Nausea Opinion and Perspectives

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nausea Opinion and Perspectives NeuroQuantology | December 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 4| Page 670-675 670 Lifintseva TP., The Buddhist pill for Satre’s Nausea Opinion and Perspectives The Buddhist Pill for Satre’s “Nausea”: Phenomenological and Hindu-Buddhist Treatments of Intentionality Tatyana Petrovna Lifintseva ABSTRACT This paper deals with one of the most complicated issues in philosophy – the problem of intentionality of consciousness. The author seeks to answer the question of whether the intentionality of consciousness can be considered a universal anthropological characteristic. Two philosophical positions regarding intentionality are compared on the basis of Jean-Paul Sartre’s major works and the sacred texts of Hinduism and Buddhism. The author first identifies certain traits of Western metaphysics, which regards consciousness as something to be revealed and to be described as intentional, and second, takes up the approach Ancient Indian metaphysics’ that regards the “depriving” consciousness of its intentionality as having a soteriological purpose. Key Words: intentionality, being, freedom, subject, subjectlessness, negaion, sansaric subject, sacred, profane NeuroQuantology 2012; 4: 670-675 1 In this paper I dare to step into the unsteady discussion regarding just epistemology in the and ungrateful soil of comparativistics and to second half of the nineteenth century and in attempt to compare Western and Indian the beginning of the twentieth century metaphysics through the philosophical and (neokantianism, phenomenology, literary creativity of Jean-Paul Sartre (1905 – empiriocriticism, pragmaticism) generated an 1980) and through various Buddhist and Vedic explosion of interest in ontology in the first sacred texts. The concept of intentionality will half of the twentieth century – from the be the key in my attempt and my research “reigns of being” of George Santayana to “the question is: the possibility of intentionality “to fundamental ontology” of Martin Heidegger be or not to be” a defining characteristic of and Systematic theology of Paul Tillich. At the consciousness. beginning of his famous book Being and Time It is possible to describe Sartre's (1927) Heidegger repeated like a conjuration: philosophy of the 1930’s and 40’s as “the “We should raise anew the question of the search for Being.” One cannot say that during meaning of Being. … The concept of “Being” the epoch he was very original in this is rather the most obscure of all. … We see aspiration. The permanent philosophical the fundamental necessity of repeating a question on the meaning of Being anew. … To retrieve the question of Being means first Corresponding author: Tatyana Lifintseva of all to work out adequately the formulation Address: Tatyana Lifintseva Vlasov st., b. 6, app. 33, Moscow region, of the question” (Heidegger, 1996. pp. xix, 2- Lyubertsy, Russia 140002. National Research University Higher School of Economics, Moscow, Russian Federation. 3). Phone: +79099748119 First, I am going to address Sartre's [email protected] Received Sept 9, 2012. Revised Dec 04, 2012. Accepted Dec 08, 2012. fundamental work Being and Nothingness eISSN 1303-5150 (1943). In this text a classical (accepted in Contributors and Supporting: Laina Saul, George Mason University Western philosophy) relation of being and (final editorial correction). www.neuroquantology.com NeuroQuantology | December 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 4| Page 670-675 671 Lifintseva TP., The Buddhist pill for Satre’s Nausea thinking, nature and spirit, matter and of an external being and its own past, its consciousness, object and subject are previous conditions. Being "nothing", Sartre’s transferred by Sartre to a plane of two person “secretes this Nothing as a gland "regions" of Being: “Being-in-itself" and secretes hormones” (Sartre, 1970; p.103). "Being-for-itself”. Briefly… ”Being-in-itself”, Sartre traces (certainly, not in an exhaustive according to Sartre, is “self-identical, way) the tradition of the description of undecomposed, dense, massive and compact.” consciousness as negative in European It is an absolute passivity; it is what it is, no philosophy. He quotes Spinoza's formula, “To more than that and any definitions are define means to deny”. Hegel admired this inapplicable to it. It is indiscernible, saying, and reformulated it in the judgment – undifferentiated, deprived of any qualitative “The Spirit is a negative”. Additionally earlier definiteness and self-sufficient; it does not in the Scholastics there exist a classical comprise any distinction between “this "and example of a bad artist who painted a lion, but “other”. It means that only the consciousness to the spectator, so it would be clear, the artist (“Being-for-itself”) introduces everything into signed: “This is a lion, but not a dog”. the world: discreteness, plurality, and Asserting that it is a lion, we thereby deny the causality, variability, movement, quantity, possibility for it to be a dog, a mouse, a fish, a quality, and also form, space, time (and, unicorn, a comet, etc... accordingly, mortal destiny), sense, meaning, Human activity, according to Sartre, good, harm, etc. Accordingly, all proceeds is absolutely unpremised: a person creates a from consciousness, the subject. And "Being- new existence every time, every moment he or in-itself" is absolutely indifferent to she “chooses him/her-self”. But then it turns consciousness, "Being-for-itself". Within the out that this instant creativity loses any person this indifference generates a double binding principle and dissipates in a set of feeling concerning the world: either a disgust separate acts which are not at all bound (as in the novel Nausea), or a painful envy (as between themselves. But then how is self- in the cycle of novels The Roads of Freedom), identification possible? Why is Jean-Paul but always this is the feeling of absolute Sartre nevertheless Sartre, instead of Mao- otherness and rejectedness. Zedong (whom he honored greatly), or not a What does this rejectedness mean for Parisian homeless (clochard)? Here, strangely consciousness and what does consciousness enough, Descartes comes, to the aid of Sartre. mean for Sartre? Consciousness, certainly, is Yes, Sartre struggled with Cartesian tradition not reduced to knowledge; it is a and denied the “thinking substance.” But in transphenomenal measurement of being of a the article “Cartesian freedom” (1957) (in the subject. "For-itself" literally means "not-in- preface to Descartes' collected works) Sartre itself", which means non-equality to itself, an makes an attempt of an existentialist orientation on something other and external to interpretation of Descartes. The starting point consciousness, e. g. the table, the chair, the of Descartes’ philosophy, which is the tree, the rat’s tail, Hegel’s Absolute Idea, lost methodical doubt, was interpreted by Sartre as youth, the actual infinity – everything that one an ability to say "NO", as the negating activity can think about. That the consciousness is of consciousness, as freedom (See Sartre, directed toward "something", toward an 1980, p.238). Descartes wrote: “The mind, "other", means that it is not that "something"; using freedom inherent in it, assumes that the consciousness is nothing. (The analogy there is none of things concerning which with the apofatic theology defining God as existence it should feel though the slightest “none of created things”, as "nothing", is doubt” (Descartes, 1952, p.185). And in rather transparent here. On a related note, in Sartre’s Being and Nothingness we read: Sartre’s novel Nausea it is possible to draw “Descartes following the Stoics has given a analogies with the Christian ascetics: the name to this possibility which human reality nausea in Sartre's anthropology seems to has to secrete a nothingness which isolates it – substitute the ascetics’ Christian disgust for it is freedom” (Sartre, 1970; pp.24-25). the all carnal and material. This is however a Therefore, the principle uniting activity of separate theme and we do not have the space human consciousness for Sartre was a to consider it here). permanence of negation, a freedom. The life of consciousness in Sartre's Sartre paraphrases Descartes: “I deny – description appears as a permanent negation hence I exist”. The liberation of a person was www.neuroquantology.com NeuroQuantology | December 2012 | Volume 10 | Issue 4| Page 670-675 672 Lifintseva TP., The Buddhist pill for Satre’s Nausea thought by Sartre as “the ability to self- every intentional object (whether it is a isolation.” “If "Being-in-itself" is self-identical physical thing, the city of Freiburg or “a and self-sufficient, than, for Sartre, “the thousandagon”) are equally ideal and belong consciousness (“Being-for itself”) represents a to consciousness as they are correlated with way not to be coincidence with itself, to escape intentional acts. Husserl understood identity” (Sartre, 1970; p.77). “Nothing is like a intentionality as a general property of hole of Being in the heart of Being”, – is consciousness – to be “consciousness about …” Sartre's well-known aphorism (Sartre, 1970; Sartre makes a certain inversion in p.617). relation to the Husserlian concept of The necessary condition for freedom is intentionality: in which it seems he comes choice, and choice is identical to back to the “intention” of the Stoics and the consciousness. Freedom is an ontological Scholastics, where the consciousness characteristic of a person’s being. Choosing corresponds with… no, not with an object, but one, we simultaneously
Recommended publications
  • Exploring Existential Angst, and the Self in Social Media Existentialism of Jean-Paul Sartre in Nausea
    Exploring Existential Angst, and the Self in Social Media Existentialism of Jean-Paul Sartre in Nausea By Kelly Mansfiled and Christine Onofrey Subjects: ELA, Philosophy, French Grade: 9-12 Introduction: Students will be introduced to Existentialism through discussion and excerpts from Jean-Paul Sartre’s novel, Nausea, which describes a certain vague feeling the main character, Roquentin, calls “nausea”. This feeling is basically a result of suspecting that there is a reality behind what we perceive as reality, an objective and subjective reality or Self. Realizing that upon piercing the veil of existence, there’s a subjective reality that we alone are responsible for creating - this creates a freedom, but also a burden and anxiety or nausea. That subjectivity (or the word “contingency” is used in Nausea) is the 1st principle of Existentialism. You may want to read some additional information to become more familiar with these ideas yourself. We recommend Sartre’s Existentialism is a Humanism for you, or even as extended reading for students. Roquentin’s revelations about reality and human consciousness lead him to his understanding that “existence precedes essence”. We exist first, and then do stuff and define who we are after the fact of existing.The implications of this are that we are all free to define our own essence. We exist, therefore we have anxiety about what to do with ourselves now that we exist. This overwhelming freedom is highly relatable to our students who are coping with their first waves of existential angst, as well as trying to construct their virtual Self/ Selves through multiplying social media and other online platforms.
    [Show full text]
  • "Pierre Loves Horranges": Sartre and Malabou on the Fantastic in Philosophy
    LABYRINTH Vol. 17, No. 2,Winter 2015 CONSTANCE L. MUI (New Orleans) JULIEN S. MURPHY (Portland, Maine) "Pierre Loves Horranges": Sartre and Malabou on the Fantastic in Philosophy Abstract In "Pierre Loves Horranges ", a little noticed essay on Sartre's existential psychoanalysis, emerging French philosopher Catherine Malabou offers a new reading of "Doing and Having", in Sartre's Being and Nothingness for her philosophy of the fantastic. We compare Sartre and Malabou on the fantastic, focusing on their analyses of quality, viscosity and ontological difference. We argue that Malabou's reinterpretation of Sartre's symbolic schema, which serves to make visible the change and exchange in the ontological difference, is valuable for a psychoanalysis of the future, one that comes after metaphysics and deconstruction. Key Words: Sartre, Malabou, ontology, psychoanalysis, plasticity, fantastic Interest in Sartre's existential psychoanalysis has declined in recent years with one notable exception, Catherine Malabou, a rising voice in recent continental philosophy.1 Sartre would no doubt be surprised at how few French women philosophers have garnered attention more than thirty-five years after his death. For instance, Ian James's recent collec- tion, The New French Philosophy, includes only one woman, Catherine Malabou, while other recent French philosophy volumes turn up no other names (Badiou 2012; Gutting 2013, and Mullarkey 2006). Certainly, after Sartre's longstanding encouragement of Beau- voir – she credits him for the idea of The Second Sex – he would pause to learn that the related question of women's subjectivity and autonomy would remain unsettled as Malabou shows in Changing Difference, her work on feminist philosophy and essentialism.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Should a Doctor Read Nausea? a Philosophical Analysis of Depression for Health- Science Majors Sophie Shogren St
    St. Catherine University SOPHIA Antonian Scholars Honors Program School of Humanities, Arts and Sciences 4-2015 Why Should a Doctor Read Nausea? A Philosophical Analysis of Depression for Health- Science Majors Sophie Shogren St. Catherine University Follow this and additional works at: https://sophia.stkate.edu/shas_honors Recommended Citation Shogren, Sophie, "Why Should a Doctor Read Nausea? A Philosophical Analysis of Depression for Health-Science Majors" (2015). Antonian Scholars Honors Program. 34. https://sophia.stkate.edu/shas_honors/34 This Senior Honors Project is brought to you for free and open access by the School of Humanities, Arts and Sciences at SOPHIA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Antonian Scholars Honors Program by an authorized administrator of SOPHIA. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Why Should a Doctor Read Nausea ? A Philosophical Analysis of Depression for Health-Science Majors Sophie Shogren St. Catherine University April 7, 2015 Shogren 2 Acknowledgements My sincerest thanks go to my project adviser, Anne Maloney, who initially encouraged me to pursue a philosophy minor. Her Philosophy of Religion course validated my wonderings about the universe and existence, while Philosophy and Women introduced me to inspiring feminist philosophers, and Philosophy in Literature showed me that literature helps us learn things about ourselves and was the driving factor behind my project. I am grateful to my project committee for their continued feedback and support throughout this process: Geri Chavis, who sparked my interest in bibliotherapy and the profound sense of fulfillment that novels and poetry can instill in us; Susan Hawthorne, whose scientific and philosophical advice helped me focus my project and keep it rooted in philosophy and literature; and Amy Hilden, whose Biomedical Ethics course got me thinking about the intersection of medicine and philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Nausea and the Adventures of the Narrative Self Ben Roth1
    How Sartre, Philosopher, Misreads Sartre, Novelist: Nausea and the Adventures of the Narrative Self Ben Roth1 Besides, art is fun and for fun, it has innumerable intentions and charms. Literature interests us on different levels in different fashions. It is full of tricks and magic and deliberate mystification. Literature entertains, it does many things, and philosophy does one thing. Iris Murdoch (1997, p. 4) If there is something comforting—religious, if you want—about paranoia, there is still also anti-paranoia, where nothing is connected to anything, a condition not many of us can bear for long. Thomas Pynchon, Gravity's Rainbow (p. 434) Both those who write in favor of and against the notion of the narrative self cite Sartre and his novel Nausea as exemplary opponents of it. Alasdair MacIntyre, a central proponent of the narrative self, writes: “Sartre makes Antoine Roquentin argue not just [...] that narrative is very different from life, but that to present human life in the form of a narrative is always to falsify it” (1984, p. 214). Galen Strawson, a critic of narrativity, writes that “Sartre sees the narrative, story-telling impulse as a defect, regrettable. [...] He thinks human Narrativity is essentially a matter of bad faith, of radical (and typically irremediable) inauthenticity” (2004, p. 435). I think that this type of interpretation of Nausea is blindered and bad and relies on an impoverished approach to reading fiction typical of philosophers: of taking one character at one moment as mouthpiece for both a novel as a whole and author behind it. Beginning as it does in description, the novel challenges these conceptual orders rather than taking one side or the other; it thus invites us to rethink the terrain of narrativity.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: an Existential Theory of Addiction
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1994 Love and Addiction: The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: An Existential Theory of Addiction Ross Channing Reed Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Reed, Ross Channing, "Love and Addiction: The Phenomenological Ontologies of Kierkegaard and Sartre: An Existential Theory of Addiction" (1994). Dissertations. 3461. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/3461 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1994 Ross Channing Reed LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO "LOVE" AND ADDICTION: THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL ONTOLOGIES OF KIERKEGAARD AND SARTRE AN EXISTENTIAL THEORY OF ADDICTION A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY BY ROSS CHANNING REED CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 1994 Copyright by Ross Channing Reed, 1994 All rights reserved. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to thank the following people and institutions for their support, encouragement, and prayer during the many years that led up to the production of this dissertation, as well as its actual writing: Texas A&M University Library, Millersville University Library, Franklin and Marshall College Library, Dr. John Ellsworth Winter, John Albert Cavin III, Christopher John Broniak, Richard J. Westley, John D.
    [Show full text]
  • Sartre, Existentialism and Panic Attacks Eric H
    The Linacre Quarterly Volume 59 | Number 2 Article 9 May 1992 Sartre, Existentialism and Panic Attacks Eric H. du Plessis Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended Citation du Plessis, Eric H. (1992) "Sartre, Existentialism and Panic Attacks," The Linacre Quarterly: Vol. 59: No. 2, Article 9. Available at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq/vol59/iss2/9 Sartre, Existentialism and Panic Attacks by Eric H. du Plessis, Ph.D. Associate Professor of French Literature Radford University, Radford VA Jean-Paul Sartre, the French Marxist philosopher, was the father of modern existentialism and one of the most influential thinkers of the twentieth century. His renowned phenomenological "revelation", as described in his first novel Nausea, was the starting point of his philosophical system: a series of distressing mental and physical experiences which led him to a new understanding of the nature of existence. Yet, ignored by philosophers and undetected by literary critics and biographers, Sartre's unique brand of perceptual tribulations would seem today to owe more to psychopathology than to philosophical enlightenment. Set against a background of early phobic reactions and recurring episodes of acute anxiety, the now famous "revelation" of human existence would appear to be an undiagnosed case of panic disorder. Born in 1905, Sartre was the unlikely cousin of Albert Schweitzer, the Christian physician and missionary who won the Nobel Peace Prize in 1952 for his work among the lepers of Africa. After years of brilliant studies, Sartre became the valedictorian of the class of 1929 at the Paris Ecole Normale Superieure, the most prestigious post-graduate program in philosophy within the French university system.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Speaking and Thinking
    THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Paul Murphy Higgins Washington, D.C. 2013 Speaking and Thinking about God in Rosenzweig and Heidegger Paul Murphy Higgins, Ph.D. Director: Holger Zaborowski, D.Phil. In the early twentieth century, many philosophers began to reject Kantian and Hegelian approaches to the question of God and the philosophy of religion. The challenge was then to formulate a new way of talking about God within philosophy without necessarily having to revert to pre-modern accounts. These thinkers saw the importance of retaining the insights of modernity while also taking into account the Romantic and post-Romantic critiques of modernism as a one- sided or overly rationalistic enterprise. This dissertation seeks to provide a comprehensive picture of the approaches of Franz Rosenzweig and Martin Heidegger to rethinking the question of how philosophy is to proceed, especially in light of religious phenomena. Placing Rosenzweig and Heidegger in dialogue helps to further our understanding of both figures, particularly insofar as Rosenzweig’s thought might be used as a corrective to possible shortcomings in the later Heidegger. Many scholars have argued that there is something problematic about Heidegger’s religious thought, but Rosenzweig has been almost completely overlooked as an important corrective resource. Both Rosenzweig’s comprehensive account of the basic phenomena of human existence and his grammatical method for formulating this account share many of Heidegger’s insights, yet surpass them insofar as Rosenzweig is able to address the topic in a more philosophically cogent manner.
    [Show full text]
  • Existentialist Narrators in the Novels of Albert Camus, Jean Paul Sartre, and Don Delillo Courtney Mullis Coastal Carolina University
    Coastal Carolina University CCU Digital Commons Honors College and Center for Interdisciplinary Honors Theses Studies Spring 5-15-2015 Unlikely Heroes in Despair: Existentialist Narrators in the Novels of Albert Camus, Jean Paul Sartre, and Don DeLillo Courtney Mullis Coastal Carolina University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.coastal.edu/honors-theses Part of the English Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Mullis, Courtney, "Unlikely Heroes in Despair: Existentialist Narrators in the Novels of Albert Camus, Jean Paul Sartre, and Don DeLillo" (2015). Honors Theses. 13. https://digitalcommons.coastal.edu/honors-theses/13 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors College and Center for Interdisciplinary Studies at CCU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of CCU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. '' Unlikely Heroes in Despair: Existentialist Narrators in the Novels of Albert Camus, Jean Paul Sartre, and Don DeLillo 2015 BY Courtney Mullis English Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts In the Honors Program at Coastal Carolina University May 2015 Mullis I Introduction Existentialism is a field of philosophy concerned with questions about existence, death God, and consciousness. It is "a doctrine that concentrates on the existence of the individual, who, being free and responsible, is held to be what he makes himself by the self-development of his essence through acts of the will" (OED Online). Writing by existentialist philosophers "often belongs more to literature than to philosophy" (Bigelow 173).
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger's Critique of Freedom
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eScholarship@BC Martin Heidegger's Critique of Freedom Author: Charles Robinson Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/655 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science MARTIN HEIDEGGER’S CRITIQUE OF FREEDOM a dissertation by CHARLES ROBINSON submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2009 © copyright by CHARLES ROBINSON 2009 Dissertation Abstract Title: Martin Heidegger’s Critique of Freedom Author: Charles Robinson Advisor: Professor Susan Shell Boston College Political Science Department This is a study of thought and politics of Martin Heidegger. It presents an examination of his understanding of freedom, principally as he expressed it in Being and Time, but also considers some of his subsequent essays and lectures, as well as his Rectorate Address. Ever since Heidegger’s public embrace of National Socialism, his defenders and critics have argued about the possible relation between his thinking and his infamous political commitments. While many of his critics have linked his commitments to an alleged lack of understanding of freedom, some of his scholarly defenders have sought to present interpretations of his concept of freedom at
    [Show full text]
  • The Transcendence of the Ego
    The Transcendence of the Ego First published in France in 1937 as a journal article, The Transcendence of the Ego was one of Jean-Paul Sartre’s earliest philosophical publications. When it appeared, Sartre was still largely unknown, working as a school teacher in provincial France and struggling to find a publisher for his most famous fictional work, Nausea. The Transcendence of the Ego is the outcome of Sartre’s intense engagement with the philosophy of Edmund Husserl, the founder of phenomenology. Here, as in many subsequent writings, Sartre embraces Husserl’s vision of phenomenology as the proper method for philosophy. But he argues that Husserl’s conception of the self as an inner entity, ‘behind’ conscious experience is mistaken and phenomenologically unfounded. The Transcendence of the Ego offers a brilliant diagnosis of where Husserl went wrong, and a radical alternative account of the self as a product of consciousness, situated in the world. This essay introduces many of the themes central to Sartre’s major work, Being and Nothingness: the nature of consciousness, the problem of self- knowledge, other minds, anguish. It demonstrates their presence and importance in Sartre’s thinking from the very outset of his career. This fresh translation makes this classic work available again to students of Sartre, phenomenology, existentialism, and twentieth century philosophy. It includes a thorough and illuminating introduction by Sarah Richmond, placing Sartre’s essay in its philosophical and historical context. Translated by Andrew Brown, University of Cambridge. Jean-Paul Sartre The Transcendence of the Ego A sketch for a phenomenological description Translated by Andrew Brown With an introduction by Sarah Richmond London and New York La transcendence de I’Ego © Libraire Philosophique J.Vrin, Paris, 1988 First published 2004 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxfordshire OX14 4RN Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005.
    [Show full text]
  • Jean-Paul Sartre Was Born in Paris in 1905
    INTRODUCTION Hayden Carruth Existentialism entered the American consciousness like an elephant entering a dark room: there was a good deal of breakage and the people inside naturally mistook the nature of the intrusion. What would it be? An engine of destruction perhaps, a tank left over from the war? After a while the lights were turned on and it was seen to be "only" an elephant; everyone laughed and said that a circus must be passing through town. But no, soon they found the elephant was here to stay; and then, looking closer, they saw that although he was indeed a newcomer, an odd-looking one at that, he was not a stranger: they had known him all along. This was in 1946 and 1947. And in no time at all Existentialism became a common term. No question of what it meant; it meant the life re-emerging after the war in the cafes of the Left Bank— disreputable young men in paint-smeared jeans, and their companions, those black-stockinged, makeupless girls who smoked too many cigarettes and engaged in who knows what follies besides. And their leader, apparently, was this fellow Sartre, who wrote books with loathsome titles like Nausea and The Flies. What nonsense, the wiseheads concluded. Perfectly safe to dismiss it as a fad, very likely a hoax. Meanwhile at centers of serious thought the texts of Existentialism, especially Sartre's, were being translated and studied, with a resulting profound shock to the American intellectual establish- ment. On one hand the Neo-Thomists and other moral philosophers were alarmed by Existentialism's disregard for traditional schemes of value; on the other the positivists and analytical philosophers were outraged by Existentialism's willingness to abandon rational categories and rely on nonmental processes of consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Nausea: an Expression of Sartre's Existential Philosophy
    ,_. __ . .....•.. - __ - -- .00. 0_.0 _.0__ 0_ This dissertation has been microfilmed exactly as received 70-9973 MALHOTRA, Ashok Kumar, 1940- NAUSEA: AN EXPRESSION OF SARTRE'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY. University of Hawaii, Ph.D., 1969 Philosophy University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan NAUSEA: AN EXPRESSION OF SARTREtS EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY A DISSER~TION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAII IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR mE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 1969 By Ashok Kumar Malhotra Dissertation Committee: Winfield E. Nagley, Chairman Harold E. McCarthy Kenneth K. Inada E1 iot Deutsch Henry S. Karie1 TABIE OF CON'lENTS ABSTRACT . .. ..... .. ...... i CHAPTER I. CONTROVERSY ABOUT NAUSEA •••••••••• 1 Nausea: A Philosophical Novel ••••• •• 3 Nausea: Not a Philosophical Novel ••• •• 10 Nausea: An Artistic Milestone in Twentieth century Literature ••••••• 13 Nausea: A Loose Type of Writing •••• •• 15 CHAPTER II• NAUSEA AS A WORK OF ART PART I. Summary •• .... .. 18 PART II. the Three Main Literary Devices Used A. the Use of Metaphor • •• • · • 24 B. The Use of Humor . •• • • · • 33 C. '!'he Use of Irony • . • • ·· • 36 PART III. '!'he Justification of the Use of Diary Form • .. • •• · • • 39 CHAP'lER III. EXISTENTIAL THEMES IN NAUSEA A. Existence ••••••••••••••• 45 B. Nausea.. ••••••••••••• •• 57 C. Freedom •••••••••••••• •• 61 D. Justification of Existence ••••• •• 65 CHAPTER IV. NAUSEA: AN EXPRESSION OF SARTRE'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY ••••••••••••••• •• 74 BIBLIOGRAPHY • • • ••• • • • • • • • • • •• • • • 116 NAUSEA: AN EXPRESSION OF SARTRE'S EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY By Ashok Kumar Malhotra A dissertation sUbmitted to the Graduate Division of the University of Hawaii in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy.
    [Show full text]