The Understanding of Symbols and Their Role in the Ascent of the Soul to God in Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite and Nicholas of Cusa

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Understanding of Symbols and Their Role in the Ascent of the Soul to God in Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite and Nicholas of Cusa ROCZNIKI FILOZOFICZNE Tom LXIII, numer 2 – 2015 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.18290/rf.2015.63.2-7 TOMASZ STĘPIEŃ * THE UNDERSTANDING OF SYMBOLS AND THEIR ROLE IN THE ASCENT OF THE SOUL TO GOD IN PSEUDO-DIONYSIUS THE AREOPAGITE AND NICHOLAS OF CUSA INTRODUCTION Human nature is dual—corporeal and spiritual—so on every stage of the ascension to God the human body assists the efforts of the soul. The body may be perceived as a burden and an obstacle, though man cannot get rid of the body; he remains a corporeal being even at the highest ecstatic stage of deifica- tion. That remark shows the importance of symbols in following the mystical path, which in the history of mysticism was perceived as the point of connection between the corporeal and the spiritual world. Symbols are always material; they could be written or spoken, could be an image, sound, or even the entire rite, but the sensual side always points to a certain aspect of spiritual reality. It seems that late Neoplatonic philosophers were the first who clearly realized the importance of symbols to spiritual life. However, it happened due to the influence of the mystical Chaldean and Egyptian thought trans- ferred to philosophical investigation by the Chaldean oracles and Corpus hermeticum. The late Neoplatonic thought of Iamblichus and Eastern Neo- platonic schools used symbols and rituals as integral parts of philosophical investigation understood as having a mystical goal. The first part of this article attempts to show the main issues of this first encounter of symbolism with philosophical tradition, which is important because of the revival of the Neoplatonic tradition in the fifteenth century. Pseudo-Dionysius the Areo- Ks. dr hab. TOMASZ STĘPIEŃ, prof. UKSW – Uniwersytet Kardynała Stefana Wyszyńskiego w Warszawie; adres do korespondencji: ul. Dewajtis 5, 01-815 Warszawa; e-mail: t.stepien@ uksw.edu.pl 86 TOMASZ STĘPIEŃ pagite, who creatively transformed the teaching of his pagan predecessors, incorporated the ancient Neoplatonic tradition into Christian theology. An analysis of his idea of symbols and their role in Christian life also seems to be indispensable for a proper understanding of Cusanus’ teaching. The se- cond part of this article considers which of those aspects of the under- standing of symbols were preserved by Pseudo-Dionysius, and which were transformed or completely rejected. The third part will analyze the meaning of symbolism in the thought of Nicolas of Cusa. He was deeply influenced by Pseudo-Dionysius and he also places great stress on the role of symbols for the mystical path. The key pro- blem is once again to show what was changed and what parts of ancient tradition remained in his thought. Such an approach should also allow for deriving more general conclusions on the character of philosophical thought at the dawn of the modern era. SYMBOLS WORKING THROUGH THEMSELVES The recognition of symbols as an important part of philosophical life did not come with the first Neoplatonic philosopher — Plotinus. He knew well the Chaldean oracles, and probably Corpus Hermeticum, but he did not admit that the content of those writings played any role in philosophical investigation.1 The interesting case was that of Porphyry — Plotinus’ disciple who acknowledged the importance of Chaldean symbolism in the Philosophy of Oracles, but later radically changed his view in the well-known Letter to Anebo. One of the most important issues in criticizing Chaldean and Egyp- tian influences was the irrationality of symbols and rites.2 This letter, ad- dressed probably to a fictitious person, did not survive till the present, but we can reconstruct its main topics thanks to a reply written by Iamblichus — On the Mysteries. Porphyry pointed out that through symbols and rites called “theurgical,” a philosopher can have control over the powers of Gods and even command them. For him it was irrational to claim that man, who is a lesser being, has control over a higher one. Gods and demons are more perfect and thus men cannot control them. 1 See John DILLON, “Plotinus and the Chaldean Oracles,” in Platonism in the Late Antiquity, ed. Stephen Gersh and Charles Kannengiesser (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1992), 140. 2 Emma C. CLARKE, John M. DILLON, and Jackson P. HERSHBELL, “Introduction,” in IAMBLI- CHUS, De mysteriis (Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature, 2003), xxvi–xxxvii. THE UNDERSTANDING OF SYMBOLS AND THEIR ROLE... 87 The polemic between Porphyry and Iamblichus is well known, but in our case it reveals very important aspects of the understanding of symbols. In his answer Iamblichus formulated a point of view, which was hardly changed until the end of pagan Neoplatonic philosophy. He claimed that using the rites and symbols in a philosophical way of perfection was indeed irrational, but it was not due to being less rational. On the contrary, these rites should be conceived as exceeding the human capability of understanding. If they were under- standable they would only match the activity of man, but being beyond it, they are actions of the gods themselves. The mode and efficacy of rites was revealed in sacred writings, and thus they are only given to man who cannot understand them, but can perform them using the powers of gods. Thus sacred rites that help the initiate are true theurgy—the work of gods. For Iamblichus symbols are indispensable on the path of man to per- fection and unity with the One. His position on the matter means that the way of a philosopher is no longer merely an intellectual activity. Plotinus and his disciple Porphyry claimed that intellectual activity — philosophical investigation - leads man all the way to the point where he reaches the edge of the second hypostasis, that is Intellect (nous). The One itself is above Intellect, and thus the last part of the way must follow beyond the concepts of reason. Iamblichus disagrees with that, saying that philosophical life must be partially irrational from very beginning. Norman Russell expressed it well, writing about Iamblichus that: “Doing philosophy could no longer in itself raise the soul to the level of the divine because the divine essence transcends the essence of the human soul to such a degree. It is therefore necessary for the divine to descend by a ‘providential love’ before the lower reality can be perfected through participation in the characteristics of the higher. Iamblichus speaks of theurgy as taking place through wordless sym- bols beyond the act of thinking.”3 This disproportion between the soul and the divine reality is also stressed by Iamblichus. He also underlines that symbols are entities independent of the activity of a philosopher. They produce specific effects according to their kind by themselves, not thanks to the activity of man. Iamblichus explains this in the fragment De mysteriis: “Granting then that ignorance and decep- tion are faulty and impious, it does not follow on this that the offerings made to the gods and divine works (ta theia erga) are invalid, for it is not pure thought (ennoia) that unites theurgists to the gods. Indeed what, then, would 3 Norman RUSSELL, The Doctrine of Deification in the Greek Patristic Tradition (Oxford: Ox- ford University Press, 2004), 43. 88 TOMASZ STĘPIEŃ hinder those who are theoretical philosophers (theoretikos philosophountas) from enjoying a theurgic union with the gods? But the situation is not so: it is the accomplishment of acts not to be divulged and beyond all conception (hyper pasan noesin) and the power of unutterable symbols, understood solely by the gods, which establishes theurgic union. Hence, we do not bring about these things by intellection alone; for thus their efficacy would be intellectual, and dependent upon us. But neither assumption is true. For even then we are not engaged in intellection, the symbols themselves, by themselves, perform their appropriate work, and ineffable power of the gods, to whom these symbols relate, itself recognizes the proper images of itself, not through being aroused by our thought.”4 Symbols and the effects they cause are completely incomprehensible for the human intellect. Thanks to such a notion, Iamblichus can refute the claim that lesser beings direct and command the higher ones. The intellectual comprehension of man is not the cause of the operation of symbols. The theurgist can only prepare himself to accept the divine operation of symbols by having his soul in the best condition and maintaining ritual purity.5 So the role of man is rather limited to the technique of using them in the proper way. He has no control over what a symbol does to his soul, but thanks to the knowledge revealed in sacred writings he can discover the sympathy of a symbol with the specific deity. Sympathy of this kind shows what the effect of the symbol’s work on the soul could be. The sympathy of a symbol with divinity points to the cosmological perspective. The usage of symbols in the process of a return to the divine reality must also be proper and has to take place in the sequence, which mirrors how they were created by Demiurge. Those symbols are present in the universe because the gods seeded them during the process of the creation of the material universe. A god who plays the most important role in the creation of symbols is often Demiurge.6 He is not understood as the Platonic 4 IAMBLICHUS, De mysteriis, 96, 9-97, 7. 5 Iamblichus clarifies it in the next lines of this fragment, De mysteriis, 97,7-15: “For it is not in the nature of the things containing (synthemata) to be aroused by those contained in them, nor of things perfect by things imperfect, nor even of wholes by parts.
Recommended publications
  • Cusanus, on Learned Igorance-17Z8dxd
    On Learned Ignorance Harries 1 Karsten Harries Nicholas of Cusa On Learned Ignorance Seminar Notes Fall Semester 2015 Yale University Copyright Karsten Harries On Learned Ignorance Harries 2 Contents 1. Introduction 3 Book One 2. Learned Ignorance 17 3. The Coincidence of Opposites 30 4. The Threat of Pantheism 47 5. The Power of Mathematics 61 6. Naming God 76 Book Two 7. The Shape of the Universe 90 8. Matter and Becoming 105 9. The Condition of the Earth 118 Book Three 10. The Need for Christ 131 11. Death and Resurrection 146 12. Faith and Understanding 162 13. Death, Damnation, and the Church 176 On Learned Ignorance Harries 3 1. Introduction 1 Many philosophers today have become uneasy about what philosophy has become and where it has led us. Nietzsche and Heidegger, Derrida and Rorty are just a few names. Their uneasiness mirrors widespread concern about the shape of our modern culture. As more and more begin to suspect that the road on which we have been travelling may be a dead end, attempt are made to retrace steps taken; a search begins for missed turns and for those who may have misled us. Among these Descartes has long occupied a special place as the thinker whose understanding of proper method helped found modern philosophy, science, and indeed the shape of our technological world. It is thus to be expected that attempts to question modernity, to confront it, in order perhaps to take a step beyond it, should have often taken the form of attempts to confront Descartes or Cartesian rationality.
    [Show full text]
  • Nicholas of Cusa and Islam
    Nicholas of Cusa and Islam Ian Christopher Levy, Rita George-Tvrtković, and Donald F. Duclow - 9789004274761 Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 12:32:35PM via free access Studies in Medieval and Reformation Traditions Edited by Andrew Colin Gow (Edmonton, Alberta) In cooperation with Sylvia Brown (Edmonton, Alberta) Falk Eisermann (Berlin) Berndt Hamm (Erlangen) Johannes Heil (Heidelberg) Susan C. Karant-Nunn (Tucson, Arizona) Martin Kaufhold (Augsburg) Erik Kwakkel (Leiden) Jürgen Miethke (Heidelberg) Christopher Ocker (San Anselmo and Berkeley, California) Founding Editor Heiko A. Oberman † VOLUME 183 The titles published in this series are listed at brill.com/smrt Ian Christopher Levy, Rita George-Tvrtković, and Donald F. Duclow - 9789004274761 Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 12:32:35PM via free access Nicholas of Cusa and Islam Polemic and Dialogue in the Late Middle Ages Edited by Ian Christopher Levy Rita George-Tvrtković Donald F. Duclow LEIDEN | BOSTON Ian Christopher Levy, Rita George-Tvrtković, and Donald F. Duclow - 9789004274761 Downloaded from Brill.com10/01/2021 12:32:35PM via free access This is an open access title distributed under the terms of the CC BY-NC 4.0 license, which permits any non-commercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited. Further information and the complete license text can be found at https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ by-nc/4.0/ The terms of the CC license apply only to the original material. The use of material from other sources (indicated by a reference) such as diagrams, illustrations, photos and text samples may require further permission from the respective copyright holder.
    [Show full text]
  • Nicholas of Cusa and Modern Philosophy
    //FS2/CUP/3-PAGINATION/HRP/2-PROOFS/3B2/9780521846486C09.3D 173 [173–192] 2.5.2007 8:03AM 9 DERMOT MORAN Nicholas of Cusa and modern philosophy ‘‘Gatekeeper of the modern age’’ Nicholas of Cusa (Niklas Krebs, known as Cusanus, 1401–64), one of the most original and creative intellects of the fifteenth century,1 has been variously described as ‘‘the last great philosopher of the dying Middle Ages’’ (Alexandre Koyre´), as a ‘‘transition-thinker’’ between the medieval and modern worlds (Frederick Copleston),2 and as the ‘‘gatekeeper of the modern age’’ (Rudolf Haubst).3 He is a lone figure with no real successor although he had some influence on Copernicus, Kepler, Bruno, and, tangen- tially, on Descartes. The German Idealists showed some interest in Nicholas of Cusa but the real revival of his thought was stimulated by the neo-Kantian philosopher Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945) who called him ‘‘the first modern thinker’’ and by the existentialist Karl Jaspers.4 Cassirer compared him to Kant for his view that objects have to be understood in terms of the categories of our own thought.5 Other scholars, notably Alexandre Koyre´,6 Hans-Georg Gadamer7 Hans Blumenberg,8 Werner Beierwaltes,9 and Karsten Harries,10 all see him in a certain way as a harbinger of modernity.11 Yet his outlook is essentially conservative, aiming, as Hans Blumenberg has recognized, to maintain the medieval synthesis.12 Cusanus was a humanist scholar, Church reformer – his De concordantia catholica (On Catholic Concord, 1434) included proposals for the reform of Church and state – papal diplomat, and Catholic cardinal.
    [Show full text]
  • Pál Bolberitz: the Beginnings of Hungarian Philosophy
    A SZENT IS1V AN TIJDOMANYOS AKADEMIA SZEKFOGLALO ELOADASAI Uj Folyam. 2/2. szam Szerkeszti: STIRLING JANos OESSH fot.itkar PAL BOLBERITZ THE BEGINNINGS OF HUNGARIAN PHILOSOPHY (THE RECEPTION OF NICHOLAS OF CUSA IN THE WORK ,DE HOMINE" BY PETER CS6KAS LASKOI) BUDAPEST 2004 A SZENT IS1V AN TIJDOMANYOS AKADEMIA SZEKFOGLALO ELOADASAI Uj Folyam. 2/2. szam Szerkeszti: STIRLING JANos OESSH fot.itkar PAL BOLBERITZ THE BEGINNINGS OF HUNGARIAN PHILOSOPHY (THE RECEPTION OF NICHOLAS OF CUSA IN THE WORK ,DE HOMINE" BY PETER CS6KAS LASKOI) Magyarrryelven elhangzott a Matr~ar Tu:imdnyos A lwitfmia Felol1.J:lfJ3 tern11i1m 2003. novemher 25-in BUDAPEST 2004 Minden jog fenntartva, beleertve a btirminemu eljtirtissal val6 sokszorositds jogdt is © BOLBERITZ PAL 2004 KESZULT A SZENT ISTV ANTARSULAT, AZ APOSTOLI SZENTSZEK KONYVKIAOOJA NYOMDAJABAN. IGAZGATO: FARKAS OLIVER OESSH BUDAPEST, V. KOSSUTH LAJOS U. 1. PAL BOLBERITZ THE BEGINNINGS OF HUNGARIAN PHILOSOPHY (THE RECEPTION OF NICHOLAS OF CUSA IN THE WORK DE HOMINE BY PETER Cs6KAS LASK6I) The present study does not intend to get involved in the academic dispute flaring up from time to time to discuss whether there has ever been Hungarian philosophy or not. According to our view, Hungarian philosophy did, does and, hopefully, will exist, for it has its own proper­ ties. As it is well known, philosophy is the science inves­ tigating the ultimate principles and causes. It is not un­ common for the Hungarian spirit to examine the ultimate questions either. As expressed by the Latin phrases: pri­ mum vivere,
    [Show full text]
  • NICHOLAS of CUSA's DEBATE with JOHN WENCK a Translation and an Appraisal of De Ignota Litteratura and Apologia Doctae Ignorantiae
    NICHOLAS OF CUSA'S DEBATE WITH JOHN WENCK A Translation and an Appraisal of De Ignota Litteratura and Apologia Doctae Ignorantiae by JASPER HOPKINS THE ARTHUR J. BANNING PRESS MINNEAPOLIS The English translation of Apologia Doctae Ignorantiae is made from Nicolai de Cusa Opera Omnia, Vol. II, edited by Raymond Klibansky (Leipzig: F. Meiner, 1932). Third edition, 1988 (First edition, 1981) Copyright © 1981 by The Arthur J. Banning Press, Minneapolis, Min- nesota 55402. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 80-82908 ISBN 0-938060-40-6 458 1 A DEFENSE OF LEARNED IGNORANCE FROM ONE DISCIPLE TO ANOTHER (Apologia Doctae Ignorantiae Discipuli ad Discipulum) by NICHOLAS OF CUSA Our common teacher, master Nicholas of Cusa, now added to the Col- lege of Cardinals, once told me how well you understand the coinci- dences which he disclosed to us in the books of Learned Ignorance (presented to the Apostolic Legate)1 and in many of his other works. [He spoke of] your ardent wish to gather together everything which here and there flows from him regarding these matters. [He also re- ported] that you do not allow any of the learned men to pass by you without talking with them about this approach. [And he mentioned] that you have induced many who had despised this study to break for a short while with their long-standing habit of laboring with the Aris- totelian tradition and to give themselves over to these considerations, in the faith that something important lies hidden therein—[to give themselves] to the extent that with an inward relish they become more deeply attracted and come to realize that this approach differs from others as much as sight differs from hearing.
    [Show full text]
  • Uniformity with God's Will
    Uniformity with God©s Will Author(s): Liguori, St. Alphonsus de (1696-1787) Publisher: Grand Rapids, MI: Christian Classics Ethereal Library Description: Written in 1755, Uniformity with God©s Will is a wonderful little treatise on the true love of God. Saint Alphonsus de Liguori writes to encourage believers to unify their wills with that of God©s, so that they may love God perfectly: "the more one unites his will with the divine will, the greater will be his love of God." To choose otherwise--i.e. to choose not to unify one©s will with God©s--is "a kind of idolatry." These seven short chapters, not simply prone to abstract speculation, ex- plore concretely how to make one©s own will uniform with God©s through the hardships of this life. Further, the book discusses the fruit of such a union with God©s will: happiness. De Liguori concludes by noting how, in all things, Christians must remain steadfast in their union with God©s will. For in so doing, God will "press us to his heart." Challenging and encouraging, Uniformity with God©s Will has the power to remind us of what true love of God really is. Tim Perrine CCEL Staff Writer Subjects: Christian Denominations Roman Catholic Church Biography and portraits Individual Saints, A-Z i Contents Title Page 1 Preface 2 1. Excellence of this Virtue. 3 2. Uniformity in all Things. 6 3. Happiness deriving from perfect Uniformity. 8 4. God wills our Good. 11 5. Special Practices of Uniformity. 14 6. Spiritual Desolation.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Francis of Assisi Library Author Title Section Call#1 Category: SPIRITUALITY
    St. Francis of Assisi Library Author Title Section Call#1 Category: SPIRITUALITY Allen, Paul Francis of Assisi's Canticle of the Creatures ALLE 12 Arminjon, Charles End of the Present World ARMI 16 Bacovcin, Helen Way of a Pilgrim and the Pilgrim Continues His Way BACO 09 Baker, Denise Showings of Julian of Norwich BAKE 09 Barry , Patrick Saint Benedict's Rule BARR 07 Barry, William A. Finding God in All Things BARR 08 Bodo, Murray Enter Assisi BODO 15 Bonhoeffer, Dietrich Cost of Discipleship, The BONH 08 Brady, Ignatius C., Translator Writings of Saint Francis of Assisi BRAD 10 Cantalamessa, Raniero Sober Intoxication of the Spirit CANT 07 Carrigan, Henry LIttle Talks with God CARR 16 Casey, Michael Guide to Living in the Truth, A CASE 09 Casey, Michael Strangers to the City CASE 07 Caussade, Jean-Pierre Joy of Full Surrender, The CAUS 16 Caussade, Jean-Pierre Abandonment to Divine Providence CAUS 12 Chittister, Joan Rule of Benedict, The CHIT 12 Chrysostom, John Love Chapter, The CHRY 16 Collier, Winn Let God COLL 15 Colledge, Edmund (Translator) Julian of Norwich Showings COLL 08 Corrigan, Felicitas, O.S.B. Saints Humanly Speaking, The CORR 07 Cousins, Ewert Bonaventure COUS 07 Deming, Lynne Feminine Mystic, The DEMI 14 De Montfort, St. Louis Mary God Alone DEMO 07 De Sales, St Francis Introduction to the Devout Life DESA 11 De Sales, St Francis Thy Will Be Done DESA 98 de Waal, Esther Seeking God DEWA 04 Durka, Gloria Praying with Hildegard of Bingen DURK 10 Evans, G. R., Translator & Bernard of Clairvaux EVAN 10 Fagin,Foreword Gerald Putting on the Heart of Christ FAGI 12 Fenelon, Francois Talking With God FENE 16 Hindsley, Leonard P.
    [Show full text]
  • Renewing an Ancient Christain Prayer Form: 'Centring Prayer'
    61 DIVINE CALL AND HUMAN RESPONSE Renewing an ancient christian prayer form: 'Centring Prayer' ONASTICISM was beginning to flourish in fifth-century Gaul, and in M response to an expressed need, St John Cassian produced two sets or collections of writings. The first, the Institutes, recounted the practices of the monks of Egypt and adapted them for use in the colder, western regions. In his second collection, he included what he considered the most significant teachings he had received in the course of his long pilgrimages among the monks of Egypt. These he presented in the form of Conferences given by various Fathers. In Abba Isaac's second conference we find the first written expression in the west of that tradition of which Centring Prayer is a contemporary presentation. The whole of Abba Isaac's magnificent Conference should be read. But let us here listen to just a few of the words of this wise old man, most directly related to our present concern: I think it will be easy to bring you to the heart of true prayer... I must give you a formula for contemplation. The formula was given us by a few of the older fathers who remained. They communicated it 0nly to a very few who were athirst for the true way. To maintain an unceasing recollection of God, this formula must be ever before you. The formula is this: 'O God, come to my assistance; O Lord, make haste to help me'. The mind should go on grasping this formula until it can cast away the wealth and multiplicity of other thoughts, and restrict itself to the poverty of this single word.
    [Show full text]
  • Cusa Faith/Reason-Engl
    PROLEGOMENA TO NICHOLAS OF CUSA’S CONCEPTION OF THE RELATIONSHIP OF FAITH TO REASON by JASPER HOPKINS © 1996 PROLEGOMENA TO NICHOLAS OF CUSA’S CONCEPTION OF THE RELATIONSHIP OF FAITH TO REASON “Ist der Weg des spekulativen Denkens, wenn dieses nicht eine ermüdende Spielerei wird, immer von einem Glauben her beschritten, von einem Glauben sei es der alten griechischen Fröm- migkeiten, sei es der asiatischen Glaubensweisen, sei es der christlichen?” —Karl Jaspers1 I Is there any such thing as the Cusan view of the relationship between faith and reason? That is, does Nicholas present us with clear concepts of fides and ratio and with a unique and consistent doctrine regarding their interconnection? If he does not, then the task before us is surely an impossible one: viz., the task of find- ing, describing, and setting in perspective a doctrine that never at all existed. For even with spectacles made of beryl stone or through the looking glass of Lewis Car- roll, we could not descry the totally nonexistent. Four lines of argument purport to show that the task before us is funda- mentally impossible. 1. First of all, it may be argued (a) that Nicholas of Cusa can have a coher- ent doctrine of faith and reason only if he has a generally coherent theory of knowl- edge and (b) that since his theory of knowledge is generally incoherent, so too must be the aforesaid doctrine, which is an intrinsic part of the theory of knowledge. Let us grant—for the sake of the argument—the disputable logic of this reasoning, and let us focus on the question of whether Nicholas does or does not have a viable gen- eral theory of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Non-Duality in Śaṅkara and Cusanus
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 12, No. 1 (2021): 98-110 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 / www.comparativephilosophy.org https://doi.org/10.31979/2151-6014(2021).120109 THE CONCEPT OF NON-DUALITY IN ŚAṄKARA AND CUSANUS JEROME KLOTZ ABSTRACT: When comparing diverse philosophical traditions, it becomes necessary to establish a common point of departure. This paper offers a comparative analysis of Advaita Vedānta Hinduism and esoteric Christianity, as represented by the two highly celebrated figures of Śaṅkara and Nicholas Cusanus, respectively. The common point of departure on which I base this comparison is the concept of “non-duality”—a concept that is fitting for at least two reasons. First, it is general enough to encompass both traditions, pervading the work of each figure, and thus allowing for a kind of “shared language.” Second, it is specific enough to identify a set of core and well-defined principles amenable to systematic study, chief among which are the notions of (1) the “Absolute” as an infinite unity that transcends all determinations (“no-thing”) and exceeds all oppositions (“not-other”), and (2) the world as an ontologically ambiguous “reflection” that simultaneously hides and manifests its meta- ontological Principle. In drawing these connections, I hope to show how the concept of non- duality provides the possibility for a mutual understanding among diverse traditions at the philosophical level. Keywords: Advaita Vedānta, metaphysics, mysticism, Nicholas Cusanus, non-duality, Śaṅkara 1. INTRODUCTION The concept of “non-duality” is not the exclusive possession of any one philosophical system. On the contrary, it can be found—mutatis mutandis—within religio- philosophical traditions the world over: from Philosophical Daoism, Mahāyāna Buddhism, and Advaita Vedānta Hinduism in the East, to Kabbalistic Judaism, esoteric Christianity, and mystical Islam in the West.
    [Show full text]
  • A-Z Entries List
    Alphabetical List of Entries Abelard, Peter Attributes, Divine Abortion Augustine of Hippo Action Augustinianism Adam Authority Adoptionism Agape Balthasar, Hans Urs von Agnosticism Bañezianism-Molinism-Baianism Albert the Great Baptism Alexandria, School of Baptists Alphonsus Liguori Barth, Karl Ambrose of Milan Basel-Ferrara-Florence, Council of Anabaptists Basil (The Great) of Caesarea Analogy Beatitude Angels Beauty Anglicanism Beguines Anhypostasy Being Animals Bellarmine, Robert Anointing of the Sick Bernard of Clairvaux Anselm of Canterbury Bérulle, Pierre de Anthropology Bible Anthropomorphism Biblical Theology Antinomianism Bishop Antinomy Blessing Antioch, School of Blondel, Maurice Apocalyptic Literature Boethius Apocatastasis Bonaventure Apocrypha Bonhoeffer, Dietrich Apollinarianism Book Apologists Bucer, Martin Apostle Bultmann, Rudolf Apostolic Fathers Apostolic Succession Calvin, John Appropriation Calvinism Architecture Canon Law Arianism Canon of Scriptures Aristotelianism, Christian Carmel Arminianism Casuistry Asceticism Catechesis Aseitas Catharism Athanasius of Alexandria Catholicism Atheism Chalcedon, Council of xiii Alphabetical List of Entries Character Diphysitism Charisma Docetism Chartres, School of Doctor of the Church Childhood, Spiritual Dogma Choice Dogmatic Theology Christ/Christology Donatism Christ’s Consciousness Duns Scotus, John Chrysostom, John Church Ecclesiastical Discipline Church and State Ecclesiology Circumincession Ecology City Ecumenism Cleric Edwards, Jonathan Collegiality Enlightenment
    [Show full text]
  • The Way of Perfection St
    The Way of Per fe c t i o n by St.Teresa of Avila The Way of Perfection St. Teresa of Avila Table of Contents About This Book. p. ii Title Page. p. 1 The Way of Perfection. p. 2 Presentation. p. 2 Contents. p. 2 Principal abbreviations. p. 5 Introduction. p. 5 Translator©s note. p. 10 General argument, protestations and prologue. p. 13 Protestations. p. 14 Prologue. p. 14 Of the reason which moved me to found this convent in such strict observance. p. 15 Treats of how the necessities of the body should be disregarded and of the good that comes from poverty. p. 17 Continues the subject begun in the first chapter and persuades the sisters to busy themselves constantly in beseeching God to help those who work for the Church. Ends with an exclamatory prayer. p. 19 Exhorts the nuns to keep their Rule and names three things which are important for the spiritual life. Describes the first of these three things, which is love of one©s neighbour, and speaks of the harm which can be done by individual friendships. p. 22 Appendix to chapter 4. p. 26 Continues speaking of confessors. Explains why it is important that they should be learned men. p. 27 Returns to the subject of perfect love, already begun. p. 29 Treats of the same subject of spiritual love and gives certain counsels for gaining it. p. 31 Treats of the great benefit of self-detachment, both interior and exterior, from all things created. p. 35 Treats of the great blessing that shunning their relatives brings to those who have left the world and shows how by doing so they will find truer friends.
    [Show full text]