Are We Morally Equal by Nature?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Are We Morally Equal by Nature? Are We Morally Equal by Nature? Beth Lord explores Spinoza’s rejection of natural moral equality and its relevance for modern democracy Our understanding of democracy is bound up with the concept of moral equality: the belief that all people are of equal worth and are entitled to equal respect. The doctrine of moral equality is a cornerstone of democratic Enlightenment political philosophy. Jean-Jacques Rousseau famously claimed that all men are born equal and free, and Immanuel Kant argued that we ought to treat all human beings as ‘ends in themselves’—as free, rational beings equally worthy of dignity and respect. For these philosophers, we are morally equal just by virtue of being human, regardless of our physical, intellectual, and cultural differences. This principle of a basic, inalienable equality forms the core of much contemporary thinking about human rights, civil rights, and citizenship. Rousseau and Kant believed that moral equality derives from human rationality—the capacity to direct our own thinking, a capacity they take to be unique to humans and to be found equally in all of us. Today, we might be sceptical that there is any special ‘human nature’ that makes us different from other animals, particularly one that consists in ‘rationality’. So where does that leave moral equality? If we agreed that other kinds of beings, such as primates and dolphins, also had the capacity to reason, would that make them our moral equals, and entitle them to respect and rights? Benedict de Spinoza was a seventeenth-century philosopher who believed that there is nothing special about human beings that distinguishes us from the rest of nature. But that does not mean that there is any natural moral equality among different kinds of beings, or among humans. For him, people are born unequal and are not automatically entitled to equal respect. What’s interesting is that this view turns out to be compatible with the view that moral equality is intrinsic to democracy. Spinoza believed that all being is one, and this one being is equivalent to nature, alternatively called ‘God’. Spinoza’s God is not the theological God, but the infinite being of the universe: the single substance of which all particular things are modes. Modes lack independent existence, and depend on God for their being. Now, God is not only the physical substance of the universe, but its thinking substance too. Each mode partakes of God’s physical and thinking substance, such that each and every mode has both a body and a mind—though some modes (like rocks and geraniums) have much less complex minds than others (like chimpanzees and humans). A rock’s ‘mind’ is God’s idea of what is happening to the physical rock. A human mind is God’s idea of what is happening to that human’s body, but it has a far more complex capacity to reflect on and understand this idea. For Spinoza, this is merely a difference in degree. Whereas Rousseau and Kant claimed that humans are superior by virtue of having rational minds that transcend nature, Spinoza argued that everything has a mind and that everything is ‘part of nature’. Spinoza thus rejected the claim, implicit in the philosophies of Rousseau and Kant, that certain groups of humans (typically women and non-Europeans) are inferior by virtue of being more embedded in nature. For Spinoza, everyone and everything is just as much part of nature. This looks like the basis of an argument for moral equality, not only for all human beings, but for humans and non-humans alike. Yet Spinoza does not hold that all beings are equally valued. He stated that human beings do not owe respect to other animals, plants, or things, and argued that we may use animals for any purpose whatsoever. This is based on his view that beings have different degrees of ‘power’. A being’s power or ‘natural right’ is its capacity to persist in its being and to seek its advantage. Power is unequal between different kinds of beings, and those with greater power have a concomitantly greater right over those with less. Because a farmer is more powerful than a horse, she has the right to use the horse for transport. But a person who encounters a bear has no natural right not to be eaten by it. Unequal power, and our natural right over (some) other species, means we do not take individuals of other species to be of equal worth to us. What about moral equality among human beings? Here too, Spinoza argued that there are natural inequalities of power and right. In a ‘state of nature’—that mythical time prior to laws and moral codes, frequently imagined by early modern philosophers—more powerful human beings have a natural right to subjugate, use, and kill weaker ones, just as they would over weaker animals. The weak have no natural right to live free of harm, and no one has any obligation to protect anyone else. In a state governed by nature, then, people are born unequal, with unequal levels of power and right, and are perfectly entitled to use one another merely as means to ends. Inequalities of power and right extend into the democratic state. In Spinoza’s version of the social contract, each individual retains her natural power to seek her advantage. She does not give that power to a king, but pools it with the common power of the whole population. In the democratic state, individuals continue to seek their advantage according to their own natural right or power, but they are now subject to civil laws and enjoy greater security. While acting from one’s natural right is constrained in a democracy, one’s capacity for freedom is greatly enhanced. Freedom, for Spinoza, is acting autonomously; it rests on understanding what is truly to one’s advantage, and having the power to act on it. For Spinoza, members of a democracy are unequally free, because they are unequal in understanding and power. Those who are strong, fortunate, and/or enjoy favourable circumstances will come to understand and act upon what is truly to their advantage, both physically and mentally. They will become more rational and more free: better able to act autonomously, undetermined by external powers. People who are weak, unfortunate, and/or living in poor circumstances are less able to understand their true advantage and act accordingly. They have less rational understanding and are less able to act autonomously in the face of causal determination by other people and things. Spinoza did not make the disadvantaged responsible for their lack of power, though he thought that we all have the capacity to become more free; his Ethics provides a road-map for increasing our power and rational understanding. The more rational and free are, for him, better and more virtuous human beings. Spinoza’s goal was for each of us to be as virtuous, rational, and free as we possibly can be—not for us to be equal in these respects. This is why Spinoza rejected the doctrine of natural moral equality. He believed neither that people are equally rational by nature, nor that they should aim to be. Rationality develops and varies according to our circumstances. Those who have developed more rationality are ‘better’ people, and their interests and actions are more highly valued, because what is most valuable for human beings is rational human beings who understand and act according to the highest human good. The state should work towards increasing everyone’s rationality; it is good that some are more rational so they may guide others most effectively. Spinoza argued that inequalities in reason, freedom, and ‘value’ are as natural as inequalities in power, and the superiority of some people over others in these respects is advantageous for human flourishing. Equality does, nevertheless, have an important role to play in Spinoza’s version of democracy. Democratic citizens, unlike those in the state of nature, have equal civil right, an equal stake in governing and making the law. Equal civil right is not based on natural equality, since for Spinoza there is none. It rests, instead, on the social contract. Everyone—regardless of his degree of power or rationality—agrees to transfer his right from individual to collective ownership, and thereby gains an equal share of the resulting collective power. Each person’s equal share confers on him equal civil power and right, which sits on top of his unequal natural power and right. While a person’s ‘value’ is based on the extent of his rationality, equal civil right ensures everyone’s political and legal equality, as well as their equal responsibility to obey the law. Democracy makes every citizen’s relevant interests equal under the law, and renders each citizen equally worthy of justice. This means that every democratic citizen is treated as morally equal, regardless of whether they are morally equal by nature. Moral equality is therefore not a natural condition for Spinoza, but is ‘artificially’ imposed in the structure of civil law. It stems from a collective agreement that it is right that we think of one another as moral equals, rather than on core beliefs about human nature. At a time when we are less convinced that there is such a thing as human nature at all, this is a useful perspective to consider. It suggests that we can and should uphold moral equality within our communities, regardless of our views about human nature and what might constitute it. Beth Lord is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Aberdeen.
Recommended publications
  • Kant and Spinozism
    Kant and Spinozism Transcendental Idealism and Immanence from Jacobi to Deleuze Beth Lord Renewing Philosophy General Editor: Gary Banham Titles include: Lou Agosta EMPATHY IN THE CONTEXT OF PHILOSOPHY Karin de Boer ON HEGEL The Sway of the Negative Kyriaki Goudeli CHALLENGES TO GERMAN IDEALISM Schelling, Fichte and Kant Keekok Lee PHILOSOPHY AND REVOLUTIONS IN GENETICS Deep Science and Deep Technology Beth Lord KANT AND SPINOZISM Transcendental Idealism and Immanence from Jacobi to Deleuze Vincent W. Lloyd LAW AND TRANSCENDENCE On the Unfi nished Project of Gillian Rose Jill Marsden AFTER NIETZSCHE Jean-Paul Martinon ON FUTURITY Malabou, Nancy & Derrida Simon O’Sullivan ART ENCOUNTERS DELEUZE AND GUATTARI Thought Beyond Representation Peg Rawes SPACE, GEOMETRY AND AESTHETICS Through Kant and Towards Deleuze Celine Surprenant FREUD’S MASS PSYCHOLOGY Alberto Toscano THE THEATRE OF PRODUCTION Philosophy and Individuation Between Kant and Deleuze Vasiliki Tsakiri KIERKEGAARD Anxiety, Repetition and Contemporaneity Philip Walsh SKEPTICISM, MODERNITY AND CRITICAL THEORY Martin Weatherston HEIDEGGER’S INTERPRETATION OF KANT Categories, Imagination and Temporality Renewing Philosophy Series Standing Order ISBN 978–0–333–91928–6 (hardback) 978–0–230–20086–9 (paperback) (outside North America only) You can receive future titles in this series as they are published by placing a standing order. Please contact your bookseller or, in case of diffi culty, write to us at the address below with your name and address, the title of the series and the ISBN
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord
    EDINBURGH PHILOSOPHICAL GUIDES Spinoza's Ethics Beth Lord Spinoza’s Ethics Edinburgh Philosophical Guides Series Titles in the series include: Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Douglas Burnham with Harvey Young Derrida’s Of Grammatology Arthur Bradley Heidegger’s Being and Time William Large Plato’s Republic D. J. Sheppard Spinoza’s Ethics Beth Lord Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy Kurt Brandhorst Husserl’s The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Katrin Joost Nietzsche’s Thus Spoke Zarathustra Martin Jesinghausen and Douglas Burnham Spinoza’s Ethics An Edinburgh Philosophical Guide Beth Lord Edinburgh University Press © Beth Lord, 2010 Edinburgh University Press Ltd 22 George Square, Edinburgh www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Monotype Baskerville by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Antony Rowe, Chippenham and Eastbourne A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 3449 1 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 3450 7 (paperback) The right of Beth Lord to be identifi ed as author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Contents Series Editor’s Preface vi Acknowledgements vii List of Figures viii Introduction 1 1. A Guide to the Text 15 Part I: Being, Substance, God, Nature 15 Part II: Minds, Bodies, Experience and Knowledge 49 Part III: The Affects 83 Part IV: Virtue, Ethics and Politics 103 Part V: Freedom and Eternity 136 2. Study Aids 159 Glossary 159 Further Reading 167 Types of Question you will Encounter 168 Tips for Writing about Spinoza 169 Bibliography 173 Index 179 Series Editor’s Preface To us, the principle of this series of books is clear and simple: what readers new to philosophical classics need fi rst and foremost is help with reading these key texts.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and Museums: Ethics, Aesthetics and Ontology
    Royal Institute of Philosophy, Annual Conference 2013 Philosophy and Museums: Ethics, Aesthetics and Ontology University of Glasgow and the Burrell Collection, 24th-26th July, 2013 Launch Event: Tuesday 23rd July, 5.30 – 7.30 p.m. Hunterian Art Gallery. Open to the public. Welcome by the Deputy and Senior Vice Principal, Neal Juster. Lecture by Dr Mark O'Neill (Director of Policy and Research, Glasgow Life), 'Museums and their Paradoxes' with comments by Charles Taliaferro (Professor of Philosophy, St. Olaf College, Minnesota). The lecture will be followed by a civic wine reception in the Hunterian Art Gallery. No registration required. Wednesday 24th July (all talks to be held in the Bridie Library, 32 University Avenue, University of Glasgow) 9.00 – 9.30 Welcome 9.30 - 10.50 Garry Hagberg, Bard College, New York, ‘Word and Object’ Refreshments 11.00 - 12.20 Beth Lord, University of Aberdeen, ‘“A Sudden Surprise of the Soul”: Wonder in Museums and Early Modern Philosophy’ 12.20 - 1.00 Anna Bergqvist, Manchester Metropolitan University, ‘Framing Effects in Museums Narrative’ 1.00 - 1.45 Lunch 1.45 - 3.00 Constantine Sandis, Oxford Brookes, ‘Replicas and the Role of Museums’ 3.00 – 3.40 Andreas Pantazatos, Durham University, ‘The Normative Foundations of Stewardship and Trusteeship' Refreshments 4.00 – 5.15 Michael Levine, University of Western Australia, ‘Museums and the Nostalgic Self’ 5.30 – 6.30 Wine and Canapé reception at the Hunterian Museum. Welcome by Museum Director, Professor David Gaimster 6.45 Dinner. Thursday 25th July 9.30 - 11.00 Graham Oddie, University of Colorado at Boulder, ‘What do we see in Museums?’ (Art History Lecture Theatre, Hunterian Art Gallery, University of Glasgow).
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and Force: Dynamics, Natural Science and Transcendental Philosophy
    Kant and Force: Dynamics, Natural Science and Transcendental Philosophy Stephen HOWARD January 2017 Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the Centre for Research in Modern European Philosophy (CRMEP), Kingston University, for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy. Abstract This thesis presents an interpretation of Immanuel Kant’s theoretical philosophy in which the notion of ‘force’ (Kraft) is of central importance. My analysis encompasses the full span of Kant’s theoretical and natural-scientific writings, from the first publication to the drafts of an unfinished final work. With a close focus on Kant’s texts, I explicate their explicit references to force, providing a narrative of the philosophical role and significance of force in the various periods of the Kantian oeuvre. This represents an intervention into Kant scholarship that seeks to correct the marginal role accorded to ‘force’. The central problem that emerges through the thesis’ attention to force is: how to interpret the simultaneous separation and connection of physical and psychological forces in Kant’s mature, critical philosophy? Physical and psychological forces are strictly separated, and yet a common, ontological conception of force underpins these two domains. I show that this issue has its basis in a tradition of philosophical ‘dynamics’ stemming from Leibniz, which is examined in part one. The three parts of the thesis proceed chronologically through the Kantian oeuvre. Part one reconstructs the historical context of Leibnizian and Newtonian conceptions of force, and presents a narrative of the employment of force in Kant’s pre-critical writings, in their relation to the broad problematic of Leibniz’s dynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT Pittsburgh, Pa 15282 Return Service Requested 3 0 3 Duquesne Graduate Philosophy News Spring 2012 • Volume 5, Issue 1
    DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY 600 FORBES AVENUE PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT PITTSBURGH, PA 15282 RETURN SERVICE REQUESTED 3 0 3 DUQUESNE GRADUATE PHILOSOPHY NEWS Spring 2012 • Volume 5, Issue 1 MESSAGES FROM OUR DEAN AND CHAIR DEPARTMENT NEWS I have been the acting dean of the College this year, and in Daniel Selcer has March, was named dean. As such, I have been unable to been serving as interim teach, but have been able to learn a great deal about what is Director of Graduate going on in the College overall—especially the many good Studies, replacing Ron things. One of these is how many faculty, and students, Polansky while he serves outside of the department have interests in philosophy. as interim Chair. Dan has They come from political science, communications, history, recently spoken on early the natural sciences, and English—just to name a few areas. modern materialism at the One bit of news I can report is that the College is proposing to host the University of Pittsburgh, International Merleau-Ponty Circle in September 2013. We hope that this on the importance of history for philosophy at proposal will be successful. The College is also starting a Faculty Debate series. Slippery Rock University, on Spinoza’s account The first featured Dr. Miller and two other faculty members of individualism at the University of Guelph, and in a discussion entitled “Belief Today,” about religion in the on the idea of ‘operative science’ in Bacon and public sphere. - James Swindal Spinoza at Simon Fraser University. We are also pleased to announce that Dan was awarded the I look forward to our continuing as a very vibrant EWS ROM LUMNI 2012 McAnulty College and Graduate School N F A undergraduate and graduate Philosophy Department.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Fanaticism of Forces: Kant's Critique of Herder's Spinozism
    1 Against the fanaticism of forces: Kant’s critique of Herder’s Spinozism Beth Lord One of the many puzzling features of Kant’s Opus Postumum – the unpublished papers and fragments he was working on up to his death – is his frequent invocation of Spinoza. These references, found mostly in the very late sections of the text, are particularly striking given the content of its earlier sections.1 In ‘Übergang 1-14’ (labelled ‘The Ether Proofs’ in the English translation), written in 1799, Kant argues for a single dynamical continuum, the ether (also called caloric), that is the material of all appearances. Ether is posited a priori as the single object of perception whose moving forces provide the material for all bodies, and enable the subject to perceive things in space and time. This ‘universally distributed, all-penetrating world-material’ originally fills space and time with forces, making experience possible in general.2 Ether is therefore the material condition of experience, or ‘hypostatized’ space. The unity of experience demands that this single, space-filling continuum of forces be posited a priori to exist, not hypothetically, but actually. Kant had long held a dynamical theory of matter and had argued that matter, understood under the principles of natural science set out in the first Critique, is reducible to the interaction of fundamental forces.3 The concept of ether is, however, a significant development of that view. It is envisioned as the original, primary matter, which need not appeal to any ground outside itself for its being or subsistence. It contains the material for all possible experience, but is not an ideal sum-total of all possibilities.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza & the Arts
    benedictus de spinoza (1632—1677) Spinoza & the Arts: Passionate Reason Of all the things that are not under my control, what I value most is to enter into friend- ship with sincere lovers of truth. For I believe that such a loving relationship affords us a serenity surpassing any other boon in the whole wide world. — Spinoza* 2-day international symposium friday 04.10.2019 + saturday 05.10.2019 A child of the liberating power of the printing press, born into a new republic emerging wealthy from the 80 years war, Spinoza was an exemplary early modernist: irreverent, fiercely rational, politically daring. With: Moira Gatens (AU), Beth Lord (CA), Katja Diefenbach (DE), Mogens Laerke (DK), Andrea Sangiacomo (IT), Torkild Thanem (SE) moderated by Baruch Gottlieb (CA) Spinoza came to be the most prominent of the ‘free-thinkers’ a community of intellectuals which, inspired by Descartes, recently released from the oppressive theocracy of the Spanish Empire, felt entitled to subject the world anew to the full assault of human reason. The sciences, unhindered were to be released towards the full fruition of humanity's potentials. Many of us live in republics informed by the values of the young free-thinkers of The Netherlands, places where civil freedoms, of speech and of thought are promoted alongside freedom of religious belief and respect for the rule of law. The successes of the secular state in emancipating science and trade, have generated the contemporary globalised world of advanced technologies, yet paradoxically as the fruits of unhindered intellectually * From: Letter to William de Blyenbergh Jan.
    [Show full text]
  • AT the Post-Kantian Philosophy EDGES of THOUGHT
    Deleuze and AT THE Post-Kantian Philosophy EDGES OF THOUGHT Trial layout. Image increased to 77% in size and turned to 300 Cover image: ‘Beat’ by Jorinde Voigt, 2009. Cover design: Michael Chatfield ISBN 978–0–7486–9462–4 Edited by Craig Lundy and Daniela Voss At the Edges of Thought Deleuze and Post-Kantian Philosophy Edited by Craig Lundy and Daniela Voss © editorial matter and organisation Craig Lundy and Daniela Voss, 2015 © the chapters their several authors, 2015 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 10.5/13 pt Sabon by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 9462 4 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9464 8 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 0 7486 9463 1 (paperback) ISBN 978 0 7486 9465 5 (epub) The right of Craig Lundy and Daniela Voss to be identified as Editor of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). Contents Acknowledgements vii List of Contributors viii Introduction: Deleuze and Post-Kantian Thought – Method, Ideas and Aesthetics 1 Daniela Voss and Craig Lundy Part I: Deleuze, Kant and Maimon 1. Deleuze, Kant and the Transcendental Field 25 Daniel W. Smith 2. The Problematic Idea, Neo-Kantianism and Maimon’s Role in Deleuze’s Thought 44 Anne Sauvagnargues 3.
    [Show full text]
  • 'Disempowered by Nature': Spinoza on the Political Capabilities of Women Beth Lord in the Unfinished Final Chapter Of
    1 ‘Disempowered by nature’: Spinoza on the political capabilities of women Beth Lord In the unfinished final chapter of his unfinished Political Treatise we find Spinoza’s unfinished thought about the exclusion of women from the democratic polity. Spinoza says that women are deprived of citizenship in a democracy because they are ‘under the control of their husbands’ and, furthermore, ‘women do not naturally possess equal right with men’.1 The two paragraphs in which Spinoza discusses women’s exclusion from democratic citizenship have provoked both anger and puzzlement: anger because Spinoza’s reasoning here is so poor, and puzzlement because Spinoza’s position seems to run counter to what can be inferred from his Ethics about political community. The basis of human communities, as stated in the Ethics, is that we join together with others who ‘agree in nature’ with us. There is no indication there that this agreement of nature cannot include women as well as men; in fact, as we will see, there is evidence to the contrary. The best communities are formed on the basis of what we have in common, not in terms of our experiences, backgrounds, beliefs, or feelings, but in terms of what human beings essentially are and what we truly know. Our essence is to strive to preserve our being – to carry on being human beings – and to build the ‘common notions’ that are the basis of true knowledge of ourselves and nature. Common striving, common essence, and common notions bind us together to work for our mutual benefit regardless of our differences.2 At first, it looks as if Spinoza’s texts follow a familiar pattern: the ‘universal’ claim he makes for all human beings in one text is revealed in another to be restricted to men.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and Mereology Multiplicity, Structure and Composition
    Deleuze and mereology Multiplicity, structure and composition IOANNIS CHATZANTONIS Thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. JULY 2010 Στους γονείς μου, Νικήτα και Μαρίνα Contents ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ............................................................................................................. V DECLARATION ......................................................................................................................... VI ABSTRACT .............................................................................................................................. VII LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ...................................................................................................... VIII ΙNTRODUCTION ....................................................................................................................... 1 Aim and structure of investigation ............................................................................. 1 Prima facie objections ..................................................................................................... 2 1 ONE AND MANY IN PARMENIDES ................................................................................. 9 1.1 The poem ............................................................................................................... 9 The two ways of inquiry ............................................................................................... 9 The descriptive way of δόξα (B8.51-61; B9) .............................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Derrida Wordbook Maria-Daniella Dick and Julian Wolfreys
    Reference The Derrida Wordbook Maria-Daniella Dick and Julian Wolfreys March 2013 Hb 978 0 7486 2275 7 £120.00 512pp 234x156mm Alternative Formats: Eb (PDF) 978 0 7486 8037 5 £120.00 A glossary of words associated with Jacques Derrida accommodating the far-reaching implications of his work Description The Author Jacques Derrida (1930-2004) was undoubtedly one of the most infl uential thinkers Maria-Daniella Dick is presently of the twentieth century. He informed debate across many varied subjects and University Teacher in Literature since questions, from literature and philosophy to politics, ethics, religion, aesthetics, 1900 at the University of Glasgow. and culture. The Derrida Wordbook off ers scholars, students, and researchers an extensive Julian Wolfreys is Professor of Modern glossary, providing the reader with defi nitions of a wide range of terms employed Literature and Culture, with the by, or associated with, Derrida. Department of English and Drama, at Loughborough University. Table of Contents I) Words, Words, Words I Reason Readership Arrivant Ghosts Representation Aporia Hand Spectrality Researchers, teachers, graduate and Architectonic Haunting Story undergraduate students in courses Apartheid; Believing Hospitality Subjectile focusing on the work of Derrida within Book Hymen Telephone departments of English & Philosophy Betrayal Identity Trait as well as in departments of French Bêtise; Circle Iterability Unconditionality Studies, Politics, Sociology and related Circumcision Jealousy Undecidability Humanities subjects. Call Joyce Violence Corpus Kafka Virus Conjuration Khora Visitation DoorsDeath Knots Voice Democracy Knowledge Writing Deconstruction Literature Xenos Diff érance Love Yes Exhaustion Matter/Materialism II) Wordhoard Eyes Messianicity Appendices Face Metaphor 1. Bibliography of Selected Family Mimesis Publications Fold Name 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00261-6 - The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze Edited by Daniel W. Smith and Henry Somers-Hall Frontmatter More information The Cambridge Companion to DELEUZE Each volume of this series of companions to major phil­ osophers contains specially commissioned essays by an international team of scholars, together with a substantial bibliography, and will serve as a reference work for students and non­specialists. One aim of the series is to dispel the intimidation such readers feel when faced with the work of a difficult and challenging thinker. Gilles Deleuze (1925–95) was an influential and provocative twentieth­century thinker who developed and presented an alternative to the image of thought found in traditional phil­ osophy. This volume offers an extensive survey of Deleuze’s philosophy by some of his most influential interpreters. The essays give lucid accounts of the fundamental themes of his metaphysical work and its ethical and political implications. They clearly situate his thinking within the philosophical tradition, with detailed studies of his engagements with phe­ nomenology, post­Kantianism, and the sciences, and also his interventions in the arts. As well as offering new research on established areas of Deleuze scholarship, several essays address key themes that have not previously been given the attention they deserve in the English­speaking world. New readers will find this the most convenient, accessible guide to Deleuze currently available. Advanced students and specialists will find a conspectus of recent developments in the interpretation of Deleuze. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-00261-6 - The Cambridge Companion to Deleuze Edited by Daniel W.
    [Show full text]