Detecting Novel Metaphor Using Selectional Preference Information

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Detecting Novel Metaphor Using Selectional Preference Information Detecting novel metaphor using selectional preference information Hessel Haagsma and Johannes Bjerva University of Groningen The Netherlands Abstract costs an arm and a leg.’ and the Dutch ‘Dit lesboek kost een rib uit het lijf.’ (lit. ‘This textbook costs a Recent work on metaphor processing often rib from the body.’) to be mapped to the same mean- employs selectional preference information. ing representation, which should not include refer- We present a comparison of different ap- ences to any of the body parts used in the idiomatic proaches to the modelling of selectional pref- erences, based on various ways of generaliz- expressions. ing over corpus frequencies. We evaluate on In this paper, we focus on one area of figurative the VU Amsterdam Metaphor corpus, a broad language processing, namely the detection of novel corpus of metaphor. We find that using only metaphor, and especially the utility of selectional selectional preference information is enough preference features for this task. By doing this, we to outperform an all-metaphor baseline clas- hope to answer a two-fold question: can selectional sification, but that generalization through pre- preference information be used to successfully de- diction or clustering is not beneficial. A pos- tect novel metaphor? And how do generalization sible explanation for this lies in the nature of the evaluation data, and lack of power of se- methods influence the effectiveness of selectional lectional preference information on its own preference information? for non-novel metaphor detection. To bet- ter investigate the role of metaphor type in 2 Background metaphor detection, we suggest a resource with annotation of novel metaphor should be 2.1 Types of metaphor in language created. The first part of any work on metaphor processing is is to arrive at a definition for ‘metaphor’. A good starting point for this is the MIP frame- 1 Introduction work (Pragglejaz Group, 2007), which has this as Within natural language processing (NLP), there has the most important criterion for metaphor: ‘a lexi- been an increasing interest in the processing of fig- cal unit is metaphorical if it has a more basic con- urative language in recent years. This increasing in- temporary meaning in other contexts than in the cur- terest is exemplified by the (NA)ACL workshops on rent context’ (paraphrased). Where ‘more basic’ is metaphor in NLP, and shared tasks like SemEval- defined as more concrete, related to bodily action, 2015, Task 11, about sentiment analysis of figurative more precise, and historically older. This is a very language in Twitter. broad definition, causing many meanings to be clas- The main benefits of improved treatment of figu- sified as metaphorical. rative language within NLP lie with high-level tasks Examples of this are found in the VU Amster- dependent on semantics, such as semantic parsing. dam Metaphor corpus, which is annotated using the For example, in multilingual semantic parsing, one MIPVU procedure (Steen et al., 2010), an exten- would like to see both the English ‘This textbook sion of MIP. In the corpus, we find a wide range of 10 Proceedings of The Fourth Workshop on Metaphor in NLP, pages 10–17, San Diego, CA, 17 June 2016. c 2016 Association for Computational Linguistics metaphor from highly conventionalized metaphor, ble pitfall of trying to solve two essentially different such as have in Example 1, to more clear metaphor- problems using the same method. ical cases, like rolling in Example 2. 2.2 Selectional preference violation as a feature (1) Do the Greeks have a word for it? for metaphor detection (2) [...] the hillsides ceased their upward Because, by definition, we cannot use a pre-existing rolling and curved together [...] sense or meaning definition for novel metaphor, novel metaphor processing provides a new kind of Three general categories of meaning can be dis- challenge. On the other hand, with the ultimate goal tinguished. The first type of contextual meaning is of integrating figurative language processing in a se- literal meaning, which is the most basic meaning of mantic parsing framework, novel metaphor is the a word. This kind of meaning is generally the least most problematic for deducing meaning, and is thus problematic, since the meaning can be deduced from the most relevant and interesting. the lexicon. The second type of meaning is conven- Another important aspect of novel metaphors is tional metaphorical meaning, i.e. a non-basic mean- that they tend to be less frequent than conventional ing of a word, which is also in the lexicon or sense metaphor (and literals). This has the advantage of inventory. making one feature commonly used for metaphor Novel metaphors form a third type of contextual detection, selectional preference violation, more ef- meaning, one which is non-basic, but is not ac- fective. counted for by the lexicon either. These are the most The idea of using selectional preference viola- problematic, since their meaning cannot be deduced tion as an indicator of metaphoricity goes far back by selecting the correct sense from a sense inventory. (Wilks, 1975; Wilks, 1978), and has been widely Aligned with the distinction between conven- used in previous work on metaphor detection (Fass, tional metaphor and novel metaphor is the dis- 1991; Mason, 2004; Jia and Yu, 2008; Shutova et tinction between word sense disambiguation and al., 2010; Neuman et al., 2013; Wilks et al., 2013). metaphor detection. That is, word sense dis- Using selectional preference violation as a heuris- ambiguation can be expected to cover literal and tic works well, but has the fundamental shortcoming conventionalized metaphorical meanings, whereas that selectional preferences are based on frequency; metaphor processing is necessary to deal with novel selectional preference data are obtained from a cor- metaphorical meanings. pus by counting how often words occur together in a We argue here that the most important applica- certain relation. Metaphor, on the other hand, is de- tion of metaphor processing approaches lies not with fined by basicness of meaning, and not frequency of conventional metaphors, but with novel metaphors. meaning. Although these two are correlated, there This type of metaphor is the most problematic for are also many cases where the figurative sense of a other NLP applications, since it requires a deduction word has become more frequent than its original, lit- of meaning from outside the sense lexicon. There- eral sense. fore, it requires a dedicated metaphor processing The result of this is that metaphor detection sys- system, whereas more conventional metaphor can, tems based on selectional preferences erroneously in principle, be handled by existing WSD systems. classify low-frequent literals as metaphorical and This is not to say that metaphor processing re- high-frequent metaphors as literal. However, if we search should exclusively focus on novel metaphor, intend only to capture novel metaphors, the selec- since insights about metaphor and metaphoricity can tional preference violation approach is less vulnera- definitely be useful for improving the handling of ble to these errors, since novel metaphors are less conventional metaphor within a word sense disam- likely to be mistakenly classified as literal due to biguation framework. Nevertheless, the approach their lower frequency. proposed in this paper aims only to deal with novel As such, we hypothesize that this feature, when metaphor. In addition, separating the treatment of used correctly, can be very useful for metaphor de- novel and conventional metaphor avoids the possi- tection. To this purpose, we examine new ways of 11 generalizing over selectional preferences obtained scientific or encyclopaedia-style text. In contrast, from a corpus. the data used for evaluation is taken from differ- ent parts of the BNC, which represent different gen- 3 Methods res. Nevertheless, we assume that the larger size and number of topics of the Wikipedia corpus compen- Selectional preference information can be automati- sate for this. cally gathered from a large, parsed corpus. This al- As a dependency parser, we use the spacy.io3 lows for counting the occurrences of specific pairs, Python library, because of its speed, high accuracy such as ‘evoke-excitement’. Based on this, we can and ease-of-use. From the parsed corpus, all verb- then calculate conditional probabilities or a measure noun pairs with the labels nsubj and dobj were like selectional association (Resnik, 1993). extracted and counted. This yielded 101 million However, even a very large corpus will not yield verb-subject triples of 14.0 million distinct types and full coverage of all possible pairs. This could cause 67 million verb-object triples of 7.8 million distinct the system to flag, for example ‘evoke-exhilaration’ types. The triples contained 175,630 verb lemma as a selectional preference violation and thus as types and 1,982,512 noun lemma types. metaphoric, simply because this combination occurs very infrequently in the corpus. 3.2 Selectional preference metrics The solution to this problem is to do some sort of Selectional preference information can be used in generalization over these verb-noun pairs. One way three ways: as a conditional probability, a selec- of doing this is to perform clustering the verbs and tional preference strength for the verb, and as selec- nouns in semantically coherent classes. We test two tional association between a verb and a noun. The clustering methods: Brown clustering (Brown et al., conditional probability is defined as follows: 1992), and a novel method, which relies on k-means clustering of word embeddings. P (n, v) c(n, v) P (n v) = (1) In addition to these clustering methods, we also | P (v) ≈ c(v) look at using word embeddings directly in a classi- Where P (n v) is the probability of seeing noun n | fier, in order to prevent the information loss inher- occurring with verb v.
Recommended publications
  • Waking up from «Conjecture» As Well As from «Dream»
    DOSSIER WAKING UP FROM «CONJECTURE» AS WELL AS FROM «DREAM» A presentation of AIME Text: Bruno Latour GAD Distinguished Lecture, American Anthropology Association meeting, Chicago 21st of November 2013 1 Abstract As every ethnographer knows, in addition to the many blunders every one of us commits in the course of our feldwork, there exist also graver mistakes when we sense a mistaken regime of reality granted to an entity. It is at those moments, usually the most revealing in the course of our inquiries, when we try to repair broken relations by some innovative move to defne the status of the contrasting realities that have been open to misinterpretation. During the last quarter century I have attempted, quite systematically, to increase the number of templates by which the so-called Moderns account for themselves; not, to be sure, in their ofcial representation (they remain staunch adepts of the Object-Subject Operating System and will swear that they are obedient naturalists), but by looking for the many occasions where they express dissatisfaction with such an ofcial view of themselves. What I think I have documented are the protestations by many diferent people that a skewed template is being used to account for the mode of existence of the agencies that are most attached to them. Keywords: method; ontology; modernism; inquiry; physical anthropology; diplomacy «Thus there would be two natures, (the world is made of objects and subjects, period) with the one is the conJecture bewildering number of entities they have never ceased to and the other is the dream» encounter or to generate along their path.
    [Show full text]
  • Mastering the Metaphor
    Mastering the Metaphor ACBS World Conference IX Colleen Ehrnstrom, Ph.D. Boulder, Colorado, USA www.actskillsgroup.com Many thanks to Chad Emrick and Carl Baccellieri and the Boulder ACT consultation group for their advice and feedback regarding this workshop. We utter about one metaphor for every 10 to 25 words, or about six metaphors a minute (Geary, 2011). Metaphors are represented in this presentation in both written and visual form. Metaphor: Picture is worth a 1000 words (embedded in computer metaphor) 1. Learn where metaphors fit into the infrastructure of the ACT model 2. Understand the basic science of metaphors 3. Know and apply the guidelines for using metaphors in therapy 4. Watch therapists use metaphors in the therapeutic context 5. Practice using some ACT metaphors in the therapeutic context Mechanistic versus Contextual Metaphor: Bank of a stream– Where does the bank end and the water begin? Functional Contextualism – given the context, what is the function? Metaphor: Google maps v floorplan – do you want to drive there or live there? Suffering is related to language Metaphor: Your words slice through me like knives RFT is the science behind ACT Metaphor: Driving a car without knowing the mechanics of it Pliance (“plys”) – compliance with verbal rules that are socially supported. Plys are typically our first introduction to rules. Examples: Eat 5 servings of fruits and vegetables to stay healthy Wear a coat – it is cold outside Metaphor: Go the extra mile What are your plys about doing ACT in the therapy room?? Plys are more prevalent because they do not require direct experience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Use of Metaphor in Poetry
    THE USE OF METAPHOR IN POETRY structure 3.0 - Aims and Objectives 3.1 Introduction 3.2 Traditional definition of metaphor 3.3 Distinction between simile and metaphor 3.3.1 Changein the trditidndunof metaphor 3.3.2 Difference between traditional and modern uses of metaphor 3.4 Simile and metaphor in a chain 3.4.1 Comptex metaphors 3.4.2 Symbd and conceit 3.5 Varieties of metaphor 3.5.1 Contemporary concept ofmetaphor 3.5.2 USe of me!apbor in modern poetry 3.6 imageas metaphor 3.7 Analogical and contextual notions of metaphor 3.8 Summing up 3.9 Activities: aids to answers 3.10 Glossary 3.0 AIMS ANI) OBJECTIVES This Unit discusses the use of metaphor in poetry. After going through it, you wiU learn that metaphor, like simite, is based on comparison between two dissimjlar the; the language we use being metaphoric in origin, some of our expressions have lost their original metaphoric character and have become dead metaphors; the traditional definition of metaphor as shortened simile has become modified in that metaphors.are not &&ed tidm simple logical comparisons; 0 dilethe traditional use ofwetaphor is for bringing out the points of similarity between two things, the mderh use of it is to make it serve as a ceqtral concept of the poem; in many poems the simik and the metaphor are indeed combined as in a chain. This suggests that though a siml is at the root of every metaphor, it is metaphor that - makes the poem vivid and symbolical; if the suggestecf-resemblane of the things compared is far-fetched or arbitrary, the metaphor acquires the character of a symbol or a conceit; * poets no longer consider a wtaphor as a distinct rhetorical element but associate it with other stylistic elements as 'metaphors'; * metaphor has become a condition of poetry and a means for the evocathn of connota~imand assoeiationscentral to the poem; in mdmpoetry,metaphar implies a transaction between contexts and kelps the overt meanings of images toacquire metaphoric significance; and .
    [Show full text]
  • A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1990 The piE stemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics. Rodney Kennedy Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Kennedy, Rodney, "The pE istemic Power of Metaphor: A Rhetorical Model for Homiletics." (1990). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5063. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5063 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Workers in the Vineyard
    Workers in the Vineyard This parable (Mt 20:1-16) is about several workers who are hired by a land owner, over different periods of time. In the evening, the workers who are hired first expect to be paid more than those hired later. But the owner pays all of the workers equally. Land Owner: Most of the productive land was held by large-scale elite owners. From the First Temple period through the Second, a pronounced shift in the patterns of land tenure took place, shifting from smallholders producing the Mediterranean triad of grain, grapes and olives for subsistence to large estates orientated to large-scale production and export crops. The owner in this parable is one of the wealthy sub-elites who owned large estates and converted the land to viticulture dedicated to the production of export crops. Laborers: The social order consisted of a patron-and-client society of unequal relationships with the estate owners assuming the role of patrons and those who have lost the land becoming their clients. In such a relationship the client’s wellbeing is determined by the closeness of rapport he maintains with the patron. The landless laborers in the parable did not belong to the ambit of such a relationship. They were outside of any assured protection and regular work opportunity and, hence, more vulnerable to be deprived of their basic wages even on rare occasions when they found a work to do. Early workers: The working hours of the Israelites were 12 and was counted from 6:00 A.M.
    [Show full text]
  • Ockham's Razor, Truth, and Information
    Ockham's Razor, Truth, and Information Kevin T. Kelly Department of Philosophy Carnegie Mellon University [email protected] March 11, 2008 Abstract In science, one faces the problem of selecting the true theory from a range of al- ternative theories. The typical response is to select the simplest theory compatible with available evidence, on the authority of \Ockham's Razor". But how can a ¯xed bias toward simplicity help one ¯nd possibly complex truths? A short survey of standard answers to this question reveals them to be either wishful, circular, or irrelevant. A new explanation is presented, based on minimizing the reversals of opinion prior to convergence to the truth. According to this alternative approach, Ockham's razor does not inform one which theory is true but is, nonetheless, the uniquely most e±cient strategy for arriving at the true theory, where e±ciency is a matter of minimizing reversals of opinion prior to ¯nding the true theory. 1 Introduction Suppose that several or even in¯nitely many theories are compatible with the infor- mation available. How ought one to choose among them, if at all? The traditional and intuitive answer is to choose the \simplest" and to cite Ockham's razor by way of justi¯cation. Simplicity, in turn, has something to do with minimization of entities, de- scription length, causes, free parameters, independent principlies, or ad hoc hypotheses, or maximization of unity, uniformity, symmetry, testability, or explanatory power. Insofar as Ockham's razor is widely regarded as a rule of scienti¯c inference, it should help one to select the true theory from among the alternatives.
    [Show full text]
  • Narrative and Metaphor As Conceptual Tools for Understanding Evolution Theory
    Narrative and Metaphor as Conceptual Tools for Understanding Evolution Theory Paper for the Proceedings of the International Conference „Innovazione nella didattica delle scienze nella scuola primaria e dell’infanzia’ 21-22 Novembre 2014 Università degli Studi di Modena e Reggio Emilia. Jörg Zabel Institute for Biology Biology Education Johannisallee 21-23 04103 Leipzig, Germany e-mail: [email protected] phone: +49 (0) 341 97-36641 fax: +49 (0) 341 97-36899 http://www.uni-leipzig.de/~biodidak/ Abstract Human beings ‘make sense of the world by telling stories about it’ (Bruner 1996, p.130). Thus, meaningful narrative explanations cannot simply be replaced by scientific conceptions that are contradictory to the learner's experimental realism (Gropengiesser 2003). This is specifically relevant in those domains of science where conceptual change in favour of scientific explanations is difficult to achieve, e.g. the theory of evolution. Learners tend to make sense of the phenomena in their own, non-scientific way that includes intentional and teleological explanations. This paper focuses on the role of a so-called ‘narrative mode of thought’ (Bruner 1996) for meaning making in the science classroom. We present results from a study in lower secondary school (age 12-13 ys.), exploring how students make sense of adaptation phenomena. Before and after a teaching sequence on the theory of evolution, students explained the evolution of modern whales from their terrestrial ancestors by writing narrative or non-narrative texts on the issue. Text analysis, combined with student interviews, revealed students' conceptions and their individual methods of making sense of adaptation phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • THE GOOD SAMARITAN AS METAPHOR Robert W
    THE GOOD SAMARITAN AS METAPHOR Robert W. Funk University of Montana ABSTRACT The parable of the Good Samaritan is commonly under­ stood as an example story, offering an example of what it means to be a good neighbor. But the parable does not invite the hearer to view it as an example of what it means to be a good neighbor. Rather, it invites the auditor to be the victim in the ditch, as a careful reading indicates. The "meaning" of the parable is the way auditors take up rôles in the story and play out the drama. As a drama into which the hearers are drawn, the parable suggests that in the Kingdom mercy is always a surprise. 0. Literary and biblical critics have always deemed it an important matter to determine the kind of language being used in any text to be interpreted. In some cases it is crucial. For example, the argument over whether the parable of the Good Samaritan is a parable or an example story can be settled only in conjunction with determining the nature of the language. The view advocated here is that the Good Samaritan is metaphorical and there­ fore not an example story (cf. Funk: 199-222). This understanding runs counter to both the ancient and the modern traditions of interpretation. Dominic Crossan has joined the battle on the side of metaphor, while Dan Via has supported the older view with structuralist arguments (Semeia 1, 1974). The Good Samaritan is a particularly interest­ ing case because the story is felt to be a powerful symbol in the Jesus tradition and yet it is taken literally by most interpreters.
    [Show full text]
  • Grammar in Metaphor: a Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language
    UC Berkeley Dissertations, Department of Linguistics Title Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/9d9222f9 Author Sullivan, Karen Publication Date 2007 eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language by Karen Sorensen Sullivan B.A. (University of Oregon) 2001 M.A. (University of California, Berkeley) 2004 A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor Eve Sweetser, Chair Professor Gary Holland Professor George Lakoff Professor John Lindow Professor Richard Rhodes Fall 2007 Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language © 2007 by Karen Sorensen Sullivan Abstract Grammar in Metaphor: A Construction Grammar Account of Metaphoric Language by Karen Sorensen Sullivan Doctor of Philosophy in Linguistics University of California, Berkeley Professor Eve Sweetser, Chair Over the past few decades, the conceptual metaphor revolution inspired by Lakoff and Johnson (1980) has offered considerable insight into the conceptual structure of metaphor. However, interest in the conceptual characteristics of metaphor has sometimes overshadowed the question of how metaphor surfaces in language. This dissertation tackles the issue of metaphoric language by identifying how specific linguistic resources – from grammatical constructions to poetic devices – are employed to convey the conceptual structure of metaphor. The dissertation focuses on the role of grammatical constructions in metaphoric language. In metaphoric phrases that can be understood out of context, such as bright idea, the dissertation argues that words in particular constructional slots indicate the source domain of a conceptual metaphor (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's a Priori Metaphor
    Aporia vol. 22 no. 1—2012 Aristotle’s A Priori Metaphor SEAN DRISCOLL he paradigm of Aristotelian science continues to cause tension be- tween scientific and literary language1. Aristotle’s scientific legacy, Tthe dominance of a strictly logical method, disbars and degrades any methodology which it deems not as rigorous. Accordingly, the scien- tific tradition enthrones the use of unambiguous language because it as- sumes that Aristotle’s systematic methodology rejects literary explanations of reality; scientists consider any such poetic descriptions to be derivative. While tropes such as analogy, metaphor, and simile are regarded as valu- able for colorful writing2, they are dismissed as inappropriate for scientific discourse. Mary Hesse expresses her grief at this dismissal: It is still unfortunately necessary to argue that metaphor is more than a decorative literary device and that it has cognitive implications whose nature is a proper subject of philosophic discussion. (158) Because I agree with Hesse’s complaint, I will show how the scientific tradi- tion has misjudged Aristotle’s comments on metaphor. Though metaphor certainly serves as a rhetorical or literary device, it is not merely so. Not 1This paper uses the term ‘scientific’ in a broad sense. Because Aristotle’s relevant comments mostly concern the foundations of science, I have adopted that language to speak about a topic which has obvious philosophical implications. 2Though there are certainly substantial differences between the various literary tropes and their cognitive functions, Aristotle often writes about metaphor as their genus. Following this, I will not emphasize the differences. Sean Driscoll is a junior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphor and Philosophy: an Encounter with Derrida
    Metaphor and philosophy: an encounter with Derrida Article (Published Version) Morris, Michael (2000) Metaphor and philosophy: an encounter with Derrida. Philosophy, 75 (2). 225 - 244. ISSN 0031-8191 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/15696/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Royal Institute of Philosophy Metaphor and Philosophy: An Encounter with Derrida Author(s): Michael Morris Source: Philosophy, Vol. 75, No. 292 (Apr., 2000), pp. 225-244 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3751812 .
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphor and Genre: an Approach to Improve the Learning Process of English for Aeronautics
    METAPHOR AND GENRE: AN APPROACH TO IMPROVE THE LEARNING PROCESS OF ENGLISH FOR AERONAUTICS Ma DEL MAR ROBISCO MARTIN* GEORGINA CUADRADO ESCLAPEZ Universidad Politecnica de Madrid ABSTRACT. This study suggests a theoretical framework for improving the teaching/ learning process of English employed in the Aeronautical discourse that brings together cognitive learning strategies, Genre Analysis and the Contemporary theory of Metaphor (Lakoff and Johnson 1980; Lakoff 1993). It maintains that cognitive strategies such as imagery, deduction, inference and grouping can be enhanced by means of metaphor and genre awareness in the context of content based approach to language learning. A list of image metaphors and conceptual metaphors which comes from the terminological database METACITEC is provided. The metaphorical terms from the area of Aeronautics have been taken from specialised dictionaries and have been categorised according to the conceptual metaphors they respond to, by establishing the source domains and the target domains, as well as the semantic networks found. This information makes reference to the internal mappings underlying the discourse of aeronautics reflected in five aviation accident case studies which are related to accident reports from the National Transportation Safety Board (NTSB) and provides an important source for designing language teaching tasks. KEY WORDS. English for Aeronautics, genre-based approach, cognitive linguistics, metaphor. RESUMEN. La Lingilistica Cognitiva y el Andlisis del Genero han contribuido a la mejora de la ensehanza de segundas lenguas y, en particular, al desarrollo de la competencia lingilistica de los alumnos de ingles para fines especificos. Este trabajo pretende perfeccionar los procesos de ensehanza y el aprendizaje del lenguaje emple- ado en el discurso aerondutico por medio de la prdctica de estrategias cognitivas y prestando atencion a la Teoria del andlisis del genero y a la Teoria contempordnea de la metdfora (Lakoff y Johnson 1980; Lakoff 1993).
    [Show full text]