CHAPTER 8 Proofs Involving Sets

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CHAPTER 8 Proofs Involving Sets CHAPTER 8 Proofs Involving Sets tudents in their first advanced mathematics classes are often surprised S by the extensive role that sets play and by the fact that most of the proofs they encounter are proofs about sets. Perhaps you’ve already seen such proofs in your linear algebra course, where a vector space was defined to be a set of objects (called vectors) that obey certain properties. Your text proved many things about vector spaces, such as the fact that the intersection of two vector spaces is also a vector space, and the proofs used ideas from set theory. As you go deeper into mathematics, you will encounter more and more ideas, theorems and proofs that involve sets. The purpose of this chapter is to give you a foundation that will prepare you for this new outlook. We will discuss how to show that an object is an element of a set, how to prove one set is a subset of another and how to prove two sets are equal. As you read this chapter, you may need to occasionally refer back to Chapter 1 to refresh your memory. For your convenience, the main definitions from Chapter 1 are summarized below. If A and B are sets, then: A B ©(x, y): x A, y Bª, £ Æ 2 2 A B ©x :(x A) (x B)ª, [ Æ 2 _ 2 A B ©x :(x A) (x B)ª, \ Æ 2 ^ 2 A B ©x :(x A) (x B)ª, ¡ Æ 2 ^ ∉ A U A. Æ ¡ Recall that A B means that every element of A is also an element of B. ⊆ 8.1 How to Prove a A 2 We will begin with a review of set-builder notation, and then review how to show that a given object a is an element of some set A. 132 Proofs Involving Sets © ª Generally, a set A will be expressed in set-builder notation A x : P(x) , Æ where P(x) is some statement (or open sentence) about x. The set A is understood to have as elements all those things x for which P(x) is true. For example, © ª © ª x : x is an odd integer ..., 5, 3, 1,1,3,5,... Æ ¡ ¡ ¡ © ª A common variation of this notation is to express a set as A x S : P(x) . Æ 2 Here it is understood that A consists of all elements x of the (predetermined) set S for which P(x) is true. Keep in mind that, depending on context, x could be any kind of object (integer, ordered pair, set, function, etc.). There is also nothing special about the particular variable x; any reasonable symbol x, y, k, etc., would do. Some examples follow. © ª © ª n Z : n is odd ..., 5, 3, 1,1,3,5,... 2 Æ ¡ ¡ ¡ ©x N : 6 xª ©6,12,18,24,30,...ª 2 j Æ ©(a, b) Z Z : b a 5ª ©...,( 2,3),( 1,4),(0,5),(1,6),...ª 2 £ Æ Å Æ ¡ ¡ ©X P(Z): X 1ª ©...,© 1ª,©0ª,©1ª,©2ª,©3ª,©4ª,...ª 2 j j Æ Æ ¡ Now it should be clear how to prove that an object a belongs to a set © ª © ª x : P(x) . Since x : P(x) consists of all things x for which P(x) is true, to © ª show that a x : P(x) we just need to show that P(a) is true. Likewise, to © 2 ª show a x S : P(x) , we need to confirm that a S and that P(a) is true. 2 2 2 These ideas are summarized below. However, you should not memorize these methods, you should understand them. With contemplation and practice, using them becomes natural and intuitive. How to show a ©x : P(x)ª How to show a ©x S : P(x)ª 2 2 2 Show that P(a) is true. 1. Verify that a S. 2 2. Show that P(a) is true. © ª Example 8.1 Let’s investigate elements of A x : x N and 7 x . This set © ª Æ 2 j has form A x : P(x) where P(x) is the open sentence (x N) (7 x). Thus Æ 2 ^ j 21 A because P(21) is true. Similarly, 7,14,28,35, etc., are all elements of 2 A. But 8 A (for example) because P(8) is false. Likewise 14 A because ∉ ¡ ∉ P( 14) is false. ¡ © ª Example 8.2 Consider the set A X P(N): X 3 . We know that © ª © ª Æ 2 ¯© j ªj¯ Æ © ª 4,13,45 A because 4,13,45 P(N) and ¯ 4,13,45 ¯ 3. Also 1,2,3 A, © ª2 © 2 ª ¯© Æ ª¯ 2 10,854,3 A, etc. However 1,2,3,4 A because ¯ 1,2,3,4 ¯ 3. Further, © ª 2 © ª ∉ 6Æ 1,2,3 A because 1,2,3 P(N). ¡ ∉ ¡ ∉ How to Prove A B 133 ⊆ © ª Example 8.3 Consider the set B (x, y) Z Z : x y (mod 5) . Notice Æ 2 £ ´ (8,23) B because (8,23) Z Z and 8 23 (mod 5). Likewise, (100,75) B, 2 2 £ ´ 2 (102,77) B, etc., but (6,10) B. 2 ∉ Now suppose n Z and consider the ordered pair (4n 3,9n 2). Does 2 Å ¡ this ordered pair belong to B? To answer this, we first observe that (4n 3,9n 2) Z Z. Next, we observe that (4n 3) (9n 2) 5n 5 5(1 n), Å¡ ¡ 2 £ ¢ Å ¡ ¡ Æ¡ Å Æ ¡ so 5 (4n 3) (9n 2) , which means (4n 3) (9n 2) (mod 5). Therefore we j Å ¡ ¡ Å ´ ¡ have established that (4n 3,9n 2) meets the requirements for belonging Å ¡ to B, so (4n 3,9n 2) B for every n Z. Å ¡ 2 2 Example 8.4 This illustrates another common way of defining a set. © 3 ª Consider the set C 3x 2 : x Z . Elements of this set consist of all the Æ Å 2 values 3x3 2 where x is an integer. Thus 22 C because 22 3( 2)3 2. Å ¡ 2 ¡ Æ ¡ Å You can confirm 1 C and 5 C, etc. Also 0 C and 1 C, etc. ¡ 2 2 ∉ 2 ∉ 8.2 How to Prove A B ⊆ In this course (and more importantly, beyond it) you will encounter many circumstances where it is necessary to prove that one set is a subset of an- other. This section explains how to do this. The methods we discuss should improve your skills in both writing your own proofs and in comprehending the proofs that you read. Recall (Definition 1.3) that if A and B are sets, then A B means that ⊆ every element of A is also an element of B. In other words, it means if a A, then a B. Therefore to prove that A B, we just need to prove that 2 2 ⊆ the conditional statement “If a A, then a B” 2 2 is true. This can be proved directly, by assuming a A and deducing a B. 2 2 The contrapositive approach is another option: Assume a B and deduce ∉ a A. Each of these two approaches is outlined below. ∉ How to Prove A B How to Prove A B ⊆ ⊆ (Direct approach) (Contrapositive approach) Proof. Suppose a A. Proof. Suppose a B. 2 . ∉ . Therefore a B. Therefore a A. 2 ∉ Thus a A implies a B, Thus a B implies a A, 2 2 ∉ ∉ so it follows that A B. so it follows that A B. ⊆ ■ ⊆ ■ 134 Proofs Involving Sets In practice, the direct approach usually results in the most straight- forward and easy proof, though occasionally the contrapositive is the most expedient. (You can even prove A B by contradiction: Assume ⊆ (a A) (a B), and deduce a contradiction.) The remainder of this section 2 ^ ∉ consists of examples with occasional commentary. Unless stated otherwise, we will use the direct approach in all proofs; pay special attention to how the above outline for the direct approach is used. © ª © ª Example 8.5 Prove that x Z : 18 x x Z : 6 x . 2 j ⊆ 2 j © ª Proof. Suppose a x Z : 18 x . 2 2 j This means that a Z and 18 a. 2 j By definition of divisibility, there is an integer c for which a 18c. Æ Consequently a 6(3c), and from this we deduce that 6 a. Æ j© ª Therefore a is one of the integers that 6 divides, so a x Z : 6 x . © ª © 2ª 2 j We’ve shown a x Z : 18 x implies a n Z : 6 x , so it follows that © ª © 2 2ª j 2 2 j x Z : 18 x x Z : 6 x . 2 j ⊆ 2 j ■ © ª © ª © ª Example 8.6 Prove that x Z : 2 x x Z : 9 x x Z : 6 x . 2 j \ 2 j ⊆ 2 j © ª © ª Proof. Suppose a x Z : 2 x x Z : 9 x . 2 2 j \ 2 j © ª © ª By definition of intersection, this means a x Z : 2 x and a x Z : 9 x . © ª 2 2 j 2 2 j Since a x Z : 2 x we know 2 a, so a 2c for some c Z. Thus a is even. 2 © 2 j ª j Æ 2 Since a x Z : 9 x we know 9 a, so a 9d for some d Z.
Recommended publications
  • 1 Elementary Set Theory
    1 Elementary Set Theory Notation: fg enclose a set. f1; 2; 3g = f3; 2; 2; 1; 3g because a set is not defined by order or multiplicity. f0; 2; 4;:::g = fxjx is an even natural numberg because two ways of writing a set are equivalent. ; is the empty set. x 2 A denotes x is an element of A. N = f0; 1; 2;:::g are the natural numbers. Z = f:::; −2; −1; 0; 1; 2;:::g are the integers. m Q = f n jm; n 2 Z and n 6= 0g are the rational numbers. R are the real numbers. Axiom 1.1. Axiom of Extensionality Let A; B be sets. If (8x)x 2 A iff x 2 B then A = B. Definition 1.1 (Subset). Let A; B be sets. Then A is a subset of B, written A ⊆ B iff (8x) if x 2 A then x 2 B. Theorem 1.1. If A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A then A = B. Proof. Let x be arbitrary. Because A ⊆ B if x 2 A then x 2 B Because B ⊆ A if x 2 B then x 2 A Hence, x 2 A iff x 2 B, thus A = B. Definition 1.2 (Union). Let A; B be sets. The Union A [ B of A and B is defined by x 2 A [ B if x 2 A or x 2 B. Theorem 1.2. A [ (B [ C) = (A [ B) [ C Proof. Let x be arbitrary. x 2 A [ (B [ C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B [ C iff x 2 A or (x 2 B or x 2 C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B or x 2 C iff (x 2 A or x 2 B) or x 2 C iff x 2 A [ B or x 2 C iff x 2 (A [ B) [ C Definition 1.3 (Intersection).
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Proofs
    CHAPTER 1 Logic, Proofs 1.1. Propositions A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false (but not both). For instance, the following are propositions: “Paris is in France” (true), “London is in Denmark” (false), “2 < 4” (true), “4 = 7 (false)”. However the following are not propositions: “what is your name?” (this is a question), “do your homework” (this is a command), “this sentence is false” (neither true nor false), “x is an even number” (it depends on what x represents), “Socrates” (it is not even a sentence). The truth or falsehood of a proposition is called its truth value. 1.1.1. Connectives, Truth Tables. Connectives are used for making compound propositions. The main ones are the following (p and q represent given propositions): Name Represented Meaning Negation p “not p” Conjunction p¬ q “p and q” Disjunction p ∧ q “p or q (or both)” Exclusive Or p ∨ q “either p or q, but not both” Implication p ⊕ q “if p then q” Biconditional p → q “p if and only if q” ↔ The truth value of a compound proposition depends only on the value of its components. Writing F for “false” and T for “true”, we can summarize the meaning of the connectives in the following way: 6 1.1. PROPOSITIONS 7 p q p p q p q p q p q p q T T ¬F T∧ T∨ ⊕F →T ↔T T F F F T T F F F T T F T T T F F F T F F F T T Note that represents a non-exclusive or, i.e., p q is true when any of p, q is true∨ and also when both are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A
    Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Statements. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that is either true or false. Here we denote logical statements with capital letters A; B. Logical statements be combined to form new logical statements as follows: Name Notation Conjunction A and B Disjunction A or B Negation not A :A Implication A implies B if A, then B A ) B Equivalence A if and only if B A , B Here are some examples of conjunction, disjunction and negation: x > 1 and x < 3: This is true when x is in the open interval (1; 3). x > 1 or x < 3: This is true for all real numbers x. :(x > 1): This is the same as x ≤ 1. Here are two logical statements that are true: x > 4 ) x > 2. x2 = 1 , (x = 1 or x = −1). Note that \x = 1 or x = −1" is usually written x = ±1. Converses, Contrapositives, and Tautologies. We begin with converses and contrapositives: • The converse of \A implies B" is \B implies A". • The contrapositive of \A implies B" is \:B implies :A" Thus the statement \x > 4 ) x > 2" has: • Converse: x > 2 ) x > 4. • Contrapositive: x ≤ 2 ) x ≤ 4. 1 Some logical statements are guaranteed to always be true. These are tautologies. Here are two tautologies that involve converses and contrapositives: • (A if and only if B) , ((A implies B) and (B implies A)). In other words, A and B are equivalent exactly when both A ) B and its converse are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 1: Propositional Logic
    Lecture 1: Propositional Logic Syntax Semantics Truth tables Implications and Equivalences Valid and Invalid arguments Normal forms Davis-Putnam Algorithm 1 Atomic propositions and logical connectives An atomic proposition is a statement or assertion that must be true or false. Examples of atomic propositions are: “5 is a prime” and “program terminates”. Propositional formulas are constructed from atomic propositions by using logical connectives. Connectives false true not and or conditional (implies) biconditional (equivalent) A typical propositional formula is The truth value of a propositional formula can be calculated from the truth values of the atomic propositions it contains. 2 Well-formed propositional formulas The well-formed formulas of propositional logic are obtained by using the construction rules below: An atomic proposition is a well-formed formula. If is a well-formed formula, then so is . If and are well-formed formulas, then so are , , , and . If is a well-formed formula, then so is . Alternatively, can use Backus-Naur Form (BNF) : formula ::= Atomic Proposition formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula formula 3 Truth functions The truth of a propositional formula is a function of the truth values of the atomic propositions it contains. A truth assignment is a mapping that associates a truth value with each of the atomic propositions . Let be a truth assignment for . If we identify with false and with true, we can easily determine the truth value of under . The other logical connectives can be handled in a similar manner. Truth functions are sometimes called Boolean functions. 4 Truth tables for basic logical connectives A truth table shows whether a propositional formula is true or false for each possible truth assignment.
    [Show full text]
  • Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning
    Proofs and Mathematical Reasoning University of Birmingham Author: Supervisors: Agata Stefanowicz Joe Kyle Michael Grove September 2014 c University of Birmingham 2014 Contents 1 Introduction 6 2 Mathematical language and symbols 6 2.1 Mathematics is a language . .6 2.2 Greek alphabet . .6 2.3 Symbols . .6 2.4 Words in mathematics . .7 3 What is a proof? 9 3.1 Writer versus reader . .9 3.2 Methods of proofs . .9 3.3 Implications and if and only if statements . 10 4 Direct proof 11 4.1 Description of method . 11 4.2 Hard parts? . 11 4.3 Examples . 11 4.4 Fallacious \proofs" . 15 4.5 Counterexamples . 16 5 Proof by cases 17 5.1 Method . 17 5.2 Hard parts? . 17 5.3 Examples of proof by cases . 17 6 Mathematical Induction 19 6.1 Method . 19 6.2 Versions of induction. 19 6.3 Hard parts? . 20 6.4 Examples of mathematical induction . 20 7 Contradiction 26 7.1 Method . 26 7.2 Hard parts? . 26 7.3 Examples of proof by contradiction . 26 8 Contrapositive 29 8.1 Method . 29 8.2 Hard parts? . 29 8.3 Examples . 29 9 Tips 31 9.1 What common mistakes do students make when trying to present the proofs? . 31 9.2 What are the reasons for mistakes? . 32 9.3 Advice to students for writing good proofs . 32 9.4 Friendly reminder . 32 c University of Birmingham 2014 10 Sets 34 10.1 Basics . 34 10.2 Subsets and power sets . 34 10.3 Cardinality and equality .
    [Show full text]
  • Contents 1 Proofs, Logic, and Sets
    Introduction to Proof (part 1): Proofs, Logic, and Sets (by Evan Dummit, 2019, v. 1.00) Contents 1 Proofs, Logic, and Sets 1 1.1 Overview of Mathematical Proof . 1 1.2 Elements of Logic . 5 1.2.1 Propositions and Conditional Statements . 5 1.2.2 Boolean Operators and Boolean Logic . 8 1.3 Sets and Set Operations . 11 1.3.1 Sets . 11 1.3.2 Subsets . 12 1.3.3 Intersections and Unions . 14 1.3.4 Complements and Universal Sets . 17 1.3.5 Cartesian Products . 20 1.4 Quantiers . 22 1.4.1 Quantiers and Variables . 22 1.4.2 Properties of Quantiers . 24 1.4.3 Examples Involving Quantiers . 26 1.4.4 Families of Sets . 28 1 Proofs, Logic, and Sets In this chapter, we introduce a number of foundational concepts for rigorous mathematics, including an overview of mathematical proof, elements of Boolean and propositional logic, and basic elements of set theory. 1.1 Overview of Mathematical Proof • In colloquial usage, to provide proof of something means to provide strong evidence for a particular claim. • In mathematics, we formalize this intuitive idea of proof by making explicit the types of logical inferences that are allowed. ◦ To provide a mathematical proof of a claim is to give a sequence of statements showing that a partic- ular collection of assumptions (typically called hypotheses) imply the stated result (typically called the conclusion). ◦ Each statement in a proof follows logically from the previous statements in the proof or facts known to be true from elsewhere. This type of reasoning is usually called deductive reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Ch 2: LOGIC
    2 Ch 2: LOGIC 2.1 Statements A statement is a sentence that is either true or false, but not both. Ex 1: Today is Monday. Ex 2: The integer 3 is even. Not examples: The equation 3x = 12. This is not a statement b/c it depends on the value of x. There is one value that makes it true, but the sentence is not always true. Every statement has a truth value, namely true T or false F. A sentence containing a variable(s) is called an open sentence. Ex: The integer r is even. Possible truth values are often given in a table called a truth table. Examples: P Truth table for a sentence P: T F P Q T T Truth table for two sentences P and Q: T F F T F F Thus two statements will give us 22 combinations (rows below the one with P and Q) in the table. For three statements we would get 23 combinations, since there are two choices for each of the three statement(either T or F). 2.2 The Negation of a statement The negation of a statement P is the statement ∼ P : not P . Ex: P : 3 is even. ∼ P : 3 is not even. OR: ∼ P : 3 is odd. Observe that when the statement is false, its negation is true. P ∼ P Truth table for sentence ∼ P : T F F T 2.3 The Disjunction and Conjunction of a Statement For two statements P and Q, the disjunction of P and Q is P ∨ Q (P or Q).
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Formal Logic
    forall x: Calgary An Introduction to Formal Logic By P. D. Magnus Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis Robert Trueman remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc Richard Zach Fall 2021 This book is based on forallx: Cambridge, by Tim Button (University College Lon- don), used under a CC BY 4.0 license, which is based in turn on forallx, by P.D. Magnus (University at Albany, State University of New York), used under a CC BY 4.0 li- cense, and was remixed, revised, & expanded by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc & Richard Zach (University of Calgary). It includes additional material from forallx by P.D. Magnus and Metatheory by Tim Button, used under a CC BY 4.0 license, from forallx: Lorain County Remix, by Cathal Woods and J. Robert Loftis, and from A Modal Logic Primer by Robert Trueman, used with permission. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 license. You are free to copy and redistribute the material in any medium or format, and remix, transform, and build upon the material for any purpose, even commercially, under the following terms: ⊲ You must give appropriate credit, provide a link to the license, and indicate if changes were made. You may do so in any reasonable manner, but not in any way that suggests the licensor endorses you or your use. ⊲ You may not apply legal terms or technological measures that legally restrict others from doing anything the license permits. The LATEX source for this book is available on GitHub and PDFs at forallx.openlogicproject.org.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic
    An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic Rebeka Ferreira and Anthony Ferrucci 1 1An Introduction to Critical Thinking and Symbolic Logic: Volume 1 Formal Logic is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. 1 Preface This textbook has developed over the last few years of teaching introductory symbolic logic and critical thinking courses. It has been truly a pleasure to have beneted from such great students and colleagues over the years. As we have become increasingly frustrated with the costs of traditional logic textbooks (though many of them deserve high praise for their accuracy and depth), the move to open source has become more and more attractive. We're happy to provide it free of charge for educational use. With that being said, there are always improvements to be made here and we would be most grateful for constructive feedback and criticism. We have chosen to write this text in LaTex and have adopted certain conventions with symbols. Certainly many important aspects of critical thinking and logic have been omitted here, including historical developments and key logicians, and for that we apologize. Our goal was to create a textbook that could be provided to students free of charge and still contain some of the more important elements of critical thinking and introductory logic. To that end, an additional benet of providing this textbook as a Open Education Resource (OER) is that we will be able to provide newer updated versions of this text more frequently, and without any concern about increased charges each time.
    [Show full text]
  • Guide to Set Theory Proofs
    CS103 Handout 07 Summer 2019 June 28, 2019 Guide to Proofs on Sets Richard Feynman, one of the greatest physicists of the twentieth century, gave a famous series of lectures on physics while a professor at Caltech. Those lectures have been recorded for posterity and are legendary for their blend of intuitive and mathematical reasoning. One of my favorite quotes from these lectures comes early on, when Feynman talks about the atomic theory of matter. Here’s a relevant excerpt: If, in some cataclysm, all of scientific knowledge were to be destroyed, and only one sen- tence passed on to the next generations of creatures, what statement would contain the most information in the fewest words? I believe it is the atomic hypothesis (or the atomic fact, or whatever you wish to call it) that all things are made of atoms [. ...] In that one sentence, you will see, there is an enormous amount of information about the world, if just a little imagination and thinking are applied. This idea argues for a serious shift in perspective about how to interpret properties of objects in the physical world. Think about how, for example, you might try to understand why steel is so much stronger and tougher than charcoal and iron. If you don’t have atomic theory, you’d proba- bly think about what sorts of “inherent qualities” charcoal and iron each possess, and how those qualities interacting with one another would give rise to steel’s strength. That’s how you’d think about things if you were an alchemist.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Theory and Logic in Greater Detail
    Chapter 1 Logic and Set Theory To criticize mathematics for its abstraction is to miss the point entirely. Abstraction is what makes mathematics work. If you concentrate too closely on too limited an application of a mathematical idea, you rob the mathematician of his most important tools: analogy, generality, and simplicity. – Ian Stewart Does God play dice? The mathematics of chaos In mathematics, a proof is a demonstration that, assuming certain axioms, some statement is necessarily true. That is, a proof is a logical argument, not an empir- ical one. One must demonstrate that a proposition is true in all cases before it is considered a theorem of mathematics. An unproven proposition for which there is some sort of empirical evidence is known as a conjecture. Mathematical logic is the framework upon which rigorous proofs are built. It is the study of the principles and criteria of valid inference and demonstrations. Logicians have analyzed set theory in great details, formulating a collection of axioms that affords a broad enough and strong enough foundation to mathematical reasoning. The standard form of axiomatic set theory is the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, together with the axiom of choice. Each of the axioms included in this the- ory expresses a property of sets that is widely accepted by mathematicians. It is unfortunately true that careless use of set theory can lead to contradictions. Avoid- ing such contradictions was one of the original motivations for the axiomatization of set theory. 1 2 CHAPTER 1. LOGIC AND SET THEORY A rigorous analysis of set theory belongs to the foundations of mathematics and mathematical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • CS 360, Winter 2011
    CS 360, Winter 2011 Morphology of Proof: An introduction to rigorous proof techniques∗ 1 Methodology of Proof | An example Deep down, all theorems are of the form \If A then B," though they may be expressed in some other way, such as \All A are B" or \Let A be true. Then B is true." Thus every proof has assumptions|the A part|and conclusions|the B part. To prove a theorem, you must combine the assumptions you are given with definitions and other theorems to prove the conclusion. Definitions and theorems let you convert statements to other statements; by stringing these together you can convert the statements of A into the statements of B. This constitutes a proof. For example: Theorem 1. Let x be a number greater than or equal to 4. Then 2x ≥ x2. This theorem converts the statement \a number x is greater than or equal to 4" to \for this number, 2x ≥ x2." We can use it in the proof of another theorem, like so: Theorem 2. Let x be the sum of four squares, a2 + b2 + c2 + d2, where a; b; c and d are positive integers. Then 2x ≥ x2. If we can prove that x is of necessity greater than or equal to 4 (by noting, for instance, that a; b; c and d are at least 1, and thus their sum is at least 4), then we can convert the assumption of our theorem from \x is the sum of four squares" to \2x ≥ x2." This completes our proof. Often, we use definitions to expand out mathematical shorthand before we can start applying proofs.
    [Show full text]