1. MORAL EXEMPLARISM BETWEEN THEORY and ANTI-THEORY The

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1. MORAL EXEMPLARISM BETWEEN THEORY and ANTI-THEORY The 105 Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XX, 2018, 2, pp. 105-122 ISSN: 1825-5167 Sapienza Università di Roma Dipartimento di Filosofia [email protected] References to moral exemplars run deep into the history of philosophy, as we find them featured in rather disparate context and approaches which span from virtue ethics to moral perfectionism, from existentialism to moral particularism. In the varied and growing contemporary literature on moral exemplarism, we find a number of options that can be brought down to the two rather broad yet distinctive categories of theoretical and anti- theoretical approaches. In the paper, I showcase and contrast these two varieties by taking the views of Zagzebski and Rorty as representative of, respectively, the reference to exemplars as most perfect beings to aspire to and get guidance from, and the use of them as next yet foreign beings to experiment with and get provocation from. Finally, I will draw some consequences for a conception of moral education hinged on unsettlement and transformation rather than on imitation and reproduction. Moral Theory; Moral Education; Spiritual Exercises; Linda Zagzebski; Richard Rorty. 1. MORAL EXEMPLARISM BETWEEN THEORY AND ANTI-THEORY The contemporary orthodoxy in moral philosophy has variously committed to a version of isolationism, bracketing our first order moral views from their philosophical account: that is, the tools and strategies to investigate the most general shape of the moral life should not be influenced by one particular picture of it on pain of jeopardizing the impartiality of our meta-ethical and normative theories alike, hence turning moral reflection into moral preaching of sorts. This theoretical model has been attacked from a number of corners 106 SARIN MARCHETTI by the so-called “anti-theorists”1, who argued against what they take to be the impossible and eventually pernicious task of peeling off one‟s substantive conceptions of the good life from one‟s philosophical accounts of it – a maneuver which, according to this heterodox approach, often conceals precisely those very foundationalist agendas and ambitions moral theorists themselves wove against the moralizers2. With its stress on the importance of exemplar beings in both shaping one‟s conduct and revising one‟s views about how to live up to ethical standards, moral exemplarism sits rather well with, and can be read as belonging to, this feast of anti-theoretical approaches critical of mainstream moral theorizing, or so I will argue. In fact, according to this approach, moral thinking and acting move from the confrontation with embodied excellent human existences that might or might not inspire us and enlighten our conducts in the particular situation we find ourselves in, rather than with allegedly neutral templates which we should accept or reject independently from the standpoint we occupy – templates that nevertheless represent but one precise picture of the moral life as pumped by our allegedly pre-philosophical moral intuitions3. Furthermore, the very modality and goals of moral inquiry are different: while moral theorists seek moral justification and prescriptions via impersonal argumentations, exemplarists seek moral insight and transformation via personal confrontation. While acknowledging the force and opportunity of an exemplarist approach to ethics, I distinguish two main varieties of it: a broadly theoretical one – most articulately and effectively defended by Linda Zagzebski – based on the centrality of the excellence of the exemplar‟s virtues, and a broadly anti- theoretical one based on the centrality of the relationship we establish with the exemplar – which I find congenially articulated in the later work of Richard Rorty. While the former hinges on our capacity to recognize and possibly 1 For the manifesto and classical statement of anti-theory, see Williams 1985, and Clarke and Simpson 1989; for a criticism, see Louden 1992; for a recent, critical assessment of the whole debate, see Fotion 2014. 2 By moralism I here mean both the promotion of one precise moral option in disguise – to be distinguished from the inscription of moral significance into moral reflection itself – and the extension of moral considerations by means of philosophical imposition beyond the boundaries of what is ordinary felt as pertaining to the range of the moral – to be distinguished from the open-endedness of the moral. The multi-faced and wide-ranging topic of moralism has been explored in several of its nuances by Taylor 2012. 3 The battle over moral intuitions is also quite lively, and has been recently reinvigorated by the clash between experimental philosophers and their critics. For a survey and proposal congenial to the perspective advanced here, see Koopman 2012. On these themes, see also Lecaldano 2009. 107 Two Varieties of Moral Exemplarism duplicate the excellent life we read in the words and deeds of the exemplar, driven by the admiration for and aspiration to their lives, the latter hinges on our willingness to be reshaped by our real or imaginary conversations and engagement with such lives, driven by self-scrutiny and self-knowledge. While the former has among its key quests those of defining what exemplars are, how to individuate them and imitate them, the latter is interested in the relationship we establish with them and in how we are possibly displaced and transformed by them. I claim that it is exemplarism of the latter breed that we should endorse if we don't want to ultimately fall back to the prescriptivist, theoretical conception of moral thinking that exemplarism should be critical of. That is to say, it is only when exemplarism is made anti-theoretical that we can prevent it from becoming yet one more arrow in the moralist‟s quiver, thus jeopardizing its fierce opposition to abstractedness, on the one hand, and over-commitment, on the other. What I aim at disclosing is a space for moral reflection which is both morally committed (in the sense of not being morally neutral) and yet not morally charged (that is moralistically driven), where exemplars play the role of those very (concrete as against rarified) devices for moral education through which we explore and possibly transform our understanding and practice of our moral life without being given one to be inculcated from without through strokes of prescriptions. After sketching the blueprint of Zagzebski‟s theoretical model (§2), I shall voice a number of concerns about some of its metaphilosophical and ethical implications (§3), and eventually turn to an different, anti-theoretical rendering of exemplarism as inspired by a line of reasoning drawn from Rorty (§4). Some very general conclusions about the nature and scope of philosophical ethics and some gestures towards the future path to travel will round things up (§5). 2. EXEMPLARS AS EXTRAORDINARY BEINGS In a number of recent writings (most notably, 2010 and 2017), Linda Zagzebski sketched a very sophisticated and skillfully knitted up theory of moral exemplarity through which she aims to reclaim the centrality of extraordinary (virtuous) beings to moral judgment and moral education. Her goals are not so much descriptive and suggestive, but rather prescriptive and foundational in spirit: by offering a categorization and evaluation of the various directions in which exceptionality can be reached and most importantly admired and longed for, she sketches a meta-ethics as well as a 108 SARIN MARCHETTI normative theory of moral value and conduct. Moral exemplars do show what goodness is as well as urge us to realize it. This combo is presented under the auspices of a “radical kind of virtue theory [she] call[s] „exemplarism‟, which is foundational in structure but which is grounded in exemplars of moral goodness, direct reference to which anchors all the moral concepts in the theory” (2010, 41). Zagzebski‟s foundationalism is then grounded on the direct reference to exemplars and the normative role of the universal emotion of admiration. According to this scheme, narratives and tales are those very features of our ordinary moral practices through which we reinforce our confidence in referring to the right kind of people, and such identification is one pre-theoretical aspect of our moral practices that theory must explain and account for. Narratives and tales link the a priori element of moral theory (that is, foundationalism) to the practical aspect of our moral lives though (that is, exemplarism), as Zagzebski remarks at several stages, the resulting theory amounts to no manual for good deeds but rather to something closer to a moral map (2010, 43ss) which is up to the various individual to interpret and put to use. Exemplars possess a distinctive deep psychological structure that makes them maximally good or excellent, and that we can and should carefully observe, even if this natural or acquired endowment might well change among exemplars and through time. We educate the normative emotion of admiration through reflection and further experience, and in so doing we cherish and emulate those extraordinary individuals who handle us maps to get around and live by. Now, Zagzebski notices how admiration and desire are two distinct aspects of goodness, as we admire things we don‟t desire, and desire things we don‟t admire. As against Aristotle, admiration (which opposite is contempt) is depicted as primary to desirability: according to Zagzebski‟s exemplarist moral psychology, key to the moral life is the will (and often obligation) to model ourselves on whom we want to be like. Admiration is a motivating emotion that tracks how things are in the world, and, in this sense, “admirable” works as a thick concept, with the descriptive part as inseparable from the evaluative one. Zagzebski writes: The test of whether someone is admirable is always that we admire her on reflection and continue to admire her after we obtain more information about her and reflect on our emotion and the emotions of those we trust.
Recommended publications
  • Failings of Strong Moral Particularism
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections Critical Reflections 2015 Mar 28th, 10:30 AM - 11:00 AM Failings of Strong Moral Particularism Timothy Grainger Mr Carleton University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/essaysofsignificance Part of the Philosophy Commons Grainger, Timothy Mr, "Failings of Strong Moral Particularism" (2015). Critical Reflections. 3. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/essaysofsignificance/2014/eos2014/3 This Event is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in Critical Reflections by an authorized administrator of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 The Failings of Strong Particularism Timothy Grainger Jonathan Dancy has without a doubt raised important meta-ethical issues with traditional principle based ethical system, but he has also over stepped and taken up a position that he cannot defend. On one hand Dancy creates a strong argument for the need of context to play a role in ethical decision making and on the other hand he argues against the ability for principles to have any justified role in moral decision making. This paper will discuss the issues facing Dancy’s extreme rejection of principle, be it his utter rejection of moral principle or simply his rejection that any moral principle can ever be justified, and argue that such a stance is both unproductive and incoherent. Before attempting to dismantle Dancy’s position it is important to see why he should not be discounted altogether. Dancy’s particularism is motivated through two distinct paths; the idea that there is need for contextual sensitivity in ethical matters, and a belief that reasons are always holistic in nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasons and Moral Principles
    This is a repository copy of Reasons and Moral Principles. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/76787/ Version: Accepted Version Book Section: Väyrynen, P orcid.org/0000-0003-4066-8577 (2018) Reasons and Moral Principles. In: Star, D, (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. Oxford Handbooks . Oxford University Press , Oxford, UK , pp. 839-864. ISBN 9780199657889 https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199657889.013.37 © 2018, the several contributors. This material was originally published in The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Star, D., and has been reproduced by permission of Oxford University Press https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199657889.013.37. For permission to reuse this material, please visit http://global.oup.com/academic/rights. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Reasons and Moral Principles∗ Pekka V¨ayrynen University of Leeds 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1998 The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory Richard A. Posner Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Richard A. Posner, "The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory," 111 Harvard Law Review 1637 (1998). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. VOLUME 111 MAY 1998 NUMBER 7 1HARVARD LAW REVIEW1 '997 OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES LECTURES THE PROBLEMATICS OF MORAL AND LEGAL THEORY Richard A. Posner TABLE OF CONTENTS I. THE Lminrs OF MORAL THEORIZING ........................................................................... 638 A. The Thesis of PartI Summarized............................................................................. 638 B. My Moral Stance ......................................................................................................... 1642 x. Moral Relativism ................................................................................................ 1642 2. Moral Subjectivism ............................................................................................ 1643 3. Moral Skepticism ............................................................................................... 1643 4. Emotivism ..........................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • MORAL PARTICULARISM and TRANSDUCTION Gilbert Harman
    Philosophical Issues, 15, Normativity, 2005 MORAL PARTICULARISM AND TRANSDUCTION Gilbert Harman Princeton University Introduction There has been considerable recent discussion of one or another version of ‘‘moral particularism’’ as opposed to ‘‘moral generalism’’ (e.g., Dancy 1993, Sinnott-Armstrong 1999, Hooker and Little 2000, Kihlbom 2002, Va¨yrynen 2004). Moral generalism holds, either that specific moral truths have their source in general moral principles, or that reasonable or justified moral decisions and beliefs are based on the acceptance of general moral principles. Moral particularism rejects moral generalism. There are stronger and weaker versions of moral generalism and corre- spondingly weaker and stronger versions of moral particularism. Strong moral generalism holds, either that all specific moral truths have their source in general moral principles, or that all reasonable or justified moral deci- sions and beliefs are based on the acceptance of general principles. Weak moral generalism holds, either that at least some moral truths have their source in general moral principles, or that at least some reasonable or justified moral decisions and beliefs are based on the acceptance of general moral principles. Since the denial of a strong claim is weak and the denial of a weak claim is strong, strong moral particularism denies weak moral generalism and weak moral particularism denies strong moral generalism. I will be concerned with one of the issues between strong moral general- ism and weak moral particularism. The issues between particularism and generalism are metaphysical, to the extent that they concern the source of moral truths, and epistemic (or psychological), to the extent that they concern the source of reasonable or justified moral decisions and beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of a Particularist Research Program*
    A Defense of a Particularist Research Program* Uri D. Leibowitz Abstract: What makes some acts morally right and others morally wrong? Traditionally, philosophers have tried to answer this question by identifying exceptionless moral principles—principles that capture all and only morally right actions. Utilitarianism and Kantianism are paradigmatic examples of such attempts. In recent years, however, there has been a growing interest in a novel approach—Particularism—although its precise content is still a matter of controversy. In this paper I argue that some of the most common objections to particularism result from a misconception of the nature of particularism, and I offer a new formulation of the view. I argue that particularism is best understood as a research program characterized by the core hypothesis that morality can be explained without appeal to exceptionless moral principles, and I explicate some of the advantages of this formulation. Finally, I argue that particularism shows enough promise to warrant further exploration. I. Introduction Particularism is a controversial new movement in moral philosophy. It is not uncommon to hear philosophers say that particularism is a “crazy view” or that it amounts to giving up on moral theorizing. The most prevalent objections to particularism are that particularism is demonstrably false and that particularism is unmotivated.1 I believe that these negative assessments of particularism result from a misconception of the nature of particularism. I hope to show that particularism, properly understood, is a well-motivated project that should not be dismissed out of hand. I will proceed as follows: first, I will outline a recent version of the standard argument against particularism and explain why it is based on a misconception of particularism (section II).
    [Show full text]
  • Jurisprudence, Halakhah, and Moral Particularism
    Volume 64 Issue 5 Article 11 1-30-2020 Jurisprudence, Halakhah, and Moral Particularism Amy J. Sepinwall Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Amy J. Sepinwall, Jurisprudence, Halakhah, and Moral Particularism, 64 Vill. L. Rev. 757 (2020). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr/vol64/iss5/11 This Symposia is brought to you for free and open access by Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Villanova Law Review by an authorized editor of Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. Sepinwall: Jurisprudence, Halakhah, and Moral Particularism 2019] JURISPRUDENCE, HALAKHAH, AND MORAL PARTICULARISM AMY J. SEPINWALL* ALAKHAH is, perhaps maddeningly, about the particular. Examples Habound: Jewish law forbids wearing clothing that mixes wool and linen. Except if one is a kohen (Temple priest), in which case one must wear wool and linen. But only when in the Temple compound; or, accord- ing to a different school, even then only when performing Temple duties.1 Or again: On the Sabbath, a day of rest, one is prohibited from writing by hand. But not by foot or mouth. Old-school Scrabble does not count as writing, but playing on a more modern board with grooves that hold the letters in place does. The contortions and distinctions in these examples find counterparts all over the original codification of the oral tradition and the centuries of commentary that followed. Halakhah is alive, byzan- tine, and seemingly wild.2 Given halakhah’s complexity, one might have thought that it would defy theorization, envisioning it as recalcitrant to the scholar’s aim to disci- pline, unify, generalize.
    [Show full text]
  • Jonathan Dancy: Moral Particularism by Michael Brennen
    Jonathan Dancy: Moral Particularism by Michael Brennen - http://michaelbrennen.com Jonathan Dancy: Moral Particularism by Michael Brennen - Sunday, March 09, 2014 http://michaelbrennen.com/2014/03/09/jonathan-dancy-moral-particularism/ In his SEP article presenting moral particularism, Jonathan Dancy defended particularism against “absolute” and “contributory” moral generalism. Absolute moral generalism claims that a moral principle is “a universal claim to the effect that all actions of a certain type are overall wrong (or right).” On this view of morality, an absolute moral principle might be to not break a promise; thus breaking a promise, whatever the circumstances, is a moral wrong. Contributory moral generalism sees multiple moral principles as contributing to a moral valuation, with the various principles concerned coming to some net balance. On this view, breaking a promise might count against the moral valuation of a particular action, but it might be counterbalanced by other contributory principles. The appeal to principles takes both a metaphysical form and an epistemological form. In the metaphysical form, principles are what couple an action to the property of rightness or wrongness; thus the action of taking a piece of candy from a coworker’s desk is coupled to moral rightness or wrongness by the fact of whether the action is stealing, based on whether the coworker has made the candy available for the taking. In the epistemological form, we need a way to know whether an action is right or wrong, and non-moral features of the action determine its rightness or wrongness; on this view, principles are how a competent moral agent can connect the non-moral aspects of his actions to its moral rightness or wrongness.
    [Show full text]
  • Particularism and Generalism Revisited: Towards a Principled Particularism of Contingency
    PARTICULARISM AND GENERALISM REVISITED: TOWARDS A PRINCIPLED PARTICULARISM OF CONTINGENCY GEORGES THÉRIAULT Thesis submitted to the University of Ottawa in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the M.A. degree in Philosophy Department of Philosophy Faculty of Arts University of Ottawa Unceded Algonquin Territory © Georges Thériault, Ottawa, Canada, 2020 Abstract: This thesis will revisit the debate between moral particularists and moral generalists in the field of meta-ethics. The general aim of this project will be to come to a better understanding of the status and role of moral principles in a reasons-holistic moral landscape. The specific aim will be to develop a viable position within the particularism-generalism debate that will combine elements from both theories. My central argument will be threefold: (a) I will argue that, in a reasons-holistic moral landscape, exceptionless moral principles are not sufficient to ground the possibility of moral thought and judgement; (b) that the possibility of moral thought and judgement depends in part on a determinate set of exceptionless moral principles and an indeterminate set of defeasible moral principles; and (c) that moral principles are insufficient to codify all or most moral truths in finite and manageable terms. My position therefore is a modified version of Principled Particularism. In this thesis, despite defending a version of particularism, I will not shy away from employing generalist terminology or from accepting certain generalist assumptions. Furthermore, unlike some particularists, I will stress the necessity and utility of moral principles. This thesis will also incorporate research about moral thought and judgement from the fields of moral psychology, cognitive science, and neuroscience.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Particularism and Scientific Practice
    Moral Particularism and Scientific Practice Brendan Larvor Abstract: Particularism is usually understood as a position in moral philosophy. In fact, it is a view about all reasons, not only moral reasons. Here I show that particularism is a familiar and controversial position in the philosophy of science and mathematics. I then argue for particularism with respect to scientific and mathematical reasoning. This has a bearing on moral particularism, because if particularism about moral reasons is true, then particularism must be true with respect to reasons of any sort, including mathematical and scientific reasons. Keywords: ethics, moral, particularlism, science, mathematics, practice There has lately been a wave of interest in particularism. 1 This discussion has an odd feature: it has almost exclusively concerned moral particularism. This is odd because particularism is a thesis about reasons in general, not just moral reasons. The restriction of the discussion to moral reasons is a contingency. One leading particularist writer, Jonathan Dancy, claims that the debate has focussed on moral reasons because, in non-moral domains, particularism is uncontroversially true.2 The contention of this paper is that particularism is true of scientific and mathematical reasoning, but controversially so. Therefore, defenders of an unrestricted particularism about reasons must make the case for particularism with respect to non- moral reasons, including scientific and mathematical reasons. 3 In this paper, I shall first briefly characterise particularism in moral philosophy. Then, I will show that particularism is a familiar and controversial position in the philosophy of science and mathematics. I will then argue for particularism about 1 scientific and mathematical reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Dreams and Formulas: the Roles of Particularism and Principlism in the Law
    DREAMS AND FORMULAS: THE ROLES OF PARTICULARISM AND PRINCIPLISM IN THE LAW R. George Wright* I. INTRODUCTION The term “particularism” is encountered only rarely in the law.1 The basic idea of particularism itself is, however, of great importance in the law. Particularism is, helpfully, much more prominent in contemporary moral philosophy.2 The opposite of particularism, in moral philosophy and in law, is usually taken to be “generalism” or “principlism.”3 For the moment, we may think of particularism in the law as strongly de-emphasizing the roles of principles, rules, standards, policies, and tests.4 More positively, we may think of particularism in * Lawrence A. Jegen Professor of Law, Indiana University School of Law—Indianapolis. The author hereby extends his thanks to Rachel Anne Scherer for her continued advice and counsel. 1. For examples, see CASS R. SUNSTEIN, LEGAL REASONING AND POLITICAL CONFLICT 194 (1996) (“General theories do not decide concrete cases, and case-by-case particularism has advantages over the creation and application of broad rules.”); Frederick Schauer, Harry Kalven and the Perils of Particularism, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 397, 398 (1989) (reviewing HARRY KALVEN, JR., A WORTHY TRADITION: FREEDOM OF SPEECH IN AMERICA (1988)) [hereinafter Schauer, Perils of Particularism] (critiquing the common understanding that Harry Kalven was “a particularist, a devotee of the case-specific methods of the common law, an opponent of grand theory, and a scholar who saw the key to free speech adjudication not in large categories but in ‘thinking small’”); and Frederick Schauer, Rules and the Rule of Law, 14 HARV.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Discussion of Jonathan Dancy's Moral Particularism
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by St Andrews Research Repository A critical discussion of Jonathan Dancy’s Moral Particularism by Philipp Schwind Dissertation submitted for the degree of M.Phil. University of St. Andrews School of Philosophical, Anthropological and Film Studies December 2006 Declarations I, Philipp Schwind, hereby certify that this thesis, which is approximately 40,000 words in length, has been written by me, that it is the record of work carried out by me and that it has not been submitted in any previous application for a higher degree. Date . Signature of candidate. I was admitted as a research student in September 2005 and as a candidate for the degree of M.Phil. in September 2005; the higher study for which this is a record was carried out in the University of St. Andrews between 2005 and 2006. Date . Signature of candidate. I hereby certify that the candidate has fulfilled the conditions of the Resolution and Regulations appropriate for the degree of M.Phil. in the University of St. Andrews and that the candidate is qualified to submit this thesis in application for that degree. Date . Signature of candidate. In submitting this thesis to the University of St. Andrews I understand that I am giving permission for it to be made available for use in accordance with the regulations of the University Library for the time being in force, subject to any copyright vested in the work not being affected thereby. I also understand that the title and abstract will be published, and that a copy of my work may be made and supplied to any bona fide library or research worker.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Particularism and the Charge of Intuitionism
    Moral particularism and the charge of intuitionism Juliën van Eck Master thesis Philosophy of Political Science Supervisor: Bruno Verbeek “You can't just turn on creativity like a faucet. You have to be in the right mood. - What mood is that? Last-minute panic.” ― Bill Watterson “Am I a good person? Deep down, do I even really want to be a good person, or do I only want to seem like a good person so that people (including myself) will approve of me? Is there a difference? How do I ever actually know whether I'm bullshitting myself, morally speaking?” ― David Foster Wallace Table of contents Introduction .................................................................................................................................................. 2 1. Four types of particularism ..................................................................................................................... 6 1.1 Analytic particularism ........................................................................................................................ 6 1.2 Metaphysical particularism ............................................................................................................... 7 1.3 Epistemological particularism ........................................................................................................ 11 1.4 Methodological particularism ......................................................................................................... 13 1.5 Conclusion .......................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]