Metaphor Comprehension: from Comparison to Categorization

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Metaphor Comprehension: from Comparison to Categorization Metaphor Comprehension : From Comparison to Categorization Brian F. Bowdle Dedre Gentner Department of Psychology Department of Psychology Indiana University Northwestern University 1101 East 10' Street 2029 Sheridan Road Bloomington, IN 47405 Evanston, IL 60208 (bbowdle@indiana .edu) (gentner@nwu .edu) Abstract tony, 1979 ; Tversky, 1977) . However, more recent ver- sions of the comparison view have assumed that metaphors In this paper, we explore the relationship between metaphor act to set up correspondences between partially isomorphic and polysemy . We begin by discussing how novel meta- conceptual structures rather than between sets of independ- phoric mappings can create new word meanings in the form ent properties (e .g., Gentner, 1983 of domain-general representations. Turning next to consider ; Indurkhya, 1987 ; Kit- the implications of this view for the on-line comprehension of tay & Lehrer, 1981 ; Lakoff & Johnson, 1980 ; Verbrugge figurative language, we suggest that there is a shift from & McCarrell, 1977) . In other words, metaphor can be seen comparison processing to categorization processing as meta- as a species of analogy, phors are conventionalized . Finally, we describe a series of We will use Gentner's (1983) structure-mapping theory experimental findings that support the proposed account. to articulate the processes that may take place during meta- phor comprehension . Structure-mapping theory assumes that interpreting a metaphor involves two interrelated Introduction mechanisms: alignment and projection . The alignment process operates in a local-to-global fashion to create a Metaphors establish mappings between concepts from dis- maximal structurally consistent match between two repre- parate domains of knowledge . For example, in the meta- sentations that observes one-to-one mapping and phor The mind is a computer, an abstract entity is described parallel connectivity (Falkenhainer, Forbus, & Gentner, 1989) . That in terms of a complex electronic device . It is widely be- lieved that metaphors are a major source of knowledge is, each object of one representation can be placed in corre- change, and a great deal of research has examined how spondence with at most one object of the other representa- metaphors can enrich and illuminate concepts that would tion, and arguments of aligned relations are themselves aligned. A further constraint on the alignment process is otherwise remain vague or ambiguous . However, there systematicity : Alignments that form deeply interconnected have been far fewer . explorations of a second generative structures, in which higher-order relations constrain lower- function of metaphors - namely, lexical extension . In this order relations, are preferred over less systematic sets of paper, we will discuss (1) how novel metaphoric mappings commonalities. Once a structurally consistent match be- can create new word meanings in the form of domain- general representations, and (2) how these new meanings tween the target and base domains has been found, further predicates from the base that are connected to the common may be applied during the comprehension of conventional system can be projected to the target as candidate infer- metaphors . Before turning to these issues, however, it is ences . necessary to consider the nature of metaphoric mappings in According to structure-mapping theory, metaphors of- greater depth . ten convey that a system of relations holding among the base objects also holds among the target objects, regardless Metaphor and Analogy of whether the objects themselves are intrinsically similar. Metaphors are traditionally viewed as comparisons between Thus, the metaphor Socrates was a midwife highlights cer . the target (a-term) and the base (b-term) . According to tain relational similarities between the individuals - both many early models, metaphors are understood by means of help others produce something - despite the fact that the a simple feature-matching process (e.g., Miller, 1979 ; Or- arguments of these relations are quite different in the target Bowdle, B . F., & Gentner, D . (1999) . Metaphor comprehension: From comparison to categorization. Proceedings of the Twenty-First Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 90- 95 . 90 and base domains: Socrates helped his students produce same base term is repeatedly aligned with different targets ideas, whereas a midwife helps a mother produce a baby. so as to yield the same basic interpretation, then the high- The centrality of relations during metaphor comprehension lighted system may become conventionally associated with has been confirmed by a number of studies . For example, the base as an abstract metaphoric category. At this point, people's interpretations of metaphors tend to include more the base term will be polysemous, having both a domain- relations than simple attributes, even for statements that specific meaning and a related domain-general meaning . suggest both types of commonalities (e.g., Gentner & Clem- We will refer to this proposed evolution as the career of ent, 1988; Shen, 1992 ; Tourangeau & Rips, 1991) . Fur- metaphor hypothesis . (For related proposals, see Holyoak ther, Gentner & Clement (1988) found that the relationality & Thagard, 1995 ; Murphy, 1996) . of people's interpretations of metaphors was positively re- lated to the judged aptness of these same metaphors . Implications for Metaphor Comprehension Research on metaphor comprehension often treats metaphor Metaphor and Polysemy as an undifferentiated type of figurative language . How- Like analogies, metaphors can lend additional structure to ever, a number of theorists have recently argued that meta- problematic target concepts, thereby making these concepts phor is pluralistic, and that the manner in which a metaphor more coherent. However, this is not the only way in which is comprehended may depend on its level of conventionality metaphors can lead to knowledge change . Metaphors are (e.g., Blank, 1988; Blasko & Connine, 1993 ; Giora, 1997 ; also a primary source of polysemy - they allow words with Turner & Katz, 1997). Our account of the relationship be- specific meanings to take on additional, related meanings tween metaphor and polysemy is in line with these claims . (e.g., Lakoff, 1987 ; Lehrer, 1990 ; Miller, 1979; Nunberg, Specifically, we believe (1) that the process of convention- 1979; Sweetser, 1990) . For example, consider the word alization is essentially one of a base term acquiring a do- roadblock. There was presumably a time when this word main-general meaning, and (2) that this representational referred only, to a barricade set up in a road . With repeated shift will be accompanied by a shift in mode of processing . metaphoric use, however, roadblock has also come to refer These ideas are illustrated in Figure 1, which shows to any obstacle to meeting a goal (as in Fear is a roadblock how novel and conventional metaphors differ on the career to success). of metaphor view . Novel metaphors involve base terms that How do metaphors create new word meanings? One refer to a domain-specific concept, but are not (yet) associ- recent and influential proposal is that such lexical exten- ated with a domain-general category . For example, the sions are due to stable projections of conceptual structures novel base term glacier (as in Science is a glacier) has a and corresponding vocabulary items from one (typically literal sense - "a large body of ice spreading outward over a concrete) domain of experience to another (typically ab- land surface" - but no related metaphoric sense (e.g., stract) domain of experience (e .g., Lakoff, 1987 ; Lehrer, "anything that progresses slowly but steadily") . Novel 1990; Sweetser, 1990). On this view, the metaphoric metaphors are therefore interpreted as comparisons, in meaning of a polysemous word is understood directly in which the target concept is structurally aligned with the lit- terms of the word's literal meaning . eral base concept. However, metaphoric categories may We wish to consider an alternative account of the rela- arise as a byproduct of this comparison process . tionship between metaphor and polysemy - one that follows In contrast to novel metaphors, conventional metaphors naturally from viewing metaphor as a species of analogy . involve base terms that refer both to a literal concept and to Research on analogical problem solving has shown that the an associated metaphoric category . For example, the con- alignment of two relationally similar situations can lead to ventional base term blueprint (as in A gene is a blueprint) the induction of domain-general problem schemas that can has two closely related senses: "a blue and white photo- be applied to future situations (e.g., Gick & Holyoak, 1983 ; graphic print in showing an architect's plan" and "anything Novick & Holyoak, 1991 ; Ross & Kennedy, 1990) . We that provides a plan." Conventional base terms are polyse- believe that similar forces are at work during metaphor mous, and the literal and metaphoric meanings are semanti- comprehension . The central idea is that the process of cally linked due to their similarity. Conventional metaphors structural alignment allows for the induction of metaphoric may therefore be interpreted either as comparisons, by categories, which may in turn be lexicalized as secondary matching the target concept with the literal base concept, or senses of metaphor base terms (Bowdle, 1998 ; Bowdle & as categorizations, by seeing the target concept as a member Gentner,
Recommended publications
  • Waking up from «Conjecture» As Well As from «Dream»
    DOSSIER WAKING UP FROM «CONJECTURE» AS WELL AS FROM «DREAM» A presentation of AIME Text: Bruno Latour GAD Distinguished Lecture, American Anthropology Association meeting, Chicago 21st of November 2013 1 Abstract As every ethnographer knows, in addition to the many blunders every one of us commits in the course of our feldwork, there exist also graver mistakes when we sense a mistaken regime of reality granted to an entity. It is at those moments, usually the most revealing in the course of our inquiries, when we try to repair broken relations by some innovative move to defne the status of the contrasting realities that have been open to misinterpretation. During the last quarter century I have attempted, quite systematically, to increase the number of templates by which the so-called Moderns account for themselves; not, to be sure, in their ofcial representation (they remain staunch adepts of the Object-Subject Operating System and will swear that they are obedient naturalists), but by looking for the many occasions where they express dissatisfaction with such an ofcial view of themselves. What I think I have documented are the protestations by many diferent people that a skewed template is being used to account for the mode of existence of the agencies that are most attached to them. Keywords: method; ontology; modernism; inquiry; physical anthropology; diplomacy «Thus there would be two natures, (the world is made of objects and subjects, period) with the one is the conJecture bewildering number of entities they have never ceased to and the other is the dream» encounter or to generate along their path.
    [Show full text]
  • Mastering the Metaphor
    Mastering the Metaphor ACBS World Conference IX Colleen Ehrnstrom, Ph.D. Boulder, Colorado, USA www.actskillsgroup.com Many thanks to Chad Emrick and Carl Baccellieri and the Boulder ACT consultation group for their advice and feedback regarding this workshop. We utter about one metaphor for every 10 to 25 words, or about six metaphors a minute (Geary, 2011). Metaphors are represented in this presentation in both written and visual form. Metaphor: Picture is worth a 1000 words (embedded in computer metaphor) 1. Learn where metaphors fit into the infrastructure of the ACT model 2. Understand the basic science of metaphors 3. Know and apply the guidelines for using metaphors in therapy 4. Watch therapists use metaphors in the therapeutic context 5. Practice using some ACT metaphors in the therapeutic context Mechanistic versus Contextual Metaphor: Bank of a stream– Where does the bank end and the water begin? Functional Contextualism – given the context, what is the function? Metaphor: Google maps v floorplan – do you want to drive there or live there? Suffering is related to language Metaphor: Your words slice through me like knives RFT is the science behind ACT Metaphor: Driving a car without knowing the mechanics of it Pliance (“plys”) – compliance with verbal rules that are socially supported. Plys are typically our first introduction to rules. Examples: Eat 5 servings of fruits and vegetables to stay healthy Wear a coat – it is cold outside Metaphor: Go the extra mile What are your plys about doing ACT in the therapy room?? Plys are more prevalent because they do not require direct experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Use of Metaphor in Poetry
    THE USE OF METAPHOR IN POETRY structure 3.0 - Aims and Objectives 3.1 Introduction 3.2 Traditional definition of metaphor 3.3 Distinction between simile and metaphor 3.3.1 Changein the trditidndunof metaphor 3.3.2 Difference between traditional and modern uses of metaphor 3.4 Simile and metaphor in a chain 3.4.1 Comptex metaphors 3.4.2 Symbd and conceit 3.5 Varieties of metaphor 3.5.1 Contemporary concept ofmetaphor 3.5.2 USe of me!apbor in modern poetry 3.6 imageas metaphor 3.7 Analogical and contextual notions of metaphor 3.8 Summing up 3.9 Activities: aids to answers 3.10 Glossary 3.0 AIMS ANI) OBJECTIVES This Unit discusses the use of metaphor in poetry. After going through it, you wiU learn that metaphor, like simite, is based on comparison between two dissimjlar the; the language we use being metaphoric in origin, some of our expressions have lost their original metaphoric character and have become dead metaphors; the traditional definition of metaphor as shortened simile has become modified in that metaphors.are not &&ed tidm simple logical comparisons; 0 dilethe traditional use ofwetaphor is for bringing out the points of similarity between two things, the mderh use of it is to make it serve as a ceqtral concept of the poem; in many poems the simik and the metaphor are indeed combined as in a chain. This suggests that though a siml is at the root of every metaphor, it is metaphor that - makes the poem vivid and symbolical; if the suggestecf-resemblane of the things compared is far-fetched or arbitrary, the metaphor acquires the character of a symbol or a conceit; * poets no longer consider a wtaphor as a distinct rhetorical element but associate it with other stylistic elements as 'metaphors'; * metaphor has become a condition of poetry and a means for the evocathn of connota~imand assoeiationscentral to the poem; in mdmpoetry,metaphar implies a transaction between contexts and kelps the overt meanings of images toacquire metaphoric significance; and .
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Workers in the Vineyard
    Workers in the Vineyard This parable (Mt 20:1-16) is about several workers who are hired by a land owner, over different periods of time. In the evening, the workers who are hired first expect to be paid more than those hired later. But the owner pays all of the workers equally. Land Owner: Most of the productive land was held by large-scale elite owners. From the First Temple period through the Second, a pronounced shift in the patterns of land tenure took place, shifting from smallholders producing the Mediterranean triad of grain, grapes and olives for subsistence to large estates orientated to large-scale production and export crops. The owner in this parable is one of the wealthy sub-elites who owned large estates and converted the land to viticulture dedicated to the production of export crops. Laborers: The social order consisted of a patron-and-client society of unequal relationships with the estate owners assuming the role of patrons and those who have lost the land becoming their clients. In such a relationship the client’s wellbeing is determined by the closeness of rapport he maintains with the patron. The landless laborers in the parable did not belong to the ambit of such a relationship. They were outside of any assured protection and regular work opportunity and, hence, more vulnerable to be deprived of their basic wages even on rare occasions when they found a work to do. Early workers: The working hours of the Israelites were 12 and was counted from 6:00 A.M.
    [Show full text]
  • Detecting Novel Metaphor Using Selectional Preference Information
    Detecting novel metaphor using selectional preference information Hessel Haagsma and Johannes Bjerva University of Groningen The Netherlands Abstract costs an arm and a leg.’ and the Dutch ‘Dit lesboek kost een rib uit het lijf.’ (lit. ‘This textbook costs a Recent work on metaphor processing often rib from the body.’) to be mapped to the same mean- employs selectional preference information. ing representation, which should not include refer- We present a comparison of different ap- ences to any of the body parts used in the idiomatic proaches to the modelling of selectional pref- erences, based on various ways of generaliz- expressions. ing over corpus frequencies. We evaluate on In this paper, we focus on one area of figurative the VU Amsterdam Metaphor corpus, a broad language processing, namely the detection of novel corpus of metaphor. We find that using only metaphor, and especially the utility of selectional selectional preference information is enough preference features for this task. By doing this, we to outperform an all-metaphor baseline clas- hope to answer a two-fold question: can selectional sification, but that generalization through pre- preference information be used to successfully de- diction or clustering is not beneficial. A pos- tect novel metaphor? And how do generalization sible explanation for this lies in the nature of the evaluation data, and lack of power of se- methods influence the effectiveness of selectional lectional preference information on its own preference information? for non-novel metaphor detection. To bet- ter investigate the role of metaphor type in 2 Background metaphor detection, we suggest a resource with annotation of novel metaphor should be 2.1 Types of metaphor in language created.
    [Show full text]
  • Ockham's Razor, Truth, and Information
    Ockham's Razor, Truth, and Information Kevin T. Kelly Department of Philosophy Carnegie Mellon University [email protected] March 11, 2008 Abstract In science, one faces the problem of selecting the true theory from a range of al- ternative theories. The typical response is to select the simplest theory compatible with available evidence, on the authority of \Ockham's Razor". But how can a ¯xed bias toward simplicity help one ¯nd possibly complex truths? A short survey of standard answers to this question reveals them to be either wishful, circular, or irrelevant. A new explanation is presented, based on minimizing the reversals of opinion prior to convergence to the truth. According to this alternative approach, Ockham's razor does not inform one which theory is true but is, nonetheless, the uniquely most e±cient strategy for arriving at the true theory, where e±ciency is a matter of minimizing reversals of opinion prior to ¯nding the true theory. 1 Introduction Suppose that several or even in¯nitely many theories are compatible with the infor- mation available. How ought one to choose among them, if at all? The traditional and intuitive answer is to choose the \simplest" and to cite Ockham's razor by way of justi¯cation. Simplicity, in turn, has something to do with minimization of entities, de- scription length, causes, free parameters, independent principlies, or ad hoc hypotheses, or maximization of unity, uniformity, symmetry, testability, or explanatory power. Insofar as Ockham's razor is widely regarded as a rule of scienti¯c inference, it should help one to select the true theory from among the alternatives.
    [Show full text]
  • Narrative and Metaphor As Conceptual Tools for Understanding Evolution Theory
    Narrative and Metaphor as Conceptual Tools for Understanding Evolution Theory Paper for the Proceedings of the International Conference „Innovazione nella didattica delle scienze nella scuola primaria e dell’infanzia’ 21-22 Novembre 2014 Università degli Studi di Modena e Reggio Emilia. Jörg Zabel Institute for Biology Biology Education Johannisallee 21-23 04103 Leipzig, Germany e-mail: [email protected] phone: +49 (0) 341 97-36641 fax: +49 (0) 341 97-36899 http://www.uni-leipzig.de/~biodidak/ Abstract Human beings ‘make sense of the world by telling stories about it’ (Bruner 1996, p.130). Thus, meaningful narrative explanations cannot simply be replaced by scientific conceptions that are contradictory to the learner's experimental realism (Gropengiesser 2003). This is specifically relevant in those domains of science where conceptual change in favour of scientific explanations is difficult to achieve, e.g. the theory of evolution. Learners tend to make sense of the phenomena in their own, non-scientific way that includes intentional and teleological explanations. This paper focuses on the role of a so-called ‘narrative mode of thought’ (Bruner 1996) for meaning making in the science classroom. We present results from a study in lower secondary school (age 12-13 ys.), exploring how students make sense of adaptation phenomena. Before and after a teaching sequence on the theory of evolution, students explained the evolution of modern whales from their terrestrial ancestors by writing narrative or non-narrative texts on the issue. Text analysis, combined with student interviews, revealed students' conceptions and their individual methods of making sense of adaptation phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • THE GOOD SAMARITAN AS METAPHOR Robert W
    THE GOOD SAMARITAN AS METAPHOR Robert W. Funk University of Montana ABSTRACT The parable of the Good Samaritan is commonly under­ stood as an example story, offering an example of what it means to be a good neighbor. But the parable does not invite the hearer to view it as an example of what it means to be a good neighbor. Rather, it invites the auditor to be the victim in the ditch, as a careful reading indicates. The "meaning" of the parable is the way auditors take up rôles in the story and play out the drama. As a drama into which the hearers are drawn, the parable suggests that in the Kingdom mercy is always a surprise. 0. Literary and biblical critics have always deemed it an important matter to determine the kind of language being used in any text to be interpreted. In some cases it is crucial. For example, the argument over whether the parable of the Good Samaritan is a parable or an example story can be settled only in conjunction with determining the nature of the language. The view advocated here is that the Good Samaritan is metaphorical and there­ fore not an example story (cf. Funk: 199-222). This understanding runs counter to both the ancient and the modern traditions of interpretation. Dominic Crossan has joined the battle on the side of metaphor, while Dan Via has supported the older view with structuralist arguments (Semeia 1, 1974). The Good Samaritan is a particularly interest­ ing case because the story is felt to be a powerful symbol in the Jesus tradition and yet it is taken literally by most interpreters.
    [Show full text]
  • Grammar in Metaphor: a Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language
    UC Berkeley Dissertations, Department of Linguistics Title Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/9d9222f9 Author Sullivan, Karen Publication Date 2007 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language by Karen Sorensen Sullivan B.A. (University of Oregon) 2001 M.A. (University of California, Berkeley) 2004 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Eve Sweetser, Chair Professor Gary Holland Professor George Lakoff Professor John Lindow Professor Richard Rhodes Fall 2007 Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language © 2007 by Karen Sorensen Sullivan Abstract Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language by Karen Sorensen Sullivan Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics University of California, Berkeley Professor Eve Sweetser, Chair Over the past few decades, the conceptual metaphor revolution inspired by Lakoff and Johnson (1980) has offered considerable insight into the conceptual structure of metaphor. However, interest in the conceptual characteristics of metaphor has sometimes overshadowed the question of how metaphor surfaces in language. This dissertation tackles the issue of metaphoric language by identifying how specific linguistic resources – from grammatical constructions to poetic devices – are employed to convey the conceptual structure of metaphor. The dissertation focuses on the role of grammatical constructions in metaphoric language. In metaphoric phrases that can be understood out of context, such as bright idea, the dissertation argues that words in particular constructional slots indicate the source domain of a conceptual metaphor (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's a Priori Metaphor
    Aporia vol. 22 no. 1—2012 Aristotle’s A Priori Metaphor SEAN DRISCOLL he paradigm of Aristotelian science continues to cause tension be- tween scientific and literary language1. Aristotle’s scientific legacy, Tthe dominance of a strictly logical method, disbars and degrades any methodology which it deems not as rigorous. Accordingly, the scien- tific tradition enthrones the use of unambiguous language because it as- sumes that Aristotle’s systematic methodology rejects literary explanations of reality; scientists consider any such poetic descriptions to be derivative. While tropes such as analogy, metaphor, and simile are regarded as valu- able for colorful writing2, they are dismissed as inappropriate for scientific discourse. Mary Hesse expresses her grief at this dismissal: It is still unfortunately necessary to argue that metaphor is more than a decorative literary device and that it has cognitive implications whose nature is a proper subject of philosophic discussion. (158) Because I agree with Hesse’s complaint, I will show how the scientific tradi- tion has misjudged Aristotle’s comments on metaphor. Though metaphor certainly serves as a rhetorical or literary device, it is not merely so. Not 1This paper uses the term ‘scientific’ in a broad sense. Because Aristotle’s relevant comments mostly concern the foundations of science, I have adopted that language to speak about a topic which has obvious philosophical implications. 2Though there are certainly substantial differences between the various literary tropes and their cognitive functions, Aristotle often writes about metaphor as their genus. Following this, I will not emphasize the differences. Sean Driscoll is a junior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphor and Philosophy: an Encounter with Derrida
    Metaphor and philosophy: an encounter with Derrida Article (Published Version) Morris, Michael (2000) Metaphor and philosophy: an encounter with Derrida. Philosophy, 75 (2). 225 - 244. ISSN 0031-8191 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/15696/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Royal Institute of Philosophy Metaphor and Philosophy: An Encounter with Derrida Author(s): Michael Morris Source: Philosophy, Vol. 75, No. 292 (Apr., 2000), pp. 225-244 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3751812 .
    [Show full text]