Philosophy and the Analytic-Continental Divide, 17.2-3

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy and the Analytic-Continental Divide, 17.2-3 claim. Analytic philosophers are not much interested in In : 1993 in Stanford French Review, Special number: Philosophy and the either defining or defending the presuppositions of their Analytic-Continental Divide, 17.2-3, ed. Pascal Engel, 133-150. work. Indeed the gap between "analytic" and "non-analytic" philosophy nowadays coincides pretty closely with the division between philosophers who are not interested in POST-CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY. historico-metaphilosophical reflections on their own activity NOSOLOGICAL NOTES* and philosophers who are...2 Kevin Mulligan I should like in this essay to furnish some of the connections between nosology and history that will enable us to understand how Continental Philosophy came to occupy the §1 An Analysis position it did and what we may now look forward to. §2 A History §3 An Example: Musil, not Dewey §1 An Analysis By "Continental philosophy" (CP) I mean the sort of Born 80 years ago, Continental Philosophy is on its last philosophy produced by or in the wake of philosophers such as legs. Its extraordinary career has been helped along by an almost Husserl, Heidegger and Adorno, Habermas and Apel, Sartre and total absence of interest on the part of analytic or other exact L‚vinas, Foucault, Lacan, Althusser, Lyotard, Deleuze and Derrida, philosophers in what the Australian philosopher David Stove calls Severino and Vattimo. Skew to such a characterisation in terms of "the nosology of philosophy"1, the exploration of the manifold proper names there is also the possibility of characterising CP in forms taken by bad philosophy. Stove points out that such an terms of movements and tendencies such as "Critical Theory", enterprise involves doing history. A nosology of Continental "Decontructionism", "Structuralism", "Neo-Structuralism", "Feeble Philosophy is, at least in the first instance, inseparable from philosophy" (filosofia debole), many varieties of feminist and the history of this strand in twentieth century philosophy, a marxist thought and "Theory" tout court, pregnant like the Irish history which would make clear the relations, philosophical and bull, widespread and proudly unqualified. historical, between it and exact philosophy. Rorty is quite right to point to the absence of such a historical perspective: CP is in many ways an Anglo-American creation. It is by no means identical with philosophy on the continent, analytic or non- Analytic philosophy has pretty well closed itself off from analytic, continental philosophy. Nor is the term much used or contact with non-analytic philosophy and lives in its own understood on the continent. But it is true that since an enormous world. The scientistic aproach to philosophy which Husserl proportion of philosophers on the continent are actually shared with Carnap lives on, forming a tacit presupposition historians of philosophy the figures mentioned would have to of the work of analytic philosophers. Even though analytic figure prominently in any account of philosophy done on the philosophy now describes itself as post-positivistic, the continent. idea that philosophy "analyses" or "describes" some ahistorical formal "structures" - an idea common to Husserl, The contrasts between the way CP has been done and the way Russell, Carnap and Ryle - persists. However, there is little Analytic Philosophy is done are familiar. Analytic philosophy is explicit metaphilosophical defense or development of this first and foremost the culture of the argument, of the objection, of the distinction, of description, examples and counter-examples, even of theory construction. Whatever an analytic philosopher's * This essay complements Mulligan 1990 & 1991 and summarizes a series of lectures, Superficialities and other actual views about philosophy and science his practise almost Holes: Analytic vs Continental Philosophy (the Agnes Cumings Lectures), given at University College, Dublin, invariably exemplifies a severely theoretical attitude. in May 1992. I am grateful to Dermot Moran, Richard Kearney and others in Dublin for their comments. Thanks also to Jack Smart for putting me right about the correct Australian line on nosology and to Paul Mullen. On the topic of this essay, see the papers in Mulligan (ed.) 1991. CP, on the other hand, is melodramatic. The melodrama begins with the strident oppositions between organic Kultur and dead 1 Stove 1991, 188. Stove emphasizes that "we have as yet scarcely the glimmerings of...a nosology of human Zivilisation in Germany in the twenties. Heidegger accuses the thought" (187) although identification of examples of the pathology of human thought is so easy. He is also entire Western tradition of failing to see that the meaning of concerned to show how such examples can be found even in the writings of very good philosophers. Being involves more than mere presence. Derrida's version of this 2 Rorty 1991, II, 21. But see Skorupski 1991. melodrama is slightly more precise: the special case of the structuralist ideas, Hegelian anthropology and Freud. Habermas and ideology of presence he denounces with great eloquence is the Apel combine certain traditional moves within transcendental privilege accorded to speech and the "repression" of writing. philosophy with bits and pieces of analytic philosophy, Ethnocentrism and logocentrism "control" the concept of writing; particularly ideas from that part of the philosophy of language writing is seen as a "contamination"; it is "subversive", that deals with pragmatics. "Quelle salade !", Sartre rightly "feared". And in general the philosopher who sees through one or noted, might well be the reaction to Being and Nothingness. another of these great illusions requires above all great courage. "Syncretism", in one of its senses, is a pejorative term. But CP contains few examples of the pursuit of a thesis, of an of course the fact that a philosopher combines two or more ideas, increase in the understanding of a position. It is very rare to however distinct their provenance, is never by itself a bad thing. find a claim that has been modified as the result of discussion by It is completely unimportant where a good idea comes from. a number of philosophers. Positions are elaborated and then Syncretic philosophy is bad philosophy only when it is combined jettisoned. This lack of any continuing dialectics in CP may be with the illness I called under-determination: in particular, it held to count in favour of the view that it is a spurious entity, is only when the links between philosophemes from very different a product perhaps of the North American job market. But this would traditions or heterogenous sources - eg topology and Freud - are be to underestimate the extent to which there really is not made out that we get the characteristically Continental disagreement and opposition within CP - think of Sartre vs Lévi- variety of free association of ideas. Strauss and Foucault, Gadamer vs Habermas or Deleuze and Guattari vs Lacan. The trappings of disagreement are there. But there is CP almost invariably has politically progressive allures. It very little precise controversy. This is due, amongst other is often politically melodramatic. This is obviously the case for things, to another feature of CP. the more directly political philosophies within CP such as the anarchisms of Deleuze and Lyotard, the Marxism of Althusser or the CP contains few examples, and less arguments. Positions connexions between hermeneutical philosophy and emancipation in are under-described and under-argued, that is, under-determined. Habermas' philosophy. More surprising is the way in which Again and again one finds that the meaning of key terms remains feminists have taken seriously what they see as the political vague because they are not introduced with the help of lower order potential, progressive or not, of Lacan, and the way examples. A fortiori, the notion of a counter-example remains deconstruction has been taken to provide the means to bring out unknown. It is often held that detailed criticism is completely the reactionary nature of this or that canon. But argued, beside the point. This feature of CP goes together with another rationalist, left-wing political philosophy remains, alas, a one. rarety. CP is problem free. Positions that are systematically One example must suffice to illustrate these claims. Consider underdetermined can never achieve the sort of focus that comes the history of the concept of structure within French CP. I refer from pursuing a particular problem throughout the twists and turns to its use by avowed structuralists such as L‚vi-Strauss in his of the different arguments for and against different solutions. philosophical moments, its rôle in the criticisms of structuralism This type of underdetermination is quite compatible with another by for example Sartre and also to its rôle within Lacan's system feature of CP which lends to its texts and positions what and in the quite different alternatives to structuralism that go determination they do have. under the heading of post-structuralism and, for example, to its use by Derrida. In nearly all these cases it appears that the CP is done by doing the History of Philosophy. A philosophers in question not only did not know what a structure is Continental Philosopher typically elaborates his views in the form but, a point almost as important, did not seem to be really of a commentary on, criticism or application of the views of one interested in finding out. One finds simply the obligatory and or more of the great philosophers of the tradition3. cursory references back to Jakobson and to Levi-Strauss' applications of mathematical structures. Now the concept of a CP is syncretic. Thus a handful of ideas from semiology linguistic or non-linguistic structure suggests all sorts of and structuralism have been combined with a variety of philosophical questions: What sort of relation holds between the philosophical positions. Lacan managed to yoke together members of a contrast class and the sentence frame or frames that yields the class ? Is it an internal relation ? If so, what sort of internal relation ? What are the differences between the terms 3 On the background to this, see Smith 1991.
Recommended publications
  • Top 5 QS World China University University Ranking Ranking
    No.60 Top 5 QS World China University University Ranking Ranking Undergraduate Engineering Cluster Program in English for International Students Founded in 1896, Shanghai Jiao Tong University (SJTU) is one of the internationally recognized, top-tier research universities in China, with strong commitment to nurturing future leaders with innovative drives and global visions. The Engineering Cluster Program is a new undergraduate international program designed to combine the strengths of engineering-related fields at SJTU. Offering all major courses in English or French, the Cluster Program welcomes prospective students with an interest in engineering studies from all over the world. Undergraduate Engineering Cluster Program in English The SJTU Undergraduate Engineering Cluster program in English includes: Cluster students will take introductory > The University of Michigan-Shanghai Jiao Tong University (UM-SJTU) Joint engineering courses in the first 1.5 years at the Institute (JI) UM-SJTU Joint Institute. After meeting this > The School of Materials Science and Engineering requirement, Cluster students may choose to continue their studies at the UM-SJTU Joint > The School of Electronic, Information and Electrical Engineering, Institute or transfer to another engineering Information Engineering school (in English or Chinese) to complete > The School of Naval Architecture, Ocean and Civil Engineering their bachelor’s degree. > The School of Mechanical Engineering Reminder: Although all Cluster courses are The Cluster Program covers various engineering-related disciplines such as: taught in English, Cluster students are required to take Chinese culture and language > Mechanical Engineering courses while enrolling in their respective > Electrical and Computer Engineering degree programs. All Cluster students are > Materials Science and Engineering expected to meet HSK 4 (Chinese Language > Computer Science and Technology Test) as the minimum Chinese language > Information Engineering requirement for graduation.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in the Kant Yearbook, Vol. 11 (2019) Final Draft – Please Cite the Published Version for Correct Pagination
    Forthcoming in The Kant Yearbook, Vol. 11 (2019) Final Draft – Please cite the published version for correct pagination Can there be a Finite Interpretation of the Kantian Sublime? Sacha Golob (King’s College London) Abstract Kant’s account of the sublime makes frequent appeals to infinity, appeals which have been extensively criticised by commentators such as Budd and Crowther. This paper examines the costs and benefits of reconstructing the account in finitist terms. On the one hand, drawing on a detailed comparison of the first and third Critiques, I argue that the underlying logic of Kant’s position is essentially finitist. I defend the approach against longstanding objections, as well as addressing recent infinitist work by Moore and Smith. On the other hand, however, I argue that finitism faces distinctive problems of its own: whilst the resultant theory is a coherent and interesting one, it is unclear in what sense it remains an analysis of the sublime. I illustrate the worry by juxtaposing the finitist reading with analytical cubism. §1 – Introduction Kant’s account of the sublime makes frequent reference to infinity. The “intuition” of the sublime “carries with it the idea of...infinity”; apprehension “can progress to infinity” [kann…ins Unendliche gehen]; imagination “strives to progress towards infinity” [ein Bestreben zum Fortschritte ins Unendliche]; reason demands that we “think the infinite as a whole” (KU 5:255, 252, 250, 254).1 It is obvious that the infinite played a central role in Kant’s own presentation of the problem. It is less clear whether such references are 1 References are to the standard Akademie edition of Kant’s gesammelte Schriften (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1900–; abbreviated as Ak.): Anth: Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht (Ak.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Paul Ricoeur's Philosophy of Action
    International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Volume 7 • Number 11 • November 2017 Why the Reality is Not Totalisable: An Introduction to Paul Ricoeur’s Philosophy of Action Vinicio Busacchi Associate Professor of Theoretical Philosophy University of Cagliari Via Is Mirrionis 1 – 09100 Cagliari, Italy Abstract This article the matises Ricoeur’s speculative parcours around the philosophy of action. It starts by offering a perspective on French (Continental) philosophy’s contribution to the Philosophy of Action. The roles played by Sartre and Merleau-Ponty’s existential phenomenology, and the Structure lists are particularly emphasised, including references to Ricoeur’s speculative researches. These Ricoeurian developments can be connected under a general anthropological perspective, creating a double (productive) implication: (1) to recognise a new interpretative key for the Ricoeurian parcours, and (2) to find a new (Ricoeurian) way to defend the idea of the gnoseological and epistemological impossibility that considers the reality of the world as a comprehensive knowledge. Keywords: Action, Reality, Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, Anthropology Introduction Philosophy of action’s continued significance and use in contemporary French philosophy primarily depends on the phenomenological (phenomenological-existential) tradition, as well as philosophical hermeneutics and structuralism. Within this framework, philosophy of action is defined as a broad inter-discipline or inter- dominion, ranging from the general practical philosophy to existentialism, and covering such diverse fields as pragmatism, philosophy of mind and language, structuralism and linguistics, anthropology, sociology, and beyond. The general philosophy of action had its first speculative articulation in the Francophone area. The philosophical-religious work carried out in the mid-nineteenth century by Léon Ollé-Laprune and Maurice Blondel turned the focus of the field to the moral idealism of action (Fichte).
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Dean Franklin Moyar Department of Philosophy Johns Hopkins University 276 Gilman Hall 3400 N. Charles St. Baltimore, MD 21218 [email protected] Professional Experience 2009-present: Associate Professor (with tenure), Department of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins University. 2002-2009: Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins University. Areas AOS: Kant and German Idealism, Political Philosophy, Metaethics. AOC: Philosophy of Law, Philosophy of Action, 19th Century European Philosophy, Early Modern Philosophy, American Philosophy. Education 1994-2002 University of Chicago, Ph.D. June 2002. 1999-2000 Visiting Scholar, Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität, Münster, Germany. 1990-1994 Duke University. B.S. Summa Cum Laude with Honors in Physics. Second major in Philosophy. Monograph Hegel’s Conscience (Oxford University Press, 2011, paperback 2014). Edited Volumes The Oxford Handbook of Hegel, Editor (forthcoming, 2017). The Routledge Companion to Nineteenth Century Philosophy, Editor (Routledge, 2010). Winner, CHOICE award, 2010. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Critical Guide, Co-Editor with Michael Quante (Cambridge University Press, 2008). Journal Articles and Book Chapters “German Idealism,” Knowledge in Early Modern Philosophy, edited by Stephen Gaukroger, (forthcoming, Bloomsbury, 2017) “Die Wahrheit der mechanistischen und teleologischen Objektivität,” for a collective commentary on the Science of Logic, edited by Michael Quante and Anton Koch (forthcoming from Meiner Verlag, 2017). “Introduction” to The Oxford Handbook
    [Show full text]
  • CRITICAL THEORY Past, Present, Future Anders Bartonek and Sven-Olov Wallensein (Eds.) SÖDERTÖRN PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
    CRITICAL THEORY Past, Present, Future Anders Bartonek and Sven-Olov Wallensein (eds.) SÖDERTÖRN PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES The series is attached to Philosophy at Sder- trn University. Published in the series are es- says as well as anthologies, with a particular em- phasis on the continental tradition, understood in its broadest sense, from German idealism to phenomenology, hermeneutics, critical theory and contemporary French philosophy. The com- mission of the series is to provide a platform for the promotion of timely and innovative phil- osophical research. Contributions to the series are published in English or Swedish. Cover image: Kristofer Nilson, System (Portrait of a Swedish Tax Form), 2020, Lead pencil drawing on chalk paint, on mdf 59.2 x 42 cm. Photo: Jesper Petersen. Te Swedish tax form is one of many systems designed to handle and present information. Mapped onto the surface of an artwork, it opens a free space; an untouched surface where everything can exist at the same time. Kristofer Nilson Critical Theory Past, Present, Future Edited by Anders Bartonek & Sven-Olov Wallenstein Sdertrns hgskola Sdertrns University Library SE-141 89 Huddinge www.sh.se/publications © the Authors Published under Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 Unported License Cover layout: Jonathan Robson Graphic form: Per Lindblom & Jonathan Robson Printed by Elanders, Stockholm 2021 Sdertrn Philosophical Studies 28 ISSN 1651-6834 Sdertrn Academic Studies 83 ISSN 1650-433X ISBN 978-91-89109-35-3 (print) ISBN 978-91-89109-36-0 (digital) Contents Introduction
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources
    Post-continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources NELSON MALDONADO-TORRES It is no accident that the global geographical framework in use today is essentially a cartographic celebration of European power. After centuries of imperialism, the presumptions of a worldview of a once-dominant metropole has become part of the intellectual furniture of the world…. Metageography matters, and the attempt to engage it critically has only begun. Martin W. Lewis and Kären W. Wigen, The Myth of Continents.1 or several decades now the contours of legitimate philosophy have been drawn by advocates of F so-called analytic and continental philosophies. Analytic philosophy is often referred to as a style of thinking centered on the question of whether something is true, rather than, as continental philosophy, on the multiple factors that constitute meaning.2 Analytic philosophy is also said to be closer to the sciences, while continental philosophy has more affinity with the humanities.3 One of the reasons for this lies in that while analytic philosophy tends to dismiss history from its reflections, continental philosophy typically emphasizes the relevance of time, tradition, lived experience, and/or social context. Fortunately, this situation is slowly but gradually changing today. A variety of intellectuals are defying the rigid boundaries of these fields. Some of the most notable are Afro- American, Afro-Caribbean, and Latina/o scholars using the arsenal of these bodies of thought to analyze and interpret problems related to colonialism, racism, and sexism in the contemporary world.4 These challenges demand a critical analysis of the possibilities and limits of change within the main coordinates of these different styles or forms of philosophizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Food Composition and Analysis
    JOURNAL OF FOOD COMPOSITION AND ANALYSIS AUTHOR INFORMATION PACK TABLE OF CONTENTS XXX . • Description p.1 • Impact Factor p.1 • Abstracting and Indexing p.2 • Editorial Board p.2 • Guide for Authors p.4 ISSN: 0889-1575 DESCRIPTION . The Journal of Food Composition and Analysis publishes manuscripts on the chemical composition of human foods, analytical methods, food composition data and studies on the statistics, use and distribution of such data. Research areas include: • New methods for the chemical analysis of food • Nutrient, bioactive non-nutrient and anti-nutrient components in food • Flavour and taste components in food. • Food composition database development, management, and utilization • Processes of development and selection of single-value entries for food composition tables The Journal does not consider papers that feature as the major area of study: - Non-specific assays, such as in-vitro antioxidant capacity and total phenolic content - Clinical and pharmacological studies - Natural medicines - Physical properties of foods - Food waste materials - Foods formulated in the laboratory - Microbiological and anti-microbial assays - Sensory quality and organoleptic characteristics of foods IMPACT FACTOR . 2020: 4.556 © Clarivate Analytics Journal Citation Reports 2021 AUTHOR INFORMATION PACK 1 Oct 2021 www.elsevier.com/locate/jfca 1 ABSTRACTING AND INDEXING . Scopus AGRICOLA Biological Abstracts CAB International CAB Health Current Contents Dairy Science Abstracts FSTA (Food Science and Technology Abstracts) Nutrition Abstracts ScienceDirect AGORA Foodline: Food Science and Technology Vitis Viticulture and Enology Abstracts EMBiology EDITORIAL BOARD . Editor-in-Chief J. Stephen Elmore, University of Reading, Reading, United Kingdom Assistant Editor Charlène Girardot Consulting and Founding Editor Kent Stewart, The University of Texas System, Austin, Texas, United States of America Editors Francisco J.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Philosophical Analysis?
    JEFFREY C. KING WHAT IS A PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS? (Received 24 January 1996) It is common for philosophers to offer philosophical accounts or analyses, as they are sometimes called, of knowledge, autonomy, representation, (moral) goodness, reference, and even modesty.1 These philosophical analyses raise deep questions. What is it that is being analyzed (i.e. what sorts of things are the objects of analysis)? What sort of thing is the analysis itself (a proposition? sentence?)? Under what conditions is an analysis correct? How can a correct analysis be informative? How, if at all, does the production of philo- sophical analyses differ from what scientists do? The purpose of the present paper is to provide answers to these questions. The traditional answers to the ®rst and last of these questions are that concepts are the objects of philosophical analysis and that philo- sophical analyses differ from the results of scienti®c investigation in being conceptual analyses. Like many philosophers I am suspicious of the notions of concept and conceptual analysis as traditionally understood. Though the critique of these notions is beyond the scope of the present work, the answers I shall give to the questions raised above shall not invoke concepts (understood as things distinct from properties).2 I count it as a virtue of my account that it is able to provide answers to the questions raised above without an appeal to concepts. And to the extent that it has been felt that concepts are needed to answer these questions, the present account weakens the case for positing concepts. Before addressing these questions, however, we shall make the simplifying assumption that analyses are given in a ªcanonical formº.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Gadamer's Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Faculty Research and Creative Activity Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation January 2013 Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other Chad R. Carlson Eastern Illinois University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac Part of the Kinesiology Commons Recommended Citation Carlson, Chad R., "Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other" (2013). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 19. https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac/19 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW Chad Carlson Eastern Illinois University Gadamer’s ethics of play: Hermeneutics and the other, by Monica Vilhauer, Lanham, MD, Lexington Books, 2010, 166 pp., £37 (hardback), ISBN 978-0739139141 As a naıve graduate student, I remember signing up for a course in the Philosophy Department entitled, ‘Art and Truth’. Although I was studying sport and play in a different department, I was intrigued by the title – art seemed closely related to play and sport in the landscape of human experiences. Further, the course was offered at a convenient time and it fulfilled a deficiency I had toward graduation. Unfortunately, I had no idea what I was getting into. The course readings, which included Martin Heidegger, Friedrich Nietzsche, Maurice Merleau- Ponty, Jacques Derrida, Jurgen Habermas, and, most prominently, Hans-Georg Gadamer, seemed so dense that they necessitated long hours of introduction and prior training that I did not have.
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic and Continental Philosophy, Science, and Global Philosophy
    CHAPTER SIX ANALYTIC AND CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE, AND GLOBAL PHILOSOPHY Richard Tieszen There are many references in the philosophical literature to the division between analytic and Continental philosophy but it is not easy to provide a simple formulation of what it is that distinguishes these approaches to or styles of philosophy. There have been significant subdivisions within what has been considered analytic philosophy, such as that between for- mal philosophy, ordinary language philosophy, and conceptual analysis, and there have of course also been many variations within the general grouping of Continental philosophy, extending from eidetic phenomenol- ogy, existential phenomenology, existentialism, structuralism and semiot- ics, and neo-Freudian analysis to deconstruction. Philosophers who have written about the split between the analytic and Continental traditions have often focused on the work of particular figures who seem to embody much of what is involved in the division. In The Origins of Analytic Philoso- phy, for example, Michael Dummett looks to Frege and Husserl and holds that Frege took a turn into the philosophy of language but that Husserl did not, thus initiating a split in modern philosophy. Michael Friedman, to take another example, writes a book entitled A Parting of the Ways in which he focuses on Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Over the years I have heard or read a host of characterizations of the two traditions, such as the following: Analytic philosophy strives for clarity, exactness, precision and Continental philosophy does not. Con- tinental philosophy instead tends toward the use of poetic or dramatic language. The methodology of analytic philosophy is argumentation while Continental philosophy, if it has a methodology at all, is concerned with description or narrative or literary quality.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Program 1
    Philosophy Program 1 PHIL 126 – First Year Seminar 1 credit hour PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM The First-Year Seminar provides students with a multidisciplinary experience in which they approach an issue or problem from the Program Objectives perspective of three different academic differences. The First-Year Seminar will consist of three 1-credit hour courses taken as co-requisites • To enable students to develop thoughtful attitudes toward life and the in a single semester. The successful completion of all three courses world through a confrontation with the thought of great philosophers; satisfies the General Studies LOPER 1 course requirement. Students may • To treat such problems as the nature of our individual and social take the First-Year Seminar in any discipline, irrespective of their major or lives, the nature of the world in which we live, and the nature of our minor. Students admitted as readmit students or transfer students who apprehension of, and response to that world. All philosophy courses transfer 18 or more hours of General Studies credit to UNK are exempt will include a close reading and analysis of primary sources and a from taking a LOPER 1 course. substantive writing component. PHIL 188 – GS Portal 3 credit hours Students analyze critical issues confronting individuals and society Philosophy Major in a global context as they pertain to the discipline in which the Portal One option is available in this major: course is taught. The Portal is intended to help students succeed in their university education by being mentored in process of thinking critically 1. Philosophy (http://catalog.unk.edu/undergraduate/departments- about important ideas and articulating their own conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • NYU Paris PHIL-UA 9026 C01, History of French Philosophy
    NYU Paris PHIL-UA 9026 C01, History of French philosophy Instructor Information ● Philippe Lusson ● office hours TBD ● [email protected] Course Information ● PHIL-UA 9026 C01 ● History of French Philosophy ● An overview of important developments in French philosophy from the 16th century to the 1960s. We will pay close attention this semester to the relationship between the self and others. We will look at the debates that followed the rediscovery of Ancient philosophy and the Copernican revolution with Descartes’ rationalist and individualistic philosophy, Condillac’s empiricist critique, whose role for language brings the self into a web of social relations, and the growing recognition of the problem of society with Rousseau. We will then look at Henri Bergson’s reaction to the rise of the empirical sciences in the 19th century and especially at his distinction between the deep self and the social self. We will deepen our appreciation of the issues Bergson highlights with readings from René Girard and Jean Baudrillard, and we will look for possible solutions in Alexandre Kojève’s reading of Hegel and in Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir’s distinctive development of existentialism. ● No prerequisites ● Lecture Tuesday 5 to 6:30pm, recitation sections Thursday 3-4:30pm and 5-6:30pm ● NYU Paris, room TBD Course Overview and Goals Upon Completion of this Course, students will be able to: ● get a sense of the historical evolution of philosophy since the 16th-century, ● see how French philosophers developed some of the key ideas and movements in that history ● identity and debate important issues philosophers still discuss today ● learn how to assess the strength and weaknesses of arguments, ● engage in constructive philosophical discussion, give reasons, and raise objections, Page 1 ● perfect their skills in argumentative writing.
    [Show full text]