the nonstandard extension through ultrafilters. The main content of the survey is the nonstandard characterisation of topo- logical concepts, culminating with a treatment of compactifications. 1. A little history Calculus, as originally conceived by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, involved infinitesimals. For reasons of mathematical rigour, however, this approach to analysis has been substituted for one using limits that is due largely to Cauchy and Weierstrass. Almost 300 years after the invention of calculus a rigourous way to deal with infinitesimals emerges in Abraham Robinson’s nonstandard analysis. Although it was initially developed through a model theoretic approach in the early 60s [5], others, such as Wilhelmus Luxem- burg [4], showed that the same results could be achieved using ultrafilters. This made Robinson’s work more accessible to mathematicians who lacked training in formal logic. (The ultrafilter construction that is presented here in 2.2 is a particular case of this idea.) One of the most popular among researchers applying the nonstandard methods is the axiomatic approach. The three axioms – Extension, Trans- fer, and Saturation – arise from the close historical connection to model theory and mathematical logic. The ultrapower construction can be viewed as either a proof of the consistency of the axioms or as an independent ap- proach to building the theory. We will present the axioms with the basic concepts in 2.1, then we give an overview of the construction of a nonstan- dard extension of a mathematical universe V .
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis Simplified
    NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS - A SIMPLIFIED APPROACH - ROBERT A. HERRMANN arXiv:math/0310351v6 [math.GM] 5 Oct 2010 1 Nonstandard Analysis Simplified Copyright c 2003 by Robert A. Herrmann 2 Nonstandard Analysis Simplified CONTENTS Chapter 1 Filters Ultrafilters, Cofinite Filter, Principle Ultrafilters, Free Ultrafilters ................................. 6. Chapter 2 A Simple Nonstandard Model for Analysis Equivalence Classes of Sequences, Totally Ordered Field of Equivalence Classes, The Hyper-extension of Sets and Relations, The Standard Object Generator .................................... 9. Chapter 3 Hyper-set Algebra Infinite and Infinitesimal Numbers The Behavior of the Hyper and Standard Object Generators; Infinitesimals µ(0), The Infinite and Finite Numbers, *-Transform Process, Maximum Ideal µ(0)................ 15. Chapter 4 Basic Sequential Convergence Bounded Sequences, Convergent Sequences, Accumulation Point, Subsequences, Cauchy Criterion, Nonstandard Characteristics and Examples ....................... 23 Chapter 5 Advanced Sequential Convergence Double Sequences, Iterated Limits, Upper and Lower Limits, Nonstandard Characteristics and Examples ................................... 28. Chapter 6 Basic Infinite Series Hyperfinite Summation, Standard Results, Nonstandard Characteristics and Examples ...................... 33. Chapter 7 An Advance Infinite Series Concept Multiplying of Infinite Series, Nonstandard Characteristics and Examples ................... 37. Chapter 8 Additional Real Number Properties Interior, Closure, Cluster, Accumulation,
    [Show full text]
  • The Teaching of Elementary Calculus Using the Nonstandard Analysis Approach Author(S): Kathleen Sullivan Source: the American Mathematical Monthly, Vol
    The Teaching of Elementary Calculus Using the Nonstandard Analysis Approach Author(s): Kathleen Sullivan Source: The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 83, No. 5 (May, 1976), pp. 370-375 Published by: Mathematical Association of America Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2318657 . Accessed: 10/03/2014 11:41 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Mathematical Association of America is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Mathematical Monthly. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 132.70.4.118 on Mon, 10 Mar 2014 11:41:19 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions MATHEMATICAL EDUCATION EDITED BY PAUL T. MIELKE AND SHIRLEY HILL Materialfor this Department should be sentto Paul T. Mielke,Department of Mathematics, Wabash College, Crawfordsville,IN 47933, or to ShirleyHill, Departmentof Mathematics,University of Missouri,Kansas City,MO 64110. PEAKS, RIDGE, PASSES, VALLEY AND PITS A Slide Study of f(x,y)=Ax2+By2 CLIFF LONG The adventof computer graphics is makingit possible to payheed to thesuggestion, "a pictureis wortha thousandwords." As studentsand teachers of mathematics we shouldbecome more aware of thevariational approach to certainmathematical concepts, and considerpresenting these concepts througha sequenceof computergenerated pictures.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis of Dynamical Systems
    transactions of the american mathematical society Volume 160, October 1971 NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS OF DYNAMICAL SYSTEMS. I: LIMIT MOTIONS, STABILITY!;1) BY A. E. HURD Abstract. The methods of nonstandard analysis are applied to the study of the qualitative theory of dynamical systems. The nonstandard notions connected with limiting behavior of motions (limit sets, etc.) are developed, and then applied to the study of stability theory, including stability of sets, attracting properties, first pro- longations and stability of motions. 0. Introduction. Nonstandard analysis originated in 1960 when A. Robinson developed a logical procedure whereby the usual limiting operations of the calculus could be dealt with using a language of infinitesimals and indefinitely large quanti- ties similar to that employed by Leibniz and other early developers of the calculus [7]. In order to do this Robinson imbedded the real numbers R in a larger structure *R which shared all of the formal properties of R that could be expressed in the lower predicate calculus, and which contained infinitesimals and infinitely large quantities (and hence was non-archimedean). The enlargment *R was shown to exist using the compactness principle of the lower predicate calculus (but an explicit construction for *R can be given using ultrafilters [4]). Since Robinson's first paper nonstandard analysis has developed in many directions. Three books ([4], [5], [8]) and a recent symposium [2] have been devoted to the subject. W. A. J. Luxemburg has developed the ultrafilter techniques which in particular show the power of saturation in the construction of enlargements [3]. It is now clear that many branches of analysis can be profitably developed using nonstandard analysis as a tool.
    [Show full text]