Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship. The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation David W. Kennedy, Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship, 21 New Eng. L. Rev. 209 (1986). Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:16084569 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Critical Theory, Structuralism and Contemporary Legal Scholarship David Kennedy * TABLE OF CONTENTS I. BEFORE CRITICAL THEORY AND STRUCTURALISM ............ 210 II. CRITICAL THEORY .......................................... 216 A. Moments of Reinterpretation........................ 217 B. A Process of Development .......................... 223 C. Critical Theory Refuses Positivism and Naturalism .... 226 D. Critical Theory Aspires to be Liberating and Cognitive 230 E. The Content and Domain of a Critical Theory ........ 235 F. Critical Theory and the Law ....................... 244 III. STRUCTURALISM . ...................................... 248 A . Linguistics ........................................ 249 B. A nthropology ..................................... 252 C . L iterature ........................................ 259 D . L a w . .. .. 2 6 6 IV. BEYOND CRITICAL THEORY AND STRUCTURALISM ............. 271 A. Some Similarities and Differences ................... 271 B. A Common Problem ............................... 274 C. Some Departures From Critical Theory and Structuralism ..................................... 276 • Assistant Professor of Law, Harvard Law School; A.B., 1976, Brown University; M.A.L.D., 1977, Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy; J.D., 1980, Harvard Law School; Ph. D., 1984, Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy. The author would like to thank Nathaniel Berman, Jamie Boyle, David Charny, Clare Dalton, Guther Frankenberg, Jerry Frug, Mort Hor- witz, Duncan Kennedy, Trevor Nagel, Anne Ronnel and Dan Tarullo for their helpful criticism and research assistance. NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:2 I. BEFORE CRITICAL THEORY AND STRUCTURALISM After several decades of interdisciplinary nourishment, one can hardly pe- ruse a law journal without encountering references to what once seemed the obscure texts of divergent disciplines: economics, sociology, philosophy, anthro- pology, literary criticism and beyond. In the years since the New Deal, legal theory has become more sophisticated and the methods of legal scholarship more eclectic. This article explores this expanding eclecticism by introducing two lines of thought which have influenced some legal scholars who have de- parted from mainstream legal thought: critical theory and structuralism.' I I. The rather summary treatment given these traditions in this article is intended to whet the reader's appetite for further reading. In order to fit these very diverse projects into a single story line, I have not selected texts and authors for consideration primarily for their representative quality or "historical importance." Instead, I have, throughout, indicated other secondary litera- ture which I find useful for readers who seek alternative accounts of these traditions. I have se- lected these works either for their clarity or because they tell a different story about the authors I discuss. My hope is that legal scholars who have not yet dipped into these literatures, but who have been at least somewhat intrigued by recent critical strands of legal scholarship, will go be- yond these secondary accounts to develop their own understanding of the underlying texts. To assist readers who want to go further, I have tried to indicate the major works of authors I discuss as well as essays or portions thereof which I have found particularly accessible. Many legal schol- ars who have relied upon these two intellectual traditions are to be found in the critical legal studies movement. Generalizations about the Conference on Critical Legal Studies, founded in 1977, are difficult. The conference has no definitive methodological approach but rather seems a somewhat unstable coalition of legal academics united by their commitment to a form of radical eclecticism reappraising basic approaches to legal scholarship. Some of the conference's work seems grounded in Legal Realism. See, e.g., Freeman, Truth and Mystification in Legal Scholar- ship, 90 YALE L.J. 1229, 1230, 1233 (1981) [hereinafter Freeman, Truth and Mystification]; Parker, The Past of Constitutional Theory and Its Future, 42 OHIO ST. L.J. 223 (1981); Tushnet, Post-Realist Legal Scholarship, 15 J. Soc'Y PUB. TCHRS. L. 20, 21 (1980). The intellectual legacies of the school extend beyond Legal Realism and include inter alia: (l) Marxism, see, e.g., Fraser, The Legal Theory We Need Now, 40-41 SOCIALIST REV. 147 (1978); Klare, Law-Making as Praxis, TELOS (no. 40) 123 (1979); (2) New Left anarchism, see, e.g., DUNCAN KENNEDY, LEGAL EDUCATION AND THE REPRODUCTION OF HIERARCHY: A POLEMIC AGAINST THE SYSTEM (1983); (3) Sartrean existentialism, see. e.g., Gabel, Intention and Struc- ture in Contractual Conditions: Outline of a Method for Critical Legal Theory, 61 MINN. L. REV. 601 (1977); (4) Structuralism, see infra notes 90-143 and accompanying text; (5) Neo-Progressive historiography, see. e.g., M. HORWITz, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW 1780-1860 (1977); (6) liberal sociology, see, e.g., Galanter, Why the "Haves" Come Out Ahead: Specula- tions on the Limits of Legal Change, 9 LAW & Soc'Y REV. 95 (1974); (7) radical social theory, see, e.g., R. UNGER, KNOWLEDGE AND POLITICS (1975); R. UNGER, LAW IN MODERN SOCIETY (1976); and (8) empirical social science, see, e.g., Macaulay, Private Legislation and the Duty to Read - Business Run by IBM Machine, the Law of Contracts and Credit Cards, 19 VAND. L. REV. 1051 (1966); Trubeck, The Construction and Deconstruction of a Disputes-Focused Ap- proach: An Afterword, 15 LAW & SoC'Y REV. 727 (1981). For a more extensive list of the writ- ings of the critical school, see A Bibliography of Critical Legal Studies, 94 YALE L.J. 461 (1984). Much of the scholarship of this group develops a critique of the legal discourse of "rights." See, e.g., Frug, The City as a Legal Concept, 93 HARV. L. REV. 1057 (1980); Gabel, Reification in Legal Reasoning, 3 RES. L. & Soc. 25 (1980); Klare, Labor Law as Ideology: Toward a New Historiography of Collective Bargaining, 4 INDUST. REV. L.J. 450 (1981); Simon, The Ideology of Advocacy: Procedural Justice and Professional Ethics, 1978 Wis. L. REV. 29. This strand of the movement is associated with a critique of legal scholarship which is not 1985-19861 CRITICAL THEORY argue that although these complementary disciplines provide useful leverage against liberal legal thought, in many ways their use in legal scholarship has repeated the difficulties which motivated their importation. The final section of the article suggests that the diverse work of "post-structuralists" might prove suggestive and provocative for legal scholars who have heretofore foraged in critical theory and structuralism. Legal scholars who look to the literatures of critical theory2 and struc- turalism' share a sense of the difficulties faced by contemporary legal scholar- ship. Indeed, their perception of the problems faced by post-war legal scholars differs very little from the perception of other scholars who have turned to foreign disciplines. All seem to feel that legal theory and doctrine have become increasingly fragmented since the era of realist scholarship before the Second World War. Although legal theory and doctrine have become more pervasive over the past decades, they seem paradoxically also to have become weaker and less persuasive. Doctrinal argument seems increasingly complex and ever less able to determine outcomes. The normative moorings of the most basic doctrinal discourse by lawyers, scholars and judges seem infirm. Despite their contin- ued, if muted claims to account for events and behavior either proscriptively or prescriptively, legal principles, rules and policy arguments seem to dissolve far too easily into thin disguises for assertions of interest. The more diverse the sphere of an argument's application, the thinner it seems to become until its manipulability becomes more apparent than its persuasive clout. The result has been ever more polarized arguments, ever more sophisticated doctrinal di- directed at breaking down this ideology. See, e.g., Freeman, Truth and Mystification, supra note I; Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, 90 YALE L.J. 1017 (1981); Trubek, Scholars in Self-Estrangement: Reflections on the Crisis in Law and Development Studies in the United States, 1974 WIs. L. REV. 1062 [hereinafter Trubek, Scholars in Self-Estrangement]; Tushnet, Legal Scholarship; Its Causes and Cures, 90 YALE L. J. 1205 (1981). This strand of the move- ment exists in some tension with more program-related strands. For a fuller discussion of these splits, see Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133 U. PA. L. REV. 685 (1985); Critical Legal Studies Symposium, 36 STAN. L. REV. I (1984). The movement has devoted some attention to criticism of law and economics from both directions. See, e.g., Baker, Starting Points in the Economic Analysis of Law, 8 HOFSTRA L. REV. 939 (1980); Horwitz,
Recommended publications
  • The Fourth Perspective: Evolution and Organismal Agency
    The Fourth Perspective: Evolution and Organismal Agency Johannes Jaeger Complexity Science Hub (CSH), Vienna, Josefstädter Straße 39, 1080 Vienna Abstract This chapter examines the deep connections between biological organization, agency, and evolution by natural selection. Using Griesemer’s account of the re- producer, I argue that the basic unit of evolution is not a genetic replicator, but a complex hierarchical life cycle. Understanding the self-maintaining and self-pro- liferating properties of evolvable reproducers requires an organizational account of ontogenesis and reproduction. This leads us to an extended and disambiguated set of minimal conditions for evolution by natural selection—including revised or new principles of heredity, variation, and ontogenesis. More importantly, the con- tinuous maintenance of biological organization within and across generations im- plies that all evolvable systems are agents, or contain agents among their parts. This means that we ought to take agency seriously—to better understand the con- cept and its role in explaining biological phenomena—if we aim to obtain an or- ganismic theory of evolution in the original spirit of Darwin’s struggle for exis- tence. This kind of understanding must rely on an agential perspective on evolu- tion, complementing and succeeding existing structural, functional, and processual approaches. I sketch a tentative outline of such an agential perspective, and present a survey of methodological and conceptual challenges that will have to be overcome if we are to properly implement it. 1. Introduction There are two fundamentally different ways to interpret Darwinian evolutionary theory. Charles Darwin’s original framework grounds the process of evolution on 2 the individual’s struggle for existence (Darwin, 1859).
    [Show full text]
  • Perceptual Variation and Structuralism
    NOUSˆ 54:2 (2020) 290–326 doi: 10.1111/nous.12245 Perceptual Variation and Structuralism JOHN MORRISON Barnard College, Columbia University Abstract I use an old challenge to motivate a new view. The old challenge is due to variation in our perceptions of secondary qualities. The challenge is to say whose percep- tions are accurate. The new view is about how we manage to perceive secondary qualities, and thus manage to perceive them accurately or inaccurately. I call it perceptual structuralism. I first introduce the challenge and point out drawbacks with traditional responses. I spend the rest of the paper motivating and defending a structuralist response. While I focus on color, both the challenge and the view generalize to the other secondary qualities. 1. Perceptual Variation Our perceptual experiences tell us that lemons are yellow and sour. It’s natural to infer that lemons really are yellow and sour. But perceptions vary, even among ordinary observers. Some perceive lemons as slightly greener and sweeter. This gives rise to a challenge that forces us to rethink the nature of perception and the objectivity of what we perceive. For concreteness, I’ll focus on the perceptions of two ordinary observers, Miriam and Aaron. I’ll also focus on their perceptions of a particular lemon’s color. These restrictions will make the challenge easier to understand and the responses easier to compare. But the challenge and responses are perfectly general. Toward the end of the paper I’ll return to sourness and the other secondary qualities. When Miriam and Aaron look at the same lemon, their perceptions differ.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meanings of Structuralism : Considerations on Structures and Gestalten, with Particular Attention to the Masks of Levi-Strauss
    The meanings of structuralism : considerations on structures and Gestalten, with particular attention to the masks of Levi-Strauss Sonesson, Göran Published in: Segni e comprensione 2012 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Sonesson, G. (2012). The meanings of structuralism : considerations on structures and Gestalten, with particular attention to the masks of Levi-Strauss. Segni e comprensione, XXVI(78), 84-101. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 International RIVISTA TELEMATICA QUADRIMESTRALE - ANNO XXVI NUOVA SERIE - N. 78 – SETTEMBRE-DICEMBRE 2012 1 This Review is submitted to international peer review Create PDF files without this message by purchasing novaPDF printer (http://www.novapdf.com) Segni e comprensione International Pubblicazione promossa nel 1987 dal Dipartimento di Filosofia e Scienze sociali dell’Università degli Studi di Lecce, oggi Università del Salento, con la collaborazione del “Centro Italiano di Ricerche fenomenologiche” con sede in Roma, diretto da Angela Ales Bello.
    [Show full text]
  • Biogenetic Structuralism'
    'BIOGE~TIC STRUCTURALISM'STRUCTURALISM" AND THE LOCATION OF STRUCTURES*STRUCTURES~'< In the heyday of 'high' structuralism it was sometimes argued, explicitly or implicitly, that the ultimate 'explanation' of cultural structures was to be found in the properties of 'the human mind'. This argument, it was perhaps felt, shifted the problem of explanation to the realm 'of philosophr, which many anthropologists considered outsiqe their concern. It was not surprising, therefore, that $ceptics ofaof, a more materialist persuasionpersuas'ion would critiofze structuralist analysis for being an essentially idea11stormentalistidealJtst or mentalist undertaking.undertakirig. Even so, the analytical value, of the notion of structures (in the Levi-Straussian sense,'hasbeen increasingly recognized, even by anthro­ pologists of a materialistmateria~ist stance (e.g. in the 'structural marx.i;sm'marx,j;sm' of MauriceNaurice Godelier (1973) and JonathanJonatl1an Friedman (1974),(1974)1 to the extent that nowadays only the most ardent 'vul¢ar'vul$ar materialists' feel they can do without it. This devefopment has not, however, done away with the problem of t~e locatiori of structures; the problem has only been push~d into the background, because other problems were.were felt: by most to be of more immediate concern. , .' ~ptwhether~f.lt'whether or not we have been bothered by the location problelflproblelf1 we should all welcome the pioneering work of two auth'prl;j,auth'prl;l, Charles Laughlin, an anthropologist, and Eugene d' Aqui!i, ~ psych~atrist, in which they lay the foundations " of aneW structural approach, 'biogenetic structuralism'. In the introduction to the book they state: !~ f f ., Th~majorTh~rnajor onttllbgical-:assumptiononttJlbgical-:assumption upon which biogenetic str\.ibturalismstr~bturalism is founded is that there exists no reality intervening between the central nervous system and the environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel and the Metaphysical Frontiers of Political Theory
    Copyrighted material - provided by Taylor & Francis Eric Goodfield. American University Beirut. 23/09/2014 Hegel and the Metaphysical Frontiers of Political Theory For over 150 years G.W.F. Hegel’s ghost has haunted theoretical understanding and practice. His opponents first, and later his defenders, have equally defined their programs against and with his. In this way Hegel’s political thought has both situated and displaced modern political theorizing. This book takes the reception of Hegel’s political thought as a lens through which contemporary methodological and ideological prerogatives are exposed. It traces the nineteenth- century origins of the positivist revolt against Hegel’s legacy forward to political science’s turn away from philosophical tradition in the twentieth century. The book critically reviews the subsequent revisionist trend that has eliminated his metaphysics from contemporary considerations of his political thought. It then moves to re- evaluate their relation and defend their inseparability in his major work on politics: the Philosophy of Right. Against this background, the book concludes with an argument for the inherent meta- physical dimension of political theorizing itself. Goodfield takes Hegel’s recep- tion, representation, as well as rejection in Anglo-American scholarship as a mirror in which its metaphysical presuppositions of the political are exception- ally well reflected. It is through such reflection, he argues, that we may begin to come to terms with them. This book will be of great interest to students, scholars, and readers of polit- ical theory and philosophy, Hegel, metaphysics and the philosophy of the social sciences. Eric Lee Goodfield is Visiting Assistant Professor at the American University of Beirut, Lebanon.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Apocrypha
    Chapter 3 Hegel’s Apocrypha 1 A Rediscovery The term Jugendschriften—writings of youth, is used to refer to a series of texts and fragments produced during Hegel’s years as student and private tutor from the period 1793 to 1800 which he did not himself publish. In 1801 Hegel moved to Jena with the help of Schelling, published his first book, took his habilitation and began his academic career. The Jugendschriften were first published by Hermann Nohl in 1907.1 Nohl was a student of Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911), the advocate of the philosophy of life and of hermeneutics, who is also important as one of the founders of historicism. Dilthey himself held the view that a phi- losophy is best described in terms of the history of its development and hence that the biography of a philosopher is often the key to his philosophy. In 1905 he published a work with the title Die Jugendgeschichte Hegels—The history of the young Hegel,2 which was based on the documents in the Royal Prussian Library in Berlin that Nohl published two years later. Dilthey’s concern with Hegel’s early works was thoroughly determined by his own philosophy. For instance, he found that Hegel’s interest in the importance of biography to his- tory was comparable to his own. Hegel had written a Life of Jesus, which means that Hegel tried, just as Dilthey did in the history of philosophy, to consider Jesus Christ not as a dogmatic ‘object’ of theology, but historically, as a matter for historical investigation.
    [Show full text]
  • Durkheim and Organizational Culture
    IRLE IRLE WORKING PAPER #108-04 June 2004 Durkheim and Organizational Culture James R. Lincoln and Didier Guillot Cite as: James R. Lincoln and Didier Guillot. (2004). “Durkheim and Organizational Culture.” IRLE Working Paper No. 108-04. http://irle.berkeley.edu/workingpapers/108-04.pdf irle.berkeley.edu/workingpapers Durkheim and Organizational Culture James R. Lincoln Walter A. Haas School of Business University of California Berkeley, CA 94720 Didier Guillot INSEAD Singapore June , 2004 Prepared for inclusion in Marek Kocsynski, Randy Hodson, and Paul Edwards (editors): Social Theory at Work . Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Durkheim and Organizational Culture “The degree of consensus over, and intensity of, cognitive orientations and regulative cultural codes among the members of a population is an inv erse function of the degree of structural differentiation among actors in this population and a positive, multiplicative function of their (a) rate of interpersonal interaction, (b) level of emotional arousal, and (c) rate of ritual performance. ” Durkheim’ s theory of culture as rendered axiomatically by Jonathan Turner (1990) Introduction This paper examines the significance of Emile Durkheim’s thought for organization theory , particular attention being given to the concept of organizational culture. We ar e not the first to take the project on —a number of scholars have usefully addressed the extent and relevance of this giant of Western social science for the study of organization and work. Even so, there is no denying that Durkheim’s name appears with vast ly less frequency in the literature on these topics than is true of Marx and W eber, sociology’ s other founding fathers .
    [Show full text]
  • Structuralism 1. the Nature of Meaning Or Understanding
    Structuralism 1. The nature of meaning or understanding. A. The role of structure as the system of relationships Something can only be understood (i.e., a meaning can be constructed) within a certain system of relationships (or structure). For example, a word which is a linguistic sign (something that stands for something else) can only be understood within a certain conventional system of signs, which is language, and not by itself (cf. the word / sound and “shark” in English and Arabic). A particular relationship within a شرق combination society (e.g., between a male offspring and his maternal uncle) can only be understood in the context of the whole system of kinship (e.g., matrilineal or patrilineal). Structuralism holds that, according to the human way of understanding things, particular elements have no absolute meaning or value: their meaning or value is relative to other elements. Everything makes sense only in relation to something else. An element cannot be perceived by itself. In order to understand a particular element we need to study the whole system of relationships or structure (this approach is also exactly the same as Malinowski’s: one cannot understand particular elements of culture out of the context of that culture). A particular element can only be studied as part of a greater structure. In fact, the only thing that can be studied is not particular elements or objects but relationships within a system. Our human world, so to speak, is made up of relationships, which make up permanent structures of the human mind. B. The role of oppositions / pairs of binary oppositions Structuralism holds that understanding can only happen if clearly defined or “significant” (= essential) differences are present which are called oppositions (or binary oppositions since they come in pairs).
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources
    Post-continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources NELSON MALDONADO-TORRES It is no accident that the global geographical framework in use today is essentially a cartographic celebration of European power. After centuries of imperialism, the presumptions of a worldview of a once-dominant metropole has become part of the intellectual furniture of the world…. Metageography matters, and the attempt to engage it critically has only begun. Martin W. Lewis and Kären W. Wigen, The Myth of Continents.1 or several decades now the contours of legitimate philosophy have been drawn by advocates of F so-called analytic and continental philosophies. Analytic philosophy is often referred to as a style of thinking centered on the question of whether something is true, rather than, as continental philosophy, on the multiple factors that constitute meaning.2 Analytic philosophy is also said to be closer to the sciences, while continental philosophy has more affinity with the humanities.3 One of the reasons for this lies in that while analytic philosophy tends to dismiss history from its reflections, continental philosophy typically emphasizes the relevance of time, tradition, lived experience, and/or social context. Fortunately, this situation is slowly but gradually changing today. A variety of intellectuals are defying the rigid boundaries of these fields. Some of the most notable are Afro- American, Afro-Caribbean, and Latina/o scholars using the arsenal of these bodies of thought to analyze and interpret problems related to colonialism, racism, and sexism in the contemporary world.4 These challenges demand a critical analysis of the possibilities and limits of change within the main coordinates of these different styles or forms of philosophizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich Max Schiller Claremont Mckenna College
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2012 Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich Max Schiller Claremont McKenna College Recommended Citation Schiller, Max, "Jürgen Habermas and the Third Reich" (2012). CMC Senior Theses. Paper 358. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/358 This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Introduction The formation and subsequent actions of the Nazi government left a devastating and indelible impact on Europe and the world. In the midst of general technological and social progress that has occurred in Europe since the Enlightenment, the Nazis represent one of the greatest social regressions that has occurred in the modern world. Despite the development of a generally more humanitarian and socially progressive conditions in the western world over the past several hundred years, the Nazis instigated one of the most diabolic and genocidal programs known to man. And they did so using modern technologies in an expression of what historian Jeffrey Herf calls “reactionary modernism.” The idea, according to Herf is that, “Before and after the Nazi seizure of power, an important current within conservative and subsequently Nazi ideology was a reconciliation between the antimodernist, romantic, and irrantionalist ideas present in German nationalism and the most obvious manifestation of means ...modern technology.” 1 Nazi crimes were so extreme and barbaric precisely because they incorporated modern technologies into a process that violated modern ethical standards. Nazi crimes in the context of contemporary notions of ethics are almost inconceivable.
    [Show full text]
  • BEHAVIORAL and POST BEHAVIORAL APPROACH to POLITICAL SCIENCE Sunita Agarwal1 and Prof
    ISSN: 2455-2224 Contents lists available at http://www.albertscience.com ASIO Journal of Humanities, Management & Social Sciences Invention (ASIO-JHMSSI) Volume 1, Issue 1, 2015: 18-22 BEHAVIORAL AND POST BEHAVIORAL APPROACH TO POLITICAL SCIENCE Sunita Agarwal1 and Prof. S K Singh2 1Govt. College, Ajmer, Rajasthan, India 2Department of Political Science, Govt. College, Ajmer, Rajasthan, India ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT The Behaviourailsts had laid too a great deal significance on value-free research. Review Article History In fact it was one of their essential points. They stood for value neutrality in research at all levels. Values for all practical purposes were out of their consideration. Post Behaviourailsts however, did not agree with this perspective Corresponding Author: and stressed on value loaded political Science. According to them all information Sunita Agarwal† stands on values and that unless value is considered as the basis of knowledge there is every threat that knowledge will become meaningless. They are of the view that in political research values have big role to play. The behaviouralists Govt. College, Ajmer, Rajasthan, India argue that science had some ideal commitments and that behaviouralism shared these ideal commitments of science. This thesis of the behaviouralists is not acceptable to the post-behaviouralists. They think that the technical research and scientific knowledge pursued by the behaviouralists should not be cut off from the realities of life. It should be related to vital social problems and aim at solving some problems. It is a reform movement of Behaviouralism which appreciates the work done by Behaviourailsts in developing tools, techniques and methods of research but wish that those should be used for the good of the society.
    [Show full text]
  • From Modernism to Messianism: Liberal Developmentalism And
    From Modernism to Messianism: Liberal Developmentalism and American Exceptionalism1 Following the Second World War, we encounter again many of the same developmental themes that dominated the theory and practice of imperialism in the nineteenth century. Of course, there are important differences as well. For one thing, the differentiation and institutionalization of the human sciences in the intervening years means that these themes are now articulated and elaborated within specialized academic disciplines. For another, the main field on which developmental theory and practice are deployed is no longer British – or, more broadly, European – imperialism but American neoimperialism. At the close of the War, the United States was not only the major military, economic, and political power left standing; it was also less implicated than European states in colonial domination abroad. The depletion of the colonial powers and the imminent breakup of their empires left it in a singular position to lead the reshaping of the post-War world. And it tried to do so in its own image and likeness: America saw itself as the exemplar and apostle of a fully developed modernity.2 In this it was, in some ways, only reproducing the self-understanding and self- regard of the classical imperial powers of the modern period. But in other ways America’s civilizing mission was marked by the exceptionalism of its political history and culture, which was famously analyzed by Louis Hartz fifty years ago.3 Picking up on Alexis de Tocqueville’s observation that Americans were “born equal,” Hartz elaborated upon the uniqueness of the American political experience.
    [Show full text]