<<

media matters

edited by boomen, den van marianne sybille lammes, ann-sophie lehmann, joost raessens, schäfer tobias mirko and

Tracing Tracing in Everyday Life and amsterdam university press university amsterdam Digital Material

edited by marianne van den boomen sybille lammes Digital Material ann-sophie lehmann joost raessens mirko tobias schäfer ­ ­

­

-

playing games and playing - learning,fromrole - from touch screens to blogging and assembled their material’ ‘digital into an an accompanied by versatile popular and academic discourse. New alignment of new media yielded to a lished academic discipline, and this begs ­showcase of current research in the digital culture indeed all about ‘you’, the understanddigitalmachinerythe how and .the e crystallized internationally into an estab­ an into internationally crystallized the question: where do we stand now? this constitutes us as ‘you’? The contribu tors of the present book, all teaching and thology, covering issues ranging from desk 2.0 metaphorstopWeb to ecosystems, in the programDigital the and Media New in materialist’perspective. media are taken for granted, and which riddles are still unsolved? Is contemporary participating user, or do we still not really researching new media and digital culture, host of innovations, trials, and problems, field, from what may ‘digitalbe called a Culture at the Department for Media and Culture Studies, Utrecht University, Cybergoth music to wireless dreams. Which new questions emerge new questions now new Which www.aup.nl press university amsterdam Together the contributions provide a provide contributions the Together The editors are all teaching and researching Three decadessocietalof cultural and

media matters 0 068 4 96 978-90-896-4068-0 908 8 ISBN 97 Digital Material

Digital Material

Tracing New Media in Everyday Life and Technology

Edited by Marianne van den Boomen, Sybille Lammes, Ann-Sophie Lehmann, Joost Raessens, and Mirko Tobias Schäfer

Amsterdam University Press MediaMatters is a new series published by Amsterdam University Press on current debates about media technology and practices. International scholars critically analyze and theorize the materiality and performativity, as well as spatial practices of ‘old’ and ‘new’ media in contributions that engage with today’s culture. For more information about the series, please visit: www.aup.nl

The publication of this book was made possible with the financial support of the GATE project, funded by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO) and the Netherlands ICT Research and Innovation Authority (ICT Regie), the Transformations in Art and Culture programme (NWO) and the Innovational Research Incentives Scheme (NWO). We would also like to express our thanks to the Research Institute for History and Culture (OCG) and the Department of Med- ia and Culture Studies at Utrecht University for their kind support.

Cover illustration: Goos Bronkhorst Cover design: Suzan de Beijer, Weesp Lay out: JAPES, Amsterdam

ISBN 978 90 8964 068 0 e-ISBN 978 90 4850 666 8 NUR 670

Creative Commons License CC BY NC ND (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0) All authors / Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, 2009

Some rights reversed. Without limiting the rights under reserved above, any part of this book may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise). Table of contents

Introduction: From the virtual to matters of fact and concern 7

Processor Joost Raessens Serious games from an apparatus perspective 21

David B. Nieborg Empower yourself, defend freedom! Playing games during times of war 35

Eggo Müller Formatted spaces of participation: Interactive and the changing relationship between production and consumption 49

Erna Kotkamp Digital objects in e-learning environments: The case of WebCT 65

Memory Imar de Vries The vanishing points of mobile 81

Jos de Mul The work of art in the age of digital recombination 95

Berteke Waaldijk The design of world citizenship: A historical comparison between world exhibitions and the web 107

Isabella van Elferen ‘And created music’: Cybergothic music and the phantom voices of the technological uncanny 121

Network William Uricchio Moving beyond the artefact: Lessons from participatory culture 135

Mirko Tobias Schäfer Participation inside? User activities between design and appropriation 147

5 Marinka Copier Challenging the magic circle: How online role-playing games are negotiated by everyday life 159

Douglas Rushkoff Renaissance now! The gamers’ perspective 173

Screen Frank Kessler What you get is what you see: Digital images and the claim on the real 187

Eva Nieuwdorp The pervasive interface: Tracing the magic circle 199

Nanna Verhoeff Grasping the screen: Towards a conceptualization of touch, mobility and multiplicity 209

Sybille Lammes Terra incognita: games, cartography and spatial stories 223

Keyboard Thomas Poell Conceptualizing forums and as public sphere 239

Marianne van den Boomen Interfacing by material metaphors: How your mailbox may fool you 253

Ann-Sophie Lehmann Hidden practice: Artists’ working spaces, tools, and materials in the digital domain 267 About the authors 283 Index 285

6 digital material Introduction

From the virtual to matters of fact and concern

All that is solid melts into air Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, 1848

Technology is society made durable Bruno Latour, 1991

The 1982 Time magazine’s ‘Man of the Year’ election was a special one. For the first time in the history of this traditional annual event, a non-human was cele- brated: the computer was declared ‘Machine of the Year 1982’. The cover dis- played a table with a on it, and a man sitting passively next to it and looking rather puzzled. On the 2006 Time’s election cover once again a computer was shown, now basically a screen reflecting the ‘Person of the Year’: ‘YOU. Yes, you. You control the . Welcome to your world.’ Within 24 years the computer seemed to have changed from an exciting, mys- terious machine with unknown capabilities into a transparent mirror, reflecting you, your desires and your activities. Apparently, digital embody no un- solved puzzles any more. At the beginning of the , they are so widely distributed and used that we take them for granted – though we still call them ‘new media’. , e-, the , mobile phones, digital photo al- bums, and computer games have become common artefacts in our daily lives. Part of the initial spell has worn off, yet new spells have been cast as well, and some of the old spells still haunt the discourse about the so-called new media. Three decades of societal and cultural alignment of digital machinery yielded a host of innovations, trials, failures, and problems, accompanied by hype-hopping popular and academic discourse. Meanwhile, new media studies crystallized in- ternationally into an established academic discipline, especially when the first academic bachelor and master programs were institutionalized ten years ago, in- cluding the Utrecht program, New Media and Digital Culture.1 A decade of un- folding the field implores us to reflect on where we stand now. Which new ques- tions emerge when new media are taken for granted, and which puzzles are still unsolved? Is contemporary digital culture indeed all about ‘you’, or do we still not really fathom the digital machinery and how it constitutes us as ‘you’? The con- tributors to the present book, all teaching and researching new media and digital

7 culture, and all involved in the Utrecht Media Research group, assembled their ‘digital material’ into an anthology to celebrate the tenth anniversary of the Utrecht program. Together, the contributions provide a showcase of current state-of-the–art research in the field, from what we as editors have called a ‘digi- tal-materialist’ perspective.

Immaterial, im/material, in-material Popular discourse in the 1990s framed new media chiefly as possessing new and amazing qualities. They were believed to fundamentally transform the way we think, live, love, work, learn, and play. Hypertext, virtual reality, and cyberspace were the predominant buzzwords. They announced a new frontier of civilization, whether from an optimistic utopian perspective – pointing to the emergence of virtual communities, new democracy, and a new economy – or from a more pes- simistic and dystopian angle – with warnings against the digital divide, informa- tion glut, and ubiquitous surveillance. Yet, both outlooks were rooted in the same idea: that new media marked a shift from the material to the immaterial, a gener- al transformation of atoms into bits (Negroponte 1995) and of matter into mind (Barlow 1996). These lines of reasoning were characterized by what we may call digital mysticism, a special brand of technological determinism in which digitality and software are considered to be ontologically immaterial determinants of new media. New media and their effects were thus framed as being ‘hyper’, ‘virtual’, and ‘cyber’–that is, outside of the known materiality, existing independently of the usual material constraints and determinants, such as material bodies, politics, and the economy. Though this kind of discourse was criticized right from the start as a specific ideology (Barbrook and Cameron 1995), it proved to be persis- tent, and traces of it can still be discerned in the current academic discourse. When new media appeared on the radar of media and communication studies, the initial attempts to ground digitality consisted of remediating theories from the study of ‘old’ media, such as the performance arts (Laurel 1991), literature (Aar- seth 1997; Ryan 1999), and cinema (Manovich 2001), or even taking ‘remediation’ itself as the regulative mechanism of digital media (Bolter and Grusin 1999). Over the years, new media studies gradually became emancipated from its remediating inspirers. The field claimed its own medium specificities, yet remained multidis- ciplinary, as it appropriated theoretical concepts and research methodologies from disciplines like media studies, cultural studies, philosophy, , science and technology studies, and critical discourse analysis. This led to the emergence of subfields such as Internet studies, virtual ethnography (Hine 2000), game studies (Copier and Raessens 2003; Raessens and Goldstein 2005), and (Fuller 2008). During the past decade academic endeavors gradually left the initial speculative cyber-discourse behind. The focus shifted to the plurality of new media and digi-

8 digital material tal cultures, and how they are embedded in society and everyday life (Lievrouw 2004; Bakardjieva 2005). New media were no longer considered as being ‘out there’ but rather as being ‘here and amongst us’. Still, this does not necessarily imply the complete dissolution of digital mysti- cism. The complexity of digital code is necessarily boxed in user-friendly interfaces, and this makes assumptions of mysterious immateriality hard to exor- cize. Even explicit attempts to foreground ‘digital matters’ in order to counter the relative underexposure of the material signifier speak of ‘the paradox of im/mate- riality’ (Taylor and Harris 2005) when addressing the issue of digital ontology. The solution of this paradox is usually to phrase it in the vein of Michael Heim’s classic ‘real and material in effect, not in fact’ (Heim 1993), thus still presuppos- ing an immaterial digital domain. However, already in the early days of the of culture and communi- cation, the move beyond the seemingly insuperable dichotomy was attempted. In 1985 Jean-François Lyotard curated an exhibition at the Centre Georges Pompi- dou in Paris, entitled Les immatériaux (Lyotard 1985). This was the first public, experimental encounter with the cultural shift the computer was about to pro- duce. The exhibition was accompanied by an interactive catalogue, written by var- ious authors on the French Minitel system, thus representing one of the first pieces of collaborative electronic writing (Wunderlich 2008). While Lyotard and his co-authors – very much in tune with the predominant utopian fantasies of that period – mused about a future without material objects, the very title of the proj- ect already pointed towards the incorporation of the virtual into the material world. The simple use of the plural turned the immaterial, the realm of abstract thought, into palpable parts of something that is, although it cannot be touched, an inseparable part of the material world. In a similar vein, the authors of this volume want to go a step further in recog- nizing digital materiality, not so much as ‘im/material’ but rather as ‘in-material’ – as software for instance cannot exist by itself but is intrinsically embedded in physical data carriers (Schäfer 2008). In other words, as stuff which may defy immediate physical contact, yet which is incorporated in materiality rather than floating as a metaphysical substance in virtual space. We consider digital cultures as material practices of appropriation, and new media objects as material assem- blages of hardware, software, and wetware. As such, they are ‘society made dur- able’ (Latour 1991), that is, material artefacts and facts, configured by human actors, tools and in an intricate web of mutually shaping relations. This approach aligns with the ‘material turn’ that can be witnessed in cultural and media studies and has led to a renewed interest in anthropological and socio- logical theory in these fields. William J.T. Mitchell described the theoretical turn towards material aspects of everyday culture and the concern with objects or things (Brown 2004) as a reaction to immaterialization in a postcolonial world: ‘The age of the disembodied, immaterial virtuality and cyberspace is upon us, and introduction 9 therefore we are compelled to think about material objects’ (Mitchell 2004, 149). We would rather argue that this interest is a reaction to the myth of the immater- ial, rather than pointing to an actual immaterialization of culture. The material gatherings (Latour 2005; 1993) of new media that are explored in this book can take on many forms and formats, on various scales. They may be objects such as computer games, desktop icons, digitized archives, computer art, debates, or handheld gadgets, but also actions such as checking e-mail, up- loading a movie to YouTube, online role-playing, listening to music, or using an e-learning environment. When it comes to digital material, the lines separating objects, actions, and actors are hard to draw, as they are hybridized in technolo- gical affordances, software configurations and user interfaces. Consequently, we aim to present an integrative approach in this book that takes into account ‘tech- nological’ aspects as well as the social uses of media, including the accompanying discourses. Contrary to accounts that conceive digital artefacts as being immater- ial, this book considers both the technological specificities as well as the socio- political relations and the effects on social realities as an inherent aspect of new media. The contributions cover different areas of digital culture, but they all en- dorse a material understanding of digital artefacts by situating their objects of research in a dispositif that comprehends the dynamic connections between dis- courses, social appropriation, and technological design (Kessler 2006).

Processor, memory, network, screen, keyboard Together the chapters in this book will give an overview of, and at the same time develop a theoretical approach to, digital cultures as material practices – material practices as performed and experienced in daily life as well as configured in tech- nology. They show how the idea of a digital materiality can be grasped and theo- rized within the field of new media studies, drawing on the diverse backgrounds and research objects, ranging from wireless technologies, software studies, com- puter graphics and digital to Internet metaphors and game-play. To stay true to the digital-material approach that we envisage in this book, we have divided this book into five sections, each alluding to a material computer: PROCESSOR, MEMORY, NETWORK, SCREEN and KEYBOARD. While these con- cepts explicitly foreground technology, they should also be read as ‘metaphorical concepts’ (Lakoff and Johnson 1980), that is, as heuristic devices which highlight specific aspects of new media configurations. As computer components, they seem to refer primarily to hardware objects, yet it should be stressed that they all need software to work. Moreover, none of the components can function indepen- dently. Metaphorically, each component provides access to a different configura- tion of digital material, as each reflects another assemblage of the versatile re- search ground that new media studies entail. The PROCESSOR is the beating heart of a computer system; in this book it exemplifies the procedural inner work-

10 digital material ings of a machine, or better several machineries: technological, economical, and political. MEMORY refers to devices for storage and retrieval; metaphorically it stands for history, recurring patterns and persistent ideas. The NETWORK en- ables connections, transmissions, and extensions; as a metaphorical book section it interrogates how the social-cultural assemblages of contemporary machinery are connected to society and daily life. The last two sections – SCREEN and KEY- BOARD – pertain to passage points: how users interact with digital machines through interfaces. The SCREEN represents how the machinery reflects and re- fracts its users, how their activities are channeled, and how hardware, software, and visual culture are related. And last but not least, the KEYBOARD foregrounds how users interact with the machinery; metaphorically it shows how users appro- priate digital tools.

Inside the assemblage The first three sections – PROCESSOR, MEMORY and NETWORK – stress the social-cultural assemblage of contemporary machinery. The PROCESSOR section consists of contributions that focus on questions pertaining to how digital ma- chinery carries out certain cultural ‘programs’ or instructions. It specifically pays attention to how and by whom they are executed and created, whether in terms of ideology, participatory culture or design. In his chapter Serious games from an apparatus perspective, Joost Raessens draws our attention to so-called serious gaming when he engages in a critical discussion about educational games that are meant to incite learning through playing. By approaching them as a ludic apparatus within the conceptual framework of the Lacanian philosopher Žižek, Raessens reveals the political-ideological tendencies that are inscribed in such games, through both design and play. In Empower yourself, defend freedom! Playing games during times of war, David Nie- borg takes us to quite another instance of ‘serious gaming’, as developed inside the military machine. Discussing the branding of the game America’s Army, which was developed to recruit for the real American army, he examines how national propaganda can be effective in the context of global entertainment. Nieborg de- monstrates that the global dissemination of this game among youth culture may weaken the purpose of recruitment, but at the same time endows it with a more implicit persuasive power that has its own ideological value. In his contribution, Formatted spaces of participation: Interactive television and the changing relationship between production and consumption, Eggo Müller gives a histori- cally comparative analysis of the television machinery by fleshing out the concept of participation in interactive television and how this has transformed associa- tions between producing and consuming. By discussing three cases of interactive television and sharing sites, Müller argues that participation can be best understood in terms of formatted spaces that are culturally determined. introduction 11 The last chapter in this section returns to educational processing, now enabled not by games or entertainment but by the design of e-learning systems. In her contribution Digital objects in e-learning environments: The case of WebCT, Erna Kot- kamp argues that a different approach to the design of e-learning environments such as WebCT and Blackboard is needed when educational tools change their objectives towards user interaction rather than content transference. To function as a machine, a computer needs at very least a processor and MEMORY. The first is needed for execution and calculation, the second for sto- rage and retrieval of data. In accordance, the MEMORY section of this book com- prises chapters that deal with how digital machinery stores and retrieves data, thereby producing, reproducing and negotiating cultural artefacts. As Michel Serres famously noted in his conversation with Bruno Latour (Serres and Latour 1995), things are only contemporary by composition, and some parts are always related to memory and the past. Digital materials should correspondingly be seen as assemblages that hold various temporal references, tapping from previously stored and inscribed cultural resources. The chapters in this section examine in different ways how contemporary digital technologies relate to inscriptions of other times. Imar de Vries draws our attention to a temporal dimension of new media when he discusses utopian discourses surrounding mobile devices. In The vanishing points of mobile communication, he ascertains that just like discussions in the early 1990s about the Internet, utopian visions about mobile communication embody an age-old quest for ideal communication. Yet, as De Vries shows, such utopian discourses of progress are incongruent in certain respects with how mobile tech- nologies are experienced in everyday life. Hence, living in a connected culture entertains a paradoxical relationship with utopian ideals of perfect communica- tion. The MEMORY section takes on a more philosophical stance with Jos de Mul’s discussion of Walter Benjamin. In The work of art in the age of digital recombination, De Mul contends that Benjamin’s notion of ‘exhibition value’ should be replaced by that of ‘manipulation value’ to be able to understand art in the digital age. He claims that a ‘database ontology’ can serve as a suitable paradigmatic model to account for digital art, both by its technological affordances and its metaphorical power. In The design of world citizenship: A historical comparison between world exhibitions and the web, Berteke Waaldijk examines historical dimensions of digital practices by comparing 19th-century world fairs with the Internet. She shows that the promise of seeing everything on the web bears clear similarities to the promise of seeing the world at world exhibitions. In both cases there is a disparity between ideolo- gical promises of seeing and the vulnerability of being watched and controlled as well as an oscillation between global and local positionings of citizenship.

12 digital material In Isabella van Elferen’s contribution ‘And machine created music’: Cybergothic music and the phantom voices of the technological uncanny, memory takes on yet another meaning by asserting that a fascination with the past is a constitutive part of cybergothic music cultures that celebrate the mixing of human and technological agency of past and present. Thus situated in a twilight zone, these subcultures replay and reshape sounds and voices from the past in a contemporary digital and technological setting. The parts of our metaphorical computer can never function separately, but need to be connected to other parts to work properly. In the NETWORK section of this book, this facet is highlighted as attention shifts to how digital material should be conceived as being part of a more widespread network. How the parti- cipatory role of the user should be acknowledged as part of a network is ad- dressed in the first two chapters of this section. William Uricchio relates the digi- tal present to the analogue past when discussing in Moving beyond the artefact: Lessons from participatory culture how the ‘digital turn’, and the possibilities of parti- cipation as promised by Web 2.0 discourse, changed our concept of archiving historical data. He argues that the users’ possibilities to add and alter content have changed our concept of archiving in old and new media. In Participation inside? User activities between design and appropriation, Mirko Tobias Schäfer engages in a critical discussion about how the line between creation and consumption has blurred since the emergence of Internet applications like Nap- ster. Though user appropriation of such file-sharing technologies challenges the established media industry whose business models rely on controlling the distri- bution of media objects, user activities should not be conceived as unequivocally subversive. Schäfer therefore calls for a critical analysis of how digital network technologies are appropriated, recreated and reassembled by various actors. Marinka Copier plays up another dimension of networking technologies in de- scribing how playing on-line games like World of Warcraft becomes a part of daily practice. In her contribution Challenging the magic circle: How online role-playing games are negotiated by everyday life, she argues that playing such games is so much inter- woven with trivial daily activities that the idea of entering a ‘magic circle’ (Huizin- ga 1938) when playing a game no longer suffices. Instead, she proposes treating games like World of Warcraft as networks that are anchored in our everyday life. In Douglas Rushkoff’s chapter the digital world is understood as a network of stories in which the power of making stories is becoming more egalitarian. In Renaissance now! The gamers’ perspective, he heralds a new generation of gamers who will generate a resurrection of participation in making stories. He foresees a new digitized world of playing in which we can be active agents in producing the stories that make the world go round, thus generating new narrative networks by controlling the buttons and breaking hegemonies.

introduction 13 Points of passage The last two sections of the book concentrate less on the inside and more on the negotiations between the outside and inside of digital machinery, by respectively taking on the SCREEN and the KEYBOARD as perceptual interfaces and concep- tual metaphors that serve as points of passage between user and machine. In the SCREEN section, contributions focus on how screens function as a membrane or locus of passage that hybridize and connect different realms and categories. Frank Kessler undertakes a constructive comparison between analogue and di- gital and film in how they relate to ‘the real’ in What you get is what you see: Digital images and the claim on the real. He claims that debates about the real or authentic quality of recorded images has shifted since the emergence of new media, where an image is no longer necessarily pre-recorded and data become more mutable. He evaluates whether and how the Peircian term ‘indexicality’ (pertaining to a sign that points to a physical or existential relation) still holds validity for digital images. Also in Eva Nieuwdorp’s contribution The pervasive interface: Tracing the magic cir- cle, matters of physicality and reality are addressed, here in relation to pervasive games rather than images. Pervasive games intentionally mingle with daily life and therefore need a theoretical framework that takes this into account. She ar- gues that the notion of interface can serve as a central tool to recognize the ‘lim- inal’ character of such games that are not situated within a clearly delineated virtual game world. Hence Nieuwdorp calls for an interfacial approach to perva- sive games that allows us to acknowledge the connection between its fantastical dimensions and daily life. In the following chapter Grasping the screen: Towards a conceptualization of touch, mobility and multiplicity, Nanna Verhoeff analyzes the interface in another manner, when discussing the Nintendo DS as a particular new screen practice, that is at the same time mobile, tactile and making use of a double screen. Like Raessens, she proposes using the concept of dispositif. She appropriates this concept to show how the Nintendo DS, as a ‘theoretical object’, marks a rupture from the cinematic and televisual screen dispositif in terms of multiplicity of mobility and a shift from perception to tactile productivity. In the last chapter of this section, Sybille Lammes analyzes cartographical screens in strategy games. In Terra incognita: Computer games, cartography and spatial stories, she discusses the use of cartography in such games. She particularly fo- cuses on the mutable qualities of digital maps that are visible on the computer screen and how they are intertwined with landscapes that players have to master. Lammes shows that the distinction between tour and map as theorized by De Certeau (1984) needs to be revised in order to culturally comprehend the spatial functions of such games.

14 digital material Lastly, in the KEYBOARD section, attention shifts to another interfacial aspect of new media, namely how users interact with digital material. Closely related to the section about screens, here the accent lies on how users have ‘hands-on’ con- tact with digital machinery. The main perspective changes here towards the user of the computer, whether writer, reader, player, or artist. In the first chapter Thomas Poell discusses the user as reader and writer parti- cipating in public debates on the Internet. In Conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere, he explores whether and how the concepts of public sphere and mul- tiple public spheres can be used to understand the role of web forums and blogs in public debate. Taking the heated debate that developed on the Internet after the assassination of Dutch critic and film director Theo van Gogh as his main case, he shows that even updated versions of Habermas’s public sphere theory do not entirely cover the medium-specific dynamics of forums and blogs. Marianne van den Boomen examines the user as a ‘reader’ and operator of material metaphors. In Interfacing by material metaphors: How your mailbox may fool you, she aims to yield insight into interface metaphors, such as the mail icon, which function as ‘sign-tools’. She unravels these material metaphors as con- densed icons that absorb and conceal their indexical relations to software and hardware processes. Similar to Kessler, she discusses computer icons as Peircian indexical signs, but also as Heideggerian tools. While Van den Boomen discusses the user as an operator of sign-tools, Ann- Sophie Lehmann speaks about the user as artist. In Hidden practice: The representation of artists’ working spaces, tools and materials in digital visual culture, she compares the way that painters’ practices were represented in the pre-modern era with how the work of digital artists is presented in contemporary visual culture. She shows how media artists make use of similarly complex and custom-made tools as artists in the pre-industrial age, but contrary to representations of the painter at work, the practice of making digital art is rendered invisible.

Just like the parts of the metaphorical computer that structure this book, each chapter in this book highlights different constituents of the digital machine, map- ping out how new media can be traced as digital material. One prevalent manner of doing so is by showing how technology is interwoven with culture and history. The Utrecht Media Research program has long been concerned with research into media’s cultural construction, both diachronically and synchronically. This tradi- tion stands in sharp contrast to definitions of media based solely upon a supposi- tion of their technological, sociological, semiotic or aesthetic specificity. Our re- search is a quest for what may be termed the dynamics of media dispositifs, that is, tracing constellations of factors, including discursive formations, economic strategies, socio-cultural functions, as well as technological affordances and ap- propriation by users.

introduction 15 The contributions in this book all recognize that new media are not only em- bedded in but also generate and reassemble material cultures. This pertains to what Matthew Fuller has called the ‘reality-forming nature of a medium’ (Fuller 2005, 2). Contrary to views of new media as producing virtual experiences that lie outside everyday material realities, or as generating ‘just representations’,or‘just metaphors’, this book emphasizes that they embody, assemble and reproduce gatherings that are always material – both in effect and as matters of fact. Or better, as matters of concern, since matters of fact should never be taken for granted. As Bruno Latour (2005, 114) writes: ‘The discussion begins to shift for good when one introduces not matters of fact but what I now call matters of con- cern. While highly uncertain and loudly disputed, these real, objective, atypical, and above all, interesting agencies are taken not exactly as object but rather as gatherings.’ New media and digital material are all about such interesting gather- ings, as we hope to show in the present book.

Utrecht, December 2008

Marianne van den Boomen, Sybille Lammes, Ann-Sophie Lehmann, Joost Raes- sens, Mirko Tobias Schäfer

Note 1. For more information, see newmediastudies.nl

References Aarseth, Espen J. 1997. Cybertext: Perspectives on ergodic literature. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Bakardjieva, Maria. 2005. Internet society: The Internet in everyday life. London: Sage. Barbrook, Richard, and Andy Cameron. 1995. The Carlifornian ideology. Mute 1 (3). Barlow, John Perry. 1996. A declaration of the independence of cyberspace. http://www.eff. org/~barlow/Declaration-Final.html. Bolter, Jay David, and Richard Grusin. 1999. Remediation: Understanding new media. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Brown, Bill, ed. 2004. Things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Copier, Marinka, and Joost Raessens, eds. 2003. Level up: Digital games research conference. Utrecht: Utrecht University. De Certeau, Michel. 1984. The practice of everyday life. Berkeley: University of California Press. Fuller, Matthew. 2005. Media ecologies: Materialist energies in art and technoculture. Leonardo. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. —. 2008. Software studies: A lexicon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Heim, Michael. 1993. The essence of VR. In The metaphysics of virtual reality, 109-128. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

16 digital material Hine, Christine. 2000. Virtual ethnography. London: Sage. Huizinga, Johan. 1938. Homo ludens: Proeve eener bepaling van het spel-element der cultuur. Haar- lem: Tjeenk Willink. Kessler, Frank. 2006. Notes on dispositif. http://www.let.uu.nl/~Frank.Kessler/personal/ notes%20on%20dispositif.PDF. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chi- gago Press. Latour, Bruno. 1991. Technology is society made durable. In A sociology of monsters: Essays on power, technology, and domination, ed. John Law, 103-131. London: Routledge. —. 1993. We have never been modern. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf. —. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford: Oxford Univer- sity Press. Laurel, Brenda. 1991. Computers as theatre. Reading: Addison-Wesley. Lievrouw, Leah A. 2004. What’s changed about new media? Introduction to the fifth anni- versary issue of New Media & Society. New Media & Society 6 (1): 9-15. Lyotard, Jean-François, ed. 1985. Les Immatériaux. Paris: Centre Georges Pompidou. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1848. The communist manifesto. Vol. 1. Marx/Engels selected works. Moscow: Progress Publishers. Mitchell, William J.T. 2004. What do pictures want? The lives and loves of images. Chicago: Uni- versity of Chicago Press. Negroponte, Nicholas. 1995. Being digital. New York: Knopf. Raessens, Joost, and Jeffrey Goldstein, eds. 2005. Handbook of computer game studies. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Ryan, Marie-Laure, ed. 1999. Cyberspace textuality: Computer technology and literary theory. Bloo- mington: Indiana University Press. Schäfer, Mirko Tobias. 2008. Bastard culture! User participation and the extension of cultural indus- tries. Utrecht: Dissertation Faculty of Humanities Utrecht University. Serres, Michel, and Bruno Latour. 1995. Conversations on science, culture, and time. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Taylor, Paul A., and Jan L. Harris. 2005. Digital matters: The theory and culture of the matrix. New York: Routledge. Wunderlich, Antonia. 2008. Der Philosoph im Museum: Die Ausstellung ‘Les Immatériaux’ von Jean François Lyotard. Bielefeld: Transcript.

introduction 17

Processor

Serious games from an apparatus perspective

Joost Raessens

According to the French philosopher Gilles Deleuze, concepts are meaningless unless they are helpful to the understanding and solution of significant contem- porary problems (Deleuze and Parnet 1996).¹ In line with Deleuze, I will intro- duce the concept of the ‘gaming apparatus’ as a heuristic tool for the study of the political-ideological coloring of so-called serious games. These games have ‘an explicit and carefully thought-out educational purpose and are not intended to be played primarily for amusement’ (Michael and Chen 2006, 21). Such a tool is im- portant because, to date, much of the debate on serious games has merely been framed in terms of effectiveness without paying attention to their political-ideolo- gical interest. And when theorists do pay attention to the political-ideological in- terest of games, they barely involve the game’s medium specificity in their ana- lyses. In the first and second paragraph, I will define the concept of the gaming ap- paratus and discuss the possible political-ideological tendencies of the playing of serious games. In order to do so, I will refer to the work of the Slovenian philoso- pher Slavoj Žižek. In the third paragraph, I will interpret the possible political- ideological tendencies which Žižek refers to as ‘virtual’. These tendencies may or may not be actualized, depending on the different ways in which the player of the game is positioned in or by the gaming apparatus. As I will argue in paragraph four and five, questions about the political-ideological meaning of a specific se- rious game can, thus, only be answered by taking into account all the elements of the gaming apparatus. We will see this in my analysis of Food Force (2005), a game I consider to be quintessentially serious.

The gaming apparatus One of the founding fathers of the so-called ‘apparatus theory’–a dominant the- ory within film studies during the 1970s – is the French psychoanalytic film theor- ist Jean-Louis Baudry (1986a, 1986b). Studying media from an apparatus perspec- tive means studying them as configurations of technology and materiality, user positioning, unconscious desires, media text and context, and the production of

21 meaning as an interplay between these elements.² Therefore, the analysis of se- rious games from an apparatus perspective pays attention to these five elements that contribute to their production of meaning: (1) The technical or material basis of serious games that help to shape (2) specific positionings of the player based upon (3) specific unconscious desires to which correspond (4) different game forms or texts with their specific modes of address and (5) different institutional and cultural contexts and playing situations. This multilayered model shows that the production of meaning emerges ‘in new structures of political, material, and aesthetic combination’ (Fuller, 2005, x). As a starting point I will analyze the poli- tical-ideological tendencies of the specific unconscious desires at play when play- ing serious games. I will do so by analyzing in this paragraph the conceptual framework of the Lacanian philosopher Žižek (1999) and in the next paragraph the ways in which his philosophical framework has been translated into the field of educational gaming. Žižek starts his analysis of the range of unconscious desires by addressing the following question: ‘What are the consequences of cyberspace for Oedipus – that is, for the mode of subjectivization that psychoanalysis conceptualized as the Oe- dipus complex and its dissolution?’ (Žižek 1999, 110). What makes this question important to the study of serious games is that, framed within a Lacanian per- spective, these kinds of games deal with the player’s persuasion of or entry into the game’s symbolic order.³ Žižek himself advocates a third way, somewhere in between the two standard reactions toward cyberspace: that cyberspace involves the end of Oedipus (whether in a dystopian or utopian form) or, on the contrary, that cyberspace entails the continuation of Oedipus. This third way he defines as ‘interpassivity’. These three reactions are charted in the following table.

Žižek 1 End of Oedipus 2 Continuation of 3 In-between: 1A Dystopia 1B Utopia Oedipus interpassivity

Table 1: Reactions toward cyberspace, from a Lacanian perspective

According to Žižek, the first standard reaction toward cyberspace is that it in- volves the end of Oedipus. According to some – Žižek is referring to Jean Baudril- lard and Paul Virilio – this end of Oedipus is a dystopian development (1A, see Table 1):

Individuals regressing to pre-symbolic psychotic immersion, of losing the symbolic distance that sustains the minimum of critical/reflective attitude (the idea that the computer functions as a maternal Thing that swallows the sub- ject, who entertains an attitude of incestuous fusion towards it) (Žižek 1999, 111).

22 digital material On the other hand, there are theorists – here Žižek refers to Sandy Stone and Sherry Turkle – who emphasize the liberating potential of cyberspace (1B, see Table 1):

Cyberspace opens up the domain of shifting multiple sexual and social identi- ties, at least potentially liberating us from the hold of the patriarchal Law (...) In cyberspace, I am compelled to renounce any fixed symbolic identity, the legal/political fiction of a unique Self guaranteed by my place in the socio-sym- bolic structure (ibid., 112).

According to the second standard reaction toward cyberspace, the oedipal mode of subjectivization continues, albeit by other means:

Yes, in cyberspace, ‘you can be whatever you want’, you’re free to choose a symbolic identity (screen-persona), but you must choose one which in a way will always betray you, which will never be fully adequate; you must accept representation in cyberspace by a signifying element that runs around in the circuitry as your stand-in (ibid., 114).

Finally, Žižek argues that both standard reactions to cyberspace – as a break from or a continuation with Oedipus – are wrong and that we need to conceptualize a middle position. This ‘in between’ is described by Žižek as ‘interpassivity’. ‘Inter- activity’ and ‘interpassivity’ are two different ways in which digital technologies position people as responders. They are not oppositional, but mutually constitu- tive. According to Žižek, the term ‘’ is currently used in two senses: ‘(1) interacting with the medium – that is, not being just a passive consumer’ (Žižek 1999, 105). This is the case when a player is clicking and moving a mouse, and tapping the keys of the keyboard. The second form of interactivity occurs when these actions lead to in-game actions: ‘(2) acting through another agent, so that my job is done, while I sit back and remain passive, just observing the game’ (ibid., 105-106). This is the case when the player observes how an avatar on the screen acts. According to Žižek, interpassivity is a reversal of the second meaning of interactivity: ‘the distinguishing feature of interpassivity is that, in it, the subject is incessantly – frenetically even – active, while displacing on to another the funda- mental passivity of his or her being’ (Žižek 1999, 106). We see this interpassive mechanism at work when the player is passionately clicking and tapping while his avatar is fulfilling the game’s demands. Žižek’s prime example of interpassivity is the Japanese electronic toy, the Tamagotchi. The Tamagotchi is a virtual pet that captivates those who take care of it by issuing orders:

The interesting thing here is that we are dealing with a toy (…) that provides satisfaction precisely by behaving like a difficult child bombarding us with serious games from an apparatus perspective 23 demands. The satisfaction is provided by our being compelled to care for the object any time it wants – that is, by fulfilling its demands (…) The whole point of the game is that it always has the initiative, that the object controls the game and bombards us with demands (Žižek 1999, 107-108).

But, and this is crucial, those who take care of the Tamagotchi play this interpas- sive game under the condition of disavowal: ‘“I know very well that this is just an inanimate object, but nonetheless I act as if I believe this is a living being”’ (Žižek 1999, 107). This moment of distancing means that we can follow the Other’s or- ders while simultaneously having a critical, reflexive relation with them. Whether such a critical distance exists or needs to exist is a crucial question, as we will see in the next paragraph, in the debate about the political-ideological impact of se- rious games.

Political-ideological tendencies in serious games These three ‘virtual tendencies’, reactions toward cyberspace as developed by Ži- žek (end of Oedipus, continuation of Oedipus, and in-between interpassivity), are ‘translated’ by game researcher Caroline Pelletier into the field of the educational sciences, as I have charted in Table 2. What makes Pelletier’s approach important is that she traces these reactions in the literature about educational games. Although she specifically focuses on educational games, I would like to argue that her analysis is relevant to serious games because they have an ‘explicit and carefully thought-out educational purpose’ (Michael and Chen 2006, 21).

Žižek 1 End of Oedipus 2 Continuation of 3 In-between: 1A Dystopia 1B Utopia Oedipus interpassivity Pelletier Games as sensual Games as pain re- Games as replicas Games as dra- temptations lievers of non-virtual life matic stages for reality construc- tion

Table 2: Reactions toward cyberspace and games

According to Pelletier, elements of the so-called ‘end of Oedipus’ reaction – either its dystopian or utopian mode – can be traced in those theories which define games as ‘sensual temptations’ or as ‘pain relievers’. The games-as-sensual-temp- tations argument (see Table 2) goes like this: ‘when using games as part of class- room teaching, teachers should interrupt the play process on a regular basis to prevent students immersing themselves in the game and losing sight of the learn- ing objectives’ (Pelletier 2005, 320). As Pelletier says, ‘learning is seen to take place not through play but rather through reflection on the game’s content’

24 digital material (ibid.). At first sight this argument seems to be contradicted by those studies which show that we can learn from playing games as such (Lieberman 2006; Ritterfeld and Weber 2006). But there are other examples that show that reflec- tion on the game’s content is an important component of learning as well (Raes- sens 2007). Elements of the games-as-pain-relievers argument (see Table 2) can be traced back to the work of Mark Prensky (2001). His digital games-based learning ap- proach defines ‘active’ learning in a two-fold way: as a pleasurable and liberating activity that (1) breaks with the traditional pain of learning, and (2) gives greater agency to learners. But as Pelletier rightly argues, Prensky’s approach is mislead- ing because he is ‘challenging one form of authority in order to replace it with another – the global economy’ (Pelletier 2005, 320). What Prensky does is simply reinstating authority elsewhere: ‘So it is precisely Prensky’s playful attitude to- wards learning which initiates the supremacy of a consumer-oriented and fast- paced brand of capitalism’ (Pelletier 2005, 320). The games-as-replicas-of-non-virtual-life argument (see Table 2) deals with those theories in which the Oedipal narrative is continued by other means. What this means becomes clear in James Paul Gee’s comments on David Williamson Shaffer’s How computer games help children learn (2006). In this book Shaffer ‘shows how computer and video games can help students learn to think like engineers, urban planners, , lawyers’. Gee’s comments are in line with Pelletier’s analysis when he characterizes Shaffer as having ‘a deeply conservative vision (…) his goal is to put pressure on schools to prepare children to be productive work- ers, thoughtful members of society, and savvy citizens’ (Shaffer 2006, xii). Ac- cording to Gee and Shaffer, schools are ‘not preparing children to be innovators at the highest technical levels – the levels that will pay off most in our modern, high-tech, science-driven, global economy’ (Shaffer and Gee 2005). Their solu- tion to ‘our crisis’–the fact that the runs the risk of being over- shadowed by countries like China and India – are ‘epistemic games’ (the term is Gee and Shaffer’s). Epistemic games ‘are about having students do things that matter in the world by immersing them in rigorous professional practices of in- novation’ (ibid.). In doing so, a game player is trained to become a member of a certain community and to adopt its epistemic frame: ‘we call a community’s dis- tinctive ways of doing, valuing, and knowing its epistemic frame. We use this term because an epistemic frame ‘frames’ the way someone thinks about the world – like putting on a pair of colored glasses’ (ibid.). The meaning of the fourth argument – games-as-dramatic-stages-for-reality- construction (see Table 2) – becomes clear when we compare the playing of se- rious games to playing with a tamagotchi. When we play a serious game, according to Pelletier, the same two characteristics emerge as when we play with a Tama- gotchi. On the one hand, the game captivates the player by issuing orders: ‘Play- ing a game involves following orders; the game sets the objectives, the sequence serious games from an apparatus perspective 25 in which they are to be completed, and usually the winning conditions’ (Pelletier 2005, 322). On the other hand, playing serious games always incorporates a mo- ment of disavowal – of distancing – specific to games. ‘In playing games (…)we perform actions in the full knowledge that we are doing this within the con- straints set by someone else’ (ibid., 323). According to Pelletier, this is exactly the process on which gaming is based: ‘Because the rules are already set, the goals already decided, we can be playful around them’ (ibid.). It is useful to translate the three standard reactions towards cyberspace into the field of educational/serious game studies as Pelletier does, because it makes us understand the different ways in which the player relates to the game’s symbolic order. To decide which of these ‘virtual’ tendencies of the gaming apparatus be- come actualized in a specific situation, we have to analyze the different ways in which serious game players are positioned.

Positioning of the player In the remains of this chapter I will focus on the four different forms of player positioning: the game’s technical or material base, the game text itself, the insti- tutional and the cultural environment in which serious games are made and played. In this paragraph I will give a short description of these different ele- ments. In paragraph four I will analyze which of the four unconscious desires of the gaming apparatus are at the basis of Food Force. Finally, in paragraph five I will describe how these virtual dispositions become actualized by discussing the ways in which the game player is positioned by the game’s technology, the game texts, its institutional contexts and cultural settings. What is most striking about the technical basis of a serious game such as Food Force – a web-based, single-player PC game – is that the game player is immobi- lized yet highly active: she is sitting in a chair behind her PC with both hands occupied, one clicking and moving a mouse, the other tapping the keys of the keyboard. By using a keyboard and a mouse, the player controls the in-game ac- tions. This clicking and tapping – referred to as a form of ‘functional interactivity; or utilitarian participation’ (Salen and Zimmerman 2004, 59) – is, as I will discuss later on, more or less complemented by three other forms of player participation: interpretation (including deconstruction), reconfiguration, and construction (Raessens 2005). We also have to take into account how the player of the game is addressed or positioned both by the game text itself (Casetti) and the institutional context (Odin) in which the game is played. When we define a pragmatic approach as one that takes into account the role of the spectator (in film studies) or the player (in game studies), we can characterize textual positioning as an ‘immanent’ and contextual positioning as an ‘extrinsic’ form of pragmatics (Simons 1995, 210). The immanent film pragmatist Franceso Casetti develops three fundamental prin-

26 digital material ciples: ‘that the film signals the presence of the spectator; that it assigns a position to him/her; that it makes him follow an itinerary’ (cited in Buckland and Simons 1995, 115). Extrinsic film pragmatist Roger Odin, on the other hand, is of the opinion that a film spectator is primarily subjected to social institutions. A read- ing of a film ‘does not result from an internal [textual] constraint, but from a cultural constraint’ (Odin 1995, 213). Last but not least, we also have to take into account the cultural settings in which games are made (Jenkins). Since they are mutually constitutive, the concept of ‘interpassivity’ runs the same risk as ‘interactivity’, namely that the cultural aspects of media are neglected. As Jenkins rightly argues, ‘interactivity is a prop- erty of technologies; participation refers to what the culture does with these new media resources’ (Jenkins 2007). So, serious games scholars should focus not only on how serious games bring about a critical, reflexive relation towards their content – as Pelletier suggests in her analysis of ‘interpassivity’–but also on the two seemingly contradictory trends that are shaping the current media landscape:

On the one hand, new media technologies have lowered production and dis- tribution costs, expanded the range of available delivery channels, and enabled consumers to archive, annotate, appropriate, and re-circulate media content. At the same time, there has been an alarming concentration of the ownership of mainstream commercial media, with a small handful of multinational med- ia conglomerates dominating all sectors of the entertainment industry (Jenkins 2007).

What makes Jenkins’s position interesting is that he avoids both an attitude of refusal and an attitude of blind acceptance toward the cultural industries but opts for, as Žižek does, a position ‘in-between’: an open, negotiating relation in which consumers demand a share of by appropriating its content for their own purposes.

Virtual tendencies in Food Force Food Force (2005, www.food-force.com) was released by the United Nations World Food Programme (WPF) with children aged eight to thirteen as its target group. The game, which takes approximately thirty minutes to play, tells the story of a food crisis on the fictitious island of Sheylan. When we look more closely at the four unconscious desires both Žižek and Pelletier refer to, it seems to be a contra- dictio in terminis to think that serious games in general, and Food Force in particular, would be able or willing to put an end to Oedipus, that is, keep the player from entering the symbolic order of the game. This means that both the games-as- sensual-temptation argument and the games-as-pain-reliever argument turn out to be foreign to the seriousness of these games. That does not mean, however, serious games from an apparatus perspective 27 that Pelletier’s reflections on both tendencies are useless here. The games-as-sen- sual-temptation argument makes clear that not only the playing of the game but also the reflection on the gaming experience are an important component of learning as well. I will discuss this element later on in this chapter. The games- as-pain-reliever argument makes us aware of the risks of what Vance Packard once labeled a ‘hidden persuader’ (1984). Claiming that the gamer is in control, as theorists often do, can hide a specific symbolic order from view in which the gamer is inscribed when playing the game, as is the case in Prensky’s argument mentioned earlier. What we finally need to decide is whether the playing of se- rious games, such as Food Force, leads to a ‘continuation of Oedipus’ or to an interpassive relationship with it. Let’s first look at the ‘continuation of Oedipus’. To analyze which symbolic order the player enters when playing Food Force, I recall Shaffer and Gee’s refer- ence to the game’s epistemic frame that ‘“frames” the way someone thinks about the world – like putting on a pair of colored glasses’ (Shaffer and Gee 2005). To understand how this process works, George Lakoff’s concepts of ‘framing’ and ‘metaphor’ are useful here. According to Lakoff, metaphors frame our under- standing of the world. In order to increase our understanding of Food Force’s symbolic order, it is pro- ductive to approach it from a ‘family values’ perspective. According to Lakoff, ‘we all have a metaphor for the nation as a family (…) because we usually understand large social groups, like nations, in terms of small ones, like families or commu- nities’ (Lakoff 2004, 5). Food Force tries to persuade its players to adopt ‘a [Demo- cratic, progressive] nurturant parent family model’ (ibid., 6). According to the metaphor of the nurturant parent, ‘in foreign policy the role of the nation should be to promote cooperation and extend these values to the world’ (ibid., 40) and to focus on ‘international institutions and strong defensive and peacekeeping forces’ (ibid., 63). Caring and responsibility equal ‘caring about and acting responsibility for the world’s people; world health, hunger, poverty (…) rights for women, chil- dren (…) refugees, and ethnic minorities’ (ibid., 92). This metaphor goes against the metaphor of the [Republican, conservative] strict father family frame that, in foreign affairs, leads to the following: ‘The government should maintain its sov- ereignty and impose its moral authority everywhere it can, while seeking its self- interest (the economic self-interest of corporations and military strength)’ (ibid., 41). Because Food Force represents the United Nations World Food Programme as an organization able to – literally –‘nurture’ its family members, this game ex- presses the values and lets the player enter the symbolic order of the nurturant parent family frame. Secondly, to analyze the interpassive aspects of playing Food Force, we have to focus on the moment of disavowal – or distancing – that is specific to games, according to Pelletier. We need to answer the question of whether playing serious games entails a critical, reflexive relation towards these games. That means we

28 digital material must take a closer look at the three interpretative participatory strategies that may be activated in the player as a reaction to what Sherry Turkle calls the seduction of simulation (1996): players can surrender to the seduction of Food Force by inter- preting the game more or less according to the encoded UN-ideological frames (simulation resignation). Or they may understand these frames by demystifying or deconstructing the assumptions or frames that are built into the simulation (si- mulation understanding). Or they can completely disavow the social and political importance of these kinds of games (simulation denial). These three strategies do, indeed, determine the reactions of players and critics of both games. On the Water Cooler Games forum, for example, games critic and forum editor Gonzalo Frasca resigns to the seduction of Food Force when he writes: ‘Finally! An educational game that rocks! Informative, well produced and very enjoyable to play with. Go United Nations! (…) Overall, I am extremely happy for this game, it is an excellent example of the way edutainment should be’ (www. watercoolergames.org/archives/000381.shtml). Simulation denial and under- standing are clearly in the minority. On the same forum, some players deny Food Force’s importance by criticizing the UN for spending money on digital game de- velopment while thousands starve. Others criticize the built-in assumptions of Food Force because the game does not refer to forms of misconduct by UN person- nel: ‘How much like the real UN is it?’ What these reactions show is that it is, indeed, possible for players and critics to have the kind of critical, reflexive relation to these games described by Žižek and Pelletier. But looking through and exposing the hidden, naturalized, ideolo- gically colored rules of serious games is, however, not commonplace. Players of Food Force seem to be more superficial than both Žižek and Pelletier hope for, at least when we define superficiality as the surface of the game’s Oedipal, symbolic order as opposed to the in-depth process of deconstruction.

Player positioning by technology, text and context Let’s first look at player positioning by technology. Players of Food Force are posi- tioned by the game’s technology. We can think of the following assets: the game is accessible through the Internet; the game can be played for free; the game’s provides access to activist tools and offers the player all kinds of back- ground information. Because Food Force is a web-based, single-player PC game, it does not offer multi-user environments in its game play, maybe because of finan- cial restrictions. The game lacks a ‘constructive’ mode of participation in the sense that players are denied the possibility of game modification. The dominant mode of participation in Food Force is ‘reconfiguration’: ‘the exploration of the un- known, in the computer game represented worlds’ (Raessens 2005, 380). Secondly, I would like to look at player positioning by text. Paraphrasing Case- tti, the analysis of player positioning by the game itself must focus on three ele- serious games from an apparatus perspective 29 ments: how the game signals the presence of the player; how it assigns him a posi- tion; how it makes him follow an itinerary. In the virtual world of Food Force, the player is assigned a position that can be described as a first-person point of view on the game’s world: he is required to adopt a minimal degree of characterization, that is the young rookie addressed by the game as ‘you’. In the beginning of the game, this young rookie is briefed by a man called Carlos on a humanitarian crisis on the fictitious island Sheylan in the Indian Ocean (see Figure 1).

Figure 1: Carlos’s briefing

It is the player’s mission to deliver food as quickly as possible to Sheylan’s resi- dents. Guided by a team of experts, in a race against the , the player has to accomplish six missions or mini-games in a linear order, delivering food to an area in crisis. In the first mission, for example, the player has to pilot a helicopter over a crisis zone in Sheylan to locate the hungry (see Figure 2). The basic rule of Food Force is an ideologically motivated one: players win the game by completing the six missions and, in doing so, help to fight hunger. The goal of the game is directly conveyed to the player: ‘You can learn to fight hunger (…) Millions of people are now depending on you for help. This is more than just a game. Good luck!’ Players receive positive feedback on their performance from team members if their missions are successful. At those moments, the game sig- nals the presence of the player. If the mission fails, the player is encouraged to try again. After playing the game, a player can summit his or her final score to a worldwide high score list on the game’s website. Though the game does not have real-life consequences for the player, he is constantly reminded of the fact that in real life the WFP missions have huge consequences for these hungry people.

30 digital material Figure 2: Mission 1, Air Surveillance

Next, the player positioning by context is important. In line with Odin’s ‘extrinsic’ form of pragmatics and Jenkins’s model of convergence culture, we have to take into account that players of Food Force are also addressed or positioned by the institutional context or cultural setting in which this game is played. Three aspects of this institutional context or cultural setting are important. Firstly, the game is played in the context of a website that provides the player with background information about the social issues these games deal with. The Food Force website provides the player with information about the reality behind the game: ‘In the world today hundreds of millions of people suffer from chronic hunger and malnutrition.’ Furthermore, the player can learn about WPF’s mission to fight hunger worldwide and learn how he can actively support the WFP activ- ities outside the game world. Players can help by giving money to the WFP, by teaching others about famine, and by organizing fundraising activities at school or at home. Secondly, the game is often played in the context of a classroom situation. On the Food Force website, teachers can find all the information they need for the use of the game as a classroom tool for teaching about hunger. From a pragmatic perspective, both elements can be seen as a framework of cul- tural constraints that regulates the players’ understanding of these games and thereby helps them entering the games’ symbolic order. Thirdly, as part of today’s media transformations, organizations are increasingly able to produce their own games outside the main gaming industry (also as a form of construction), and serious games from an apparatus perspective 31 players are enabled to use the activist tools woven into the game’s website. The fact that Food Force succeeds in raising issues that the mass- media do not always consider newsworthy shows the relevance of this game.

Conclusions In this chapter I have examined how the functioning and function of serious games are ideologically colored. The functioning of serious games concerns the different forms of player positioning that contribute to the production of mean- ing. To be able to study the functioning of serious games, I have introduced the concept of the gaming apparatus. The advantage or productivity of using this concept within game studies is that it helps to articulate the understanding of the production of meaning as deeply influenced by the ways in which configurations of technology, user positioning, desire, media text and context take shape in spe- cific games. I have questioned the function of serious games by analyzing the ‘if’ and ‘how’ of the player’s entry into the game’s symbolic order. I have described the four kinds of unconscious desires –‘virtual’ tendencies in Žižek and Pelletier’s use of the term – that may or may not become actualized, depending on how the player of a specific game is positioned or addressed in or by the gaming apparatus. In Food Force, the games-as-replicas-of-non-virtual-life argument seemed to be domi- nant. The ideologically colored construction seems not to be automatically re- vealed through the mere activity of play as Pelletier suggested. Furthermore, it turned out to be almost a contradictio in terminis to presume that serious games in general and Food Force in particular would be able or willing to put an end to Oedipus, that is, to keep the player from entering the symbolic order of the game. This would mean that there seems to be little room for a critical, reflective attitude towards the game’s ideology while playing these games. Whether such a critical distance needs to exist in the first place is up for dis- cussion. It is of course a legitimate aspiration to teach children about hunger as Food Force intends to do. At the same time it is also legitimate to teach children how to understand the frames and values of which a specific serious game wants to convince its player. I agree with Turkle when she advocates the importance of an attitude of simulation understanding: ‘Understanding the assumptions that underlie simulation is a key element of political power’ (Turkle 1996, 71). It could be a task of media literacy education not only to teach children through but also about digital games. As Kurt Squire argues, ‘students might be required to critique the game and explicitly address built-in simulation biases’ (Squire 2002). The fact that in the new media landscape children are becoming participants, and not only spectators or consumers, also means that they should be aware of their ‘ethical responsibilities’ (Jenkins 2007), for example by asking ‘about the motives or accuracy of the ways games depict the world’ (ibid.) or by asking what

32 digital material kind of (ideologically colored) games they would want to design themselves. Pro- fessional serious game designers as well as serious game theorists also have an ethical-political responsibility when they make decisions about the ways in which they want to design serious games and construct theories about them. Which of the ‘virtual’ tendencies become actualized is not directly inscribed in the game’s technical properties. They are the ‘possibilities opened up by cyberspace technol- ogy, so that, ultimately, the choice is ours, the stake in a politico-ideological struggle’ (Žižek 1999, 123).

Notes 1. A longer and more elaborated version of this chapter is forthcoming in: Ritterfeld, Ute, Michael Cody and Peter Vorderer, eds. Serious games: Mechanisms and effects. New York: Routledge, Taylor and Francis (2009). 2. For a critical discussion of the Nintendo DS as mobile apparatus, see Nanna Verhoeff’s chapter in this book. 3. For an extensive discussion of the processes of persuasion in war games, see David Nieborg’s chapter.

Acknowledgements This research has been supported by the GATE project, funded by the Nether- lands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) and the Netherlands ICT Re- search and Innovation Authority (ICT Regie). I would like to thank Christien Franken for this chapter.

References Baudry, Jean-Louis. 1986a. Ideological effects of the basic cinematographic apparatus. In Narrative, apparatus, ideology, ed. Philip Rosen, 286-298. New York: Columbia University Press. Baudry, Jean-Louis. 1986b. The apparatus: Metapsychological approaches to the impres- sion of reality in the cinema. In Narrative, apparatus, ideology, ed. Philip Rosen, 299-318. New York: Columbia University Press. Buckland, Warren and Jan Simons. 2005. Introduction. In The film spectator: From sign to mind, ed. Warren Buckland, 113-117. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Deleuze, Gilles and Claire Parnet. 1996. H comme histoire de la philosophie. In L’Abécédaire de Gilles Deleuze. Paris: Vidéo Editions Montparnasse. Fuller, Mathew. 2005. Media ecologies: Materialist energies in art and technoculture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jenkins, Henri. 2007. Media literacy: Who needs it? http://www.projectnml.org/yoyogi. Lakoff, George. 2004. Don’t think of an elephant! Know your values and frame the debate. White River Junction, Vermont: Chelsea Green Publishing.

serious games from an apparatus perspective 33 Lieberman, Debra. 2006. What can we learn from playing interactive games? In Playing video games: Motives, responses, and consequences, eds. Peter Vorderer and Jennings Bryant, 379-397. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers. Michael, David and Sande Chen. 2006. Serious games: Games that educate, train, and inform. Boston, MA: Thomson. Odin, Roger. 1995. For a semio-pragmatics of film. In The film spectator: From sign to mind, ed. Warren Buckland, 213-226. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Packard, Vance. 1984. The Hidden Persuaders. New York: Pocket. Pelletier, Caroline. 2005. Reconfiguring interactivity, agency and pleasure in the education and computer games debate: Using Žižek’s concept of interpassivity to analyse educa- tional play. E-Learning (2) 4. Prensky, Mark. 2001. Digital game-based learning. New York: McGraw-Hill. Raessens, Joost. 2007. Playing history: Reflections on mobile and location-based learning. In Didactics of micro-learning: Concepts, discourses, and examples, ed. Theo Hug, 200-217. Münster: Waxmann Verlag. — 2005. Computer games as participatory media culture. In Handbook of Computer Game Studies, eds. Joost Raessens and Jeffrey Goldstein, 373-388. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ritterfeld, Ute and René Weber. 2006. Video games for entertainment and education. In Playing video games: Motives, responses, and consequences, eds. Peter Vorderer and Jennings Bryant, 399-413. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers. Salen, Katie and Eric Zimmerman. 2004. Rules of play: Game design fundamentals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Shaffer, David. 2006. How computer games help children learn. New York: Palgrave MacMillan. Shaffer, David and James Paul Gee. 2005. Before every child is left behind: How epistemic games can solve the coming crisis in education. http://epistemicgames.org. Simons, Jan. 1995. Introduction. In The film spectator: From sign to mind, ed. Warren Buck- land, 209-212. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Squire, Kurt. 2002. Cultural framing of computer/video games. http://www.gamestudies. org/0102/squire. Turkle, Sherry. 1996. Life on the screen: Identity in the age of the internet. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson. Žižek, Slavoj. 1999. Is it possible to traverse the fantasy in cyberspace? In The Žižek reader, eds. Elizabeth Wright and Edmond Wright, 102-124. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publish- ing.

34 digital material Empower yourself, defend freedom!

Playing games during times of war

David B. Nieborg

The January 2008 edition of the popular Dutch game magazine Power Unlimited featured a two-page advertisement by the Koninklijke Landmacht (Royal Dutch Army). The full color advertisement on pages two and three carried the tagline: ‘Fine leadership comes naturally.’ The left page shows soldiers pointing at a map and discussing strategy, the right page packed a lot of reading. Interestingly, the ad shows no weaponry at all and is, compared to the showy marketing material for war games, quite considerate. The underlying recruiting motive here is profes- sionalism – accepting a ranking job in the Royal Dutch Army primarily asks for management and leadership skills. Putting an ad in a game magazine is an ob- vious move, considering the shared target demographic (16- to 26-year-old boys) of both gaming magazines and army recruiters. Despite ‘a disappearing audience for war’ (Carruthers 2008), the First Person Shooter (FPS) game Call of Duty 4: Modern Warfare topped the all important 2008 holiday sales charts and has sold over nine million copies. Despite the hunger of many ‘hardcore’ gamers to experience mediated warfare, as the stunning success of Call of Duty 4 shows, the outlook for the Dutch Army, in terms of new recruits, is not at all favorable. For one thing, the Dutch involvement in the war in Afghanistan led to a number of fatal casualties, lowering the pro- pensity of Dutch youngsters to consider an army career. To aid recruiting efforts, the Dutch Army is seeking recruits at increasingly lower ages and is directly tap- ping into the fabric of game culture. At the annual Army open door days and at industry events such as game conventions, the Army set up Xbox 360 demo pods to lure gamers into their recruiting booth to play the war game Tom Clancy’sGhost Recon Advanced Warfighter 2. However, it is with a mix of envy and esteem that ranking Dutch service members look at their allies in the west. In 2006 the US Army had a whopping 3.9 billion dollar recruiting budget to spend on: ‘slick ads that reach students before they set foot on campus – in fash- ion and music magazines, free iPod downloads, MySpace campaigns, on televi- sion and hip-hop stations, and through concert and sporting even sponsor- ships’ (Allison and Solnit 2007, 46). During informal interviews with Dutch

35 service members, most of them gamers themselves, I was told that Dutch recrui- ters are particularly envious of one specific recruiting project: America’s Army. This game can be seen as the first state-produced, highly visible and popular game with an overt persuasive agenda (cf. Løvlie 2007). To label the America’s Army proj- ect as successful would be an understatement. In direct ways, by projecting the US Army brand deeply into game culture at minimal costs, and indirectly by get- ting into ‘the consideration set’ of US high school students, the project is said to have saved hundreds of millions of marketing and recruiting dollars (Nieborg 2005). The aim of this chapter is to deepen the understanding of the representation and simulation of modern war in games vis-à-vis government propaganda. There- fore, a short discussion on the Global War on Terror as a war on ideas follows first. Next, to contextualize the use of propaganda in games, the argument will be made that the theme of modern warfare is already a familiar commoditized inter- text, thereby aiding the acceptance of pro-military themes. The militarization of society and of popular culture has a long history, and war has been a familiar theme in television, movies, toys and digital and non-digital games (Regan 1994; Hall 2003). The usage of games, and America’s Army in particular, as part of wider US strategic communication efforts signals the usefulness of game culture for the dissemination of state-produced propaganda via military-operated game commu- nities (Nieborg 2006).

The America’s Army platform The America’s Army development team cleverly mixed various educational, market- ing and propaganda mechanisms at their disposal to offer a free game which on the one hand fits perfectly into the FPS genre while at the same time reinforcing a highly politicized recruiting agenda (cf. Allison and Solnit 2007).¹ The best- known version of America’s Army is its freely downloadable public version, or as version 2.8.2.1 (2008) is called America’s Army: Special Forces (Overmatch). ‘The Offi- cial US Army Game’, as it is labelled by the US Army itself, is best described as an online, multiplayer, squad-based, tactical FPS PC game. The game is distributed via various game and was developed under the auspices and with materi- al and immaterial input of the US Army. The goal of the game is to inform popu- lar culture rather than to persuade, and to raise awareness of the US Army brand rather than to recruit directly, which is done by a large group of dedicated US Army recruiters. A key component in building and maintaining both the US Army and America’s Army brand identities is the Goarmy.com website, and one of the main goals of the America’s Army project is to raise traffic to the dedicated recruit- ing website. Primarily an advanced online recruiting station, the website offers a virtual insight into an Army career. Whereas before the game launched a large number of leads to the website stemming from TV and radio advertisements, to-

36 digital material day a significant number comes from the America’s Army website and from within the game itself. Similar to the Goarmy.com website, the US Army as a possible future career is a central theme to the game’s design. Having commerce at the core of its brand identity, the PC game exemplifies the linkage of commercial goals with a cultural text through creating an engaging (brand) experience (Van der Graaf and Nieborg 2003). Along with a PC version, the America’s Army brand has been expanded since its introduction on 4 July 2002 by publishing the Xbox game America’s Army: Rise of a Soldier (2005), a Xbox 360 version called America’s Army: True Soldiers (2007), and the game America’s Army: Special Operations (2007). In addition, dedi- cated fans can buy America’s Army action figures, apparel or other knickknacks on armygamegear.com, or seek out an America’s Army cabinet in an arcade hall. Over the years the PC version of America’s Army has become more of a platform than one single and stable game within the US Army. Or as the official website explains: ‘The America’s Army “Platform” (AAP) is a government-owned core technology and content infrastructure designed to support existing warfighters, instructors & students through a new generation of low cost, PC-based, web-de- ployable, interactive training’ (US Army 2005). This set of non-public governmen- tal applications was built by specialized sub-groups of in-house game developers in cooperation with commercial game studios and US Army researchers. Together they use advanced, commercial, off-the-shelf game technology to develop various training tools (e.g. for land navigation), and modeling and simulation applica- tions (e.g. weapon testing), used by various US governmental organizations, such as the US Secret Service. The proprietary Unreal game engine, developed by the US-based Epic Games game development company, affords the Army a perpe- tually updated and versatile platform to provide high-fidelity simulations. By analyzing the production, distribution, and use of both the governmental and public version of America’s Army, four different dimensions can be distin- guished. The America’s Army Platform can be seen as an advergame, an edugame, a test bed and tool, and a propaganda game.² The edugame and test tool dimen- sion are most apparent in several governmental applications, while the public version encompasses all four dimensions. Hereafter only the public use of the PC version of America’s Army will be discussed. The adaptive character of contempo- rary game technology enables game developers to design multidimensional PC games, such as America’s Army, moving beyond ‘mere entertainment’. This begs the question: Is America’s Army a form of propaganda? If so, how does it function as a propaganda tool within the vast US military complex? And, how does its propaganda message manifest itself in the representation and simulation of war in the game? Whether or not America’s Army ‘works’ as intended, or whether it is, in the eyes of its players, a symbol of rampant American imperialism or a new form of camp is a highly relevant question, but falls outside the scope of this

empower yourself, defend freedom! 37 chapter. Next, the notion of soft power is introduced to expand upon the interplay between popular culture and propaganda.

Digital games as soft power That infamous September morning in New York, the world changed the moment the first airplane hit the Twin Towers. The US was at war. Les Brownlee, former Acting Secretary of the Army, and General Peter J. Schoomaker, Chief of Staff of the US Army, emphasize the long-term character of the current war:

This is not simply a fight against terror – terror is a tactic. This is not simply a fight against al Qaeda, its affiliates, and adherents – they are foot soldiers. This is not simply a fight to bring democracy to the Middle East – that is a strategic objective. This is a fight for the very ideas at the foundation of our society, the ways of life those ideas enable, and the freedoms we enjoy (Brown- lee and Schoomaker, 2004).

According to US government officials, such as former US Defense Secretary Rumsfeld, the Global War on Terror (or GWOT) is not only a war on ‘stateless criminals’ but also a seemingly endless war on ideas (Taylor 2008). It is a war to spread freedom and liberty – i.e. values appropriated by and associated with the United States (Nye 2004). The handling of the ongoing wars in Afghanistan and Iraq, however, has had devastating results for the image of US foreign policy: ‘The war has increased mistrust of America in Europe, weakened support for the War on Terrorism, and undermined US credibility worldwide’ (Defense Science Board 2004, 15). This trend of the US’s slipping global image and dwindling sup- port for the GWOT is backed by the polling data of the Pew Research Center (2006). They conclude that although the values such as freedom and democracy, as well as free market capitalism, are shared around the world, the Bush-Cheney White House’s handling of the war effort is seen as the main reason for the de- creasing support of the US-led GWOT (Hersh 2004; Woodward 2006). The question is then, how? How are anti-American attitudes to be altered? In his book Power, terror, peace, and war: America’s grand strategy in a world at risk, foreign relations expert Walter Russell Mead (2004) reflects on this question and dis- cusses the changing role of the US as a superpower. In his opening chapter he addresses the almost messianic role of American grand strategy, to spread peace, freedom and liberty around the world using various forms of power. Mead builds on Joseph Nye’s (2002) distinction between hard and soft power, offering two sub-categories for both. Hard (military and economical) power is split up into sharp (military) and sticky (economical) power, and soft power (cultural power) is split up in hegemonic and sweet power.³ As comic books and Coca-Cola are part of the US’s sweet power, so are games, movies and television series. Accord-

38 digital material ing to Mead and Nye the GWOT cannot be won by hard power alone, you need soft power as well: ‘In any case, American sweet power, though limited and vari- able, clearly plays an important role in winning sympathy and support for Amer- ican foreign policy around the world’ (Mead 2004, 39-40). Soft power is not un- der government control like propaganda is, and has limits, just as military power does. But, as I will argue hereafter, America’sArmyis not only a propaganda tool, it is a powerful example of the ability of the US to successfully wield soft power by directly tapping into popular culture.

The military entertainment arcade If foreign relations experts are to be believed, anti-American attitudes are not only a direct threat to US national security, they also undermine the sole surviving superpower’s soft power. Since soft power is mostly manufactured by commercial enterprises, it will be no surprise that the US military is eager to appropriate such valuable practices. The Defense Science Board (2004) directly points to the private sector with its expert knowledge when it comes to successfully getting across messages with an agenda. One way to do this is by using ‘interactive and mediated channels’, because ‘pervasive technology permits the cost effective engagement of target audiences in sustained two-way interac- tions using electronic mail, interactive dialogue, virtual communication, interac- tive video games, and interactive Internet games’ (ibid, 57-8). As such, online games are to be used for the US effort. And why not, the sweet power of many military themed games seems stronger than anything else. Think of recent exam- ples such as Battlefield 2 (2006), Call of Duty 4: Modern Warfare (2007), and Tom Clancy’s Ghost Recon Advanced Warfighter 2 (2007). How has this come to be? The US military and the global game culture are profoundly interlinked on a technical, cultural and social-economic level, and the representation and simula- tion of modern war in computer games are at the same time a result as well as a catalyst of this bond (Halter 2006). The technological symbiosis between games for entertainment and military simulations has a long shared history. With the end of the Cold War, the structure of the US military and the way US forces would wage future wars changed dramatically (Toffler and Toffler 1995). Simulta- neously, the research and development into modelling and simulation techniques flourished in the commercial entertainment industries. The booming innovation of commercial simulation technology did not go unnoticed by the US military, and the vast and influential military-industrial complex transformed into the mili- tary-entertainment complex. The reach of the military-entertainment complex is beyond the technical realm of simulation technology. Co-developed films, televi- sion series, toys, and various other entertainment products are direct outputs of the complex (Hall 2003; Robb 2004).

empower yourself, defend freedom! 39 The representation and simulation of modern warfare in games demonstrate that there is already a common understanding about digital war (Nieborg 2005). Think of the many conventions in the FPS genre such as the fetishism of weap- onry and the focus on combat (at close quarters). The US Army does not have to make an expensive movie or produce their own television series; they are able to directly tap into existing technological and socio-economical frameworks of the military-entertainment complex, and above all the military masculinity of certain parts of game culture. The Army can harness the collaborative nature of online game communities and use them to their advantage: spreading the Army’s sym- bolic capital (Van der Graaf and Nieborg 2003). Gamers are familiar or at least not surprised by another Army game, since military advisers decorated the box shots of commercial games for over a long time. Modern warfare, similar to the Harry Potter or Lord of the Rings franchises for example, has become an intertextual experiential commodity, and the need for simulations of war is omnipresent in today’s youth popular culture. A global gaming culture, with its military origins of interactive play, is entertained by games primarily based on conflict, eagerly developed by young males for young males (Kline, Dyer-Witheford and De Peuter 2003).

Empower yourself! Defend freedom Short and simple, America’s Army is a form of propaganda. At least, following the definition in the Department of Defense Dictionary of Military and Associated Terms in which propaganda is defined as: ‘Any form of communication in support of na- tional objectives designed to influence the opinions, emotions, attitudes, or beha- vior of any group in order to benefit the sponsor, either directly or indirectly’ (Department of Defense 2004, 427). Propaganda is thus a message with a clear intention, known in advance by its sender, meant to influence behavior. As stated, America’s Army’s four dimensions make it a fairly unique game. Three of its four dimensions show an interesting overlap, as propaganda, advertisement and edu- cation have much in common. The multidimensional approach of the America’s Army project leads to two coinciding ‘persuasive goals’ (Bogost 2007). The first and most vivid is its recruiting agenda. The second rhetorical goal concerns the game’s opaque ideology of war: ‘as a manifestation of the ideology that propels the U.S. Army, the game encourages players to consider the logic of duty, honor, and singular global political truth as a desirable worldview’ (Bogost 2007, 79). While America’s Army is first and foremost a sophisticated marketing tool, it also (literally) teaches gamers what it means, or at least should mean, to be a US sol- dier. America’s Army’s main design principle is to create a virtual replica of certain aspects of life in the US Army, mainly those involving combat. As an important institution in the American society, the US Army directly and indirectly represents

40 digital material the values of this society and its government. And as a copy of the US Army, the game reflects US foreign policy. The loading screen of the game features the Sol- dier’s Creed and before joining any online round, players get to see the creed tell- ing them: ‘I am a Warrior and a member of a team. I serve the people of the United States and live the Army Values,’ culminating in, ‘I stand ready to deploy, engage, and destroy the enemies of the United States of America in close combat. I am a guardian of freedom and the American way of life. I am an American Soldier.’ It seems almost like a virtual contract. When the game is ready, the load- ing screen disappears, and the player temporarily joins the virtual US Army. Propaganda does not equal lying or deceiving. Far from it, the most effective forms of propaganda are factually accurate for the greater part. It is the context of a message which turns opinions and world views into information (Taylor 1998). As with the above-mentioned Royal Dutch Army’s advertisement, America’s Army’s rhetorical strategies actually accentuate modesty and responsibility and are based on the US Army’s take on morality. Drawing on computer game theory, Løvlie (2007) emphasizes three rhetorical strategies underlying America’s Army’s per- suasive agenda: the strategy of identification, that of authenticity, and that of le- gitimization (cf. Nieborg, 2005). Let’s consider these strategies more in depth. One of the ways America’s Army aims to influence the attitudes of gamers is by showing that the use of violence by the US Army is justified because freedom has to be defended. In addition, players are taught that the US Army is a professional organization, based on the US Army values – Loyalty, Duty, Respect, Selfless Ser- vice, Honor, Integrity, and Personal Courage (LDRSHIP). To put these values into context, America’s Army appropriates the format of the FPS genre and recontextua- lizes common in-game player actions previously devoid of any political or ideolo- gical connotation. For many gamers the sheer joy of playing tactical FPS games comes from playing as a team. The US Army skilfully refurbishes conventional player actions such as teamplaying by labeling them as value-laden expressions. By offering an ‘authentic’ combat simulation, the Army provides a game space where Army values become more explicit. A vivid example of this mechanism comes from the first lecture during ‘medic training’, part of the single player edugame dimension. Sitting behind a desk in a classroom, the player a virtual drill sergeant boom:

In many cases, you will be risking your own life in a selfless way to provide first-aid. You are doing what’s right, and showing personal courage, both phy- sically and morally. By performing first aid, we are living up to the Army value of honor, because saving a human life brings honor to yourselves and to the United States Army.

In his critique of the many ‘myths of war’ Hedges argues: ‘The hijacking of lan- guage is fundamental to war’ (2002, 34). Common in-game actions, such as nur- empower yourself, defend freedom! 41 turing, self-sacrifice and acts of heroism, are assigned a new purpose in the game by designating Army values to them, such as ‘loyalty’, ‘selfless-service’ and ‘per- sonal courage’. America’s Army propagates the US Army ethos and through this, the rationale and legitimation of US foreign policy. An abrupt break with FPS design conventions is the change in point of view. The game’s point of view is, by means of a software trick, limited to that of an American soldier, setting the game apart from all other, that is commercial, FPS games. Whereas you can choose to be a German, British, American or Russian soldier in the multiplayer segments of almost every World War Two shooter out there, you cannot play one of the ‘Opposing Forces’ in America’sArmy. Just as news reporters used ‘we’ and ‘us’ to bend the complex logic of war into the more streamlined ideology of ‘good-versus-evil’ (Taylor 1998), ‘we’ and ‘us’ in America’s Army always stands for the US Army. Make no mistake, in America’s Army you are always ‘with us/US’. It is one of the oldest and most common propaganda tricks in the book, limiting the point of view in order to vilify and obscure the enemy (Toffler and Toffler 1995). The acceptance of the role as an US soldier is never really questioned on the game’s official forum, and debates asking for different roles – i.e. to play a terror- ist – are virtually nonexistent. Many gamers are aware of the fact that they per- form two roles – i.e. functioning as ‘double-bound warriors’. An American soldier towards oneself and towards your team, you see your own hands holding an American weapon. At the same time you are, in the eyes of your opponent, one of the opposing forces. The ‘terrorist’ perspective from popular FPS games such as Counter-Strike is lost to reinstate the only ‘right’ point of view. In short, the game shows how the US Army fights and why. The ‘Why?’ ques- tion is made explicit offline in the official 224-page America’s Army game manual stating: ‘while tactical movement and are often essential to the success of a mission, the US Army exists to defend freedom, and employing force in combat is an important element of their job’ (Tran 2003, 36). In this case, lethal force is justified as a legitimate state action: ‘The rules and definitions of violent force are dangerously fluid and arbitrary. By mediating the definitions of violence, nation states have the ability to shield their own uses of force from cen- sure and, furthermore, to manipulate representations of their uses of force to inspire citizens’ (Hall 2003, 27). In America’sArmythe sole justification to use lethal force is to empower oneself in order to defend freedom.

The role of strategic communication The ongoing GWOT calls for more soldiers and thus more recruits. The second Gulf War in particular has put heavy strains on the available manpower of the Army. However, while America’s Army may be a legitimate branding tool and re- cruiting aid within the US, being available worldwide conflicts with the games’

42 digital material recruitment goals. The FAQ section on the official website explains why someone outside the US can play America’s Army for free: ‘We want the whole world to know how great the US Army is’ (US Army 2007). Deliberately choosing to make the game accessible for gamers worldwide challenges the original goal of recruit- ment. Which other national army has the financial means to develop and distri- bute a free high-tech PC game? Being a free, highly advanced, and frequently updated game with the simulation of hard power, America’s Army becomes part of the US’ soft power. How then, as a form of sweet power, does America’s Army fit in the overall stra- tegic media use of the US government? The developers do not explicitly frame the game as a recruiting tool or an advergame, but as a ‘strategic communication tool’ (Davis 2004). In this paragraph the concept of strategic communication as it is used within the US military will be linked to America’s Army. Although the next definition does not directly include America’s Army, or any other video game in particular, it gives a valuable insight into the rationale of using strategic commu- nication:

(...) strategic communication describes a variety of instruments used by gov- ernments for generations to understand global attitudes and cultures, engage in a dialogue of ideas between people and institutions, advise policymakers, diplomats, and military leaders on the public opinion implications of policy choices, and influence attitudes and behavior through communications strate- gies (Defense Science Board 2004, 11).

The emphasis on influencing attitudes and behavior aligns strategic communica- tion with propaganda. The renewed attention to the role of strategic communica- tion within the US defense community is a direct result of the GWOT. The US Government uses four instruments to deploy strategic communication: public diplomacy, public affairs, international broadcasting services, and infor- mation operations. Toffler and Toffler discuss the different levels of strategy ‘at which the military propaganda game’, i.e. strategic communication, ‘is played’ (1995, 194). Information Operations, also known within the US military as Psy- chological Operations (PSYOPS), are used at the tactical level of strategy through radio transmissions, leaflets, or television broadcasts aimed at foreigners in order to influence their behavior. In an advice to the former US Secretary of Defense regarding ‘the creation and dissemination of all forms of information in support of [PSYOPS] in time of military conflict’, the Defense Science Board discusses the use of ‘other media types’ for PSYOPS:

A number of other media types, and means of dissemination, are also widely popular. Video games are perhaps the most popular. They can be disseminated by a number of techniques, ranging from diskettes to web downloads. Internet empower yourself, defend freedom! 43 games allow a number of geographically dispersed players to participate in a large, shared virtual space. (...) All are suitable for PSYOP in some situations (2004, 43).

While currently America’s Army is not directly used on the battlefield as a tactical PSYOPS tool, it just may become one in the future as public opinion will become an increasingly important factor in ‘The Long Information War’ (Taylor 2008). Two other components of strategic communication, public diplomacy and pub- lic affairs, are two aspects of strategic communication which are more directly related to the use of America’s Army. Public diplomacy is an interactive way to in- form foreigners about US culture, values and policy (e.g. by offering scholarships, official websites in various languages, and televised interviews with ambassadors and military commanders). As discussed before, America’s Army explicitly commu- nicates various values, policies and views on US (military) culture. By doing so, America’s Army has become so much more than just a free downloadable game, it forms part of the US public diplomacy effort. In times where the US’s interna- tional public standing is in disarray, the success of America’s Army justifies the expansion of the America’s Army brand into global popular culture. In its role as a strategic communication tool, the game and its many spinoffs may turn out to be the cheapest weapon in the US arsenal ever conceived. As with any weapon of war, however, there is ‘collateral damage’. In this case it is the subsequent mili- tarization of popular culture and the politization of game culture.

Conclusion America’s Army goes beyond branding and marketing when it disseminates US Army ideology and thus indirectly US foreign policy into a global popular culture. By showing a global audience why and how the US Army fights, the game has become an example of public diplomacy through the exchange of ‘ideas to build lasting relationships and receptivity to a nation’s culture, values, and policies’ (Defense Science Board 2004, 12). It even may be classified as a psychological operation, being a ‘military activity’ using selected information and indicators ‘to influence the attitudes and behavior’ of ‘groups, and individuals in support of military and national security objectives’ (ibid, 13). Media have become instru- ments of war; an army may win a battle on the tactical level, but lose on the strategic level, and thus lose the entire war by a lack of public support: ‘Wars that lose their mythic stature for the public, such as Korea and Vietnam, are doomed to failure, for war is exposed for what it is – organized murder’ (Hedges 2002, 21). In the wake of the ubiquitously criticized war in Iraq, America’s Army’s simple slogans and cliché good-versus-evil dichotomy reifies the ‘myth of war’ as a his- torical inevitable and justified state operation.

44 digital material In a similar vein Toffler and Toffler argue that future warfare ‘will take place on the media battlefield’ (1995, 194). However, various are still wary of direct Pentagon intrusion (Taylor 1998). In this light, games such as America’s Army seem like highly suitable propaganda tools. In the end, rather than embed- ding a camera crew or censoring Hollywood scripts, the highly sanitized view on war in America’s Army is constructed by the US Army itself. America’s Army shows non-US citizens that the US Army is a highly trained, professional force, willing to fight against ‘those who oppose freedom’ and does so in an interactive dialogue with gamers through both the game and its community. In addition, as a bypro- duct of using the format of a technologically advanced free FPS game, America’s Army adds to the US’ soft power as a strategic communication tool. By employing a discourse of authenticity in its marketing efforts, the US Army uses/misuses its institutional discursive power to market their game to a group of gamers who have never experienced real combat – i.e. teens. From a skilfully de- signed first-person viewpoint, a specific ideological perspective on the GWOT reaches the hearts and minds of a global youth culture. Entertainment has always been an indispensable element in the propagandist’s toolbox. For many, America’s Army is a legitimate model of how to use soft power to win a war on ideas. The Defense Science Board (2004) is clear about the role for the wider military-enter- tainment complex; its many military contractors should be ordered to develop even more vehicles, that is military games, for the dissemination of US soft power. As such, the unrelenting success of America’s Army has serious implications for thinking about the use of games for advertisement, education, and most of all, state-produced propaganda.

Notes 1. For a critical discussion of the ideological implications of educational games, see the chapter by Joost Raessens in this book. 2. See Nieborg (2005) for an overview and a detailed analysis of America’s Army’s four di- mensions. 3. Hegemonic power is the interplay of sharp, sticky, and sweet power making: ‘Some- thing as artificial and arbitrary, historically speaking, as the American world system since World War II looks natural, desirable, inevitable and permanent. So, at least, we hope’ (Mead 2004, 25).

References Allison, Aimee, and David Solnit. 2007. Army of none: Strategies to counter military recruitment, end war and build a better world. New York: Seven Stories Press. Bogost, Ian. 2007. Persuasive games: The expressive power of videogames. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Brownlee, Les, and Peter J. Schoomaker. 2004. Serving a nation at war: A campaign quality army with joint and expeditionary capabilities. Parameters 34 (2). empower yourself, defend freedom! 45 Carruthers, Susan L. 2008. No one’s looking: The disappearing audience for war. Media, War & Conflict 1 (1): 70-76. Davis, Margaret, ed. 2004. America’s Army pc game vision and realization. San Francisco: US Army and the Moves Institute. Defense Science Board. 2004. Report of the defense science board task force on strategic communica- tion. Washington, DC: Office of the Under Secretary of Defense For Acquisition, Tech- nology, and Logistics. Department of Defense. 2004. Department of defense dictionary of military and associated terms. Washington DC: Department of Defense. Hall, Karen J. 2003. War games and imperial postures: Spectacles of combat in US popular culture, 1942-2001. PhD Thesis. Syracuse University. Halter, Ed. 2006. From Sun Tzu to xbox: War and video games. New York: Thunder’s Mouth Press. Hedges, Chris. 2002. War is a force that gives us meaning. New York: PublicAffairs. Hersh, Seymour. 2004. Chain of command: The road from 9/11 to Abu Ghraib. London: Harper- Collins. Kline, Stephen, Nick Dyer-Witheford and Greig de Peuter. 2003. Digital play: The interaction of technology, culture, and marketing. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. Løvlie, Anders Sundnes. 2007. The rhetoric of persuasive games: Freedom and discipline in America’s Army. Master thesis. University of Oslo. Mead, Walter Russell. 2004. Power, terror, peace and war: America’s grand strategy in a world at risk. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Nieborg, David B. 2005. Changing the rules of engagement: Tapping into the popular culture of America’s Army, the official US army computer game. Master thesis. Utrecht University. http://www.gamespace.nl/thesis. Nieborg, David B. 2006. Mods, nay! Tournaments, yay! The appropriation of contemporary game culture by the US military. Fibreculture Journal 4 (8). http://journal.fibreculture.org/ issue8/issue8_nieborg.html. Nye, Joseph S. 2002. The paradox of American power: Why the world’s only superpower can’tgoit alone. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nye, Joseph S. 2004. Soft power: The means to success in world politics. New York: PublicAffairs. Pew Research Center for the People & the Press. 2006. No global warming alarm in the U.S., China: America’s image slips, but allies share U.S. concerns over Iran, Hamas. Washington, DC. Regan, Patrick. M. 1994. War toys, war movies, and the militarization of the United States, 1900-85. Journal of Peace Research 31 (1): 45-58. Robb, David. 2004. Operation Hollywood: How the Pentagon shapes and censors the movies. Am- herst, NY: Prometheus Books. Taylor, Philip M. 1998. War and the media – Propaganda and persuasion in the Gulf War. 2nd ed. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Taylor, Philip M. 2008. Can the information war on terror be won? A polemical essay. Media, War & Conflict 1 (1): 118-124. Toffler, Alvin, and Heidi Toffler. 1995. War and anti-war (Making sense of today’s global chaos). New York: Warner Books. Tran, Nam ‘DocNartman’. 2003. America’s Army version 2.0 Training manual. Army Game Project.

46 digital material US Army. 2005. America’s Army platform: Technology. http://info.americasarmy.com/technol- ogy.php. US Army. 2007. America’s Army: Special Forces – Support – Frequently Asked Questions. 2007. Americasarmy.com. http://www.americasarmy.com/support/faqs.php?t=3&z=12#12. US Army. 2008. America’s Army: Special Forces (Overmatch). US Army. Van der Graaf, Shenja, and David Nieborg. 2003. Together we brand: America’s Army. In Level up: Digital games research conference, eds. Marinka Copier and Joost Raessens. Utrecht: Utrecht University: 324-38. Woodward, Bob. 2006. State of denial: Bush at war, part III. New York: Simon & Schuster.

empower yourself, defend freedom! 47

Formatted spaces of participation

Interactive television and the changing relationship between production and consumption

Eggo Müller

As has occurred before within the history of emerging media, the advent of digital media and the generated two opposing discourses on the social and cultural effects of the new media: one utopian and one dystopian. The more prevalent utopian discourse proclaims the revolutionary transformation of mass media into a truly democratic mediascape: one in which old and new media con- verge; where users do not merely consume pre-fabricated media content pas- sively, but themselves become interactive producers and distributors of media content; and a location where creative ideas and knowledge are mutually shared online by ordinary people: ‘[T]he interactive (…) is about using power- ful tools to create our own educational and entertainment experiences rather than passively accepting that which is fed to us by so-called experts. It is about the dissolution of boundaries and the translation of all thought into a common voca- bulary. Binary code is the digital Esperanto that is leading concurrently to individ- ual empowerment and worldwide unity’ (Pierce 1997, xvii). This McLuhanian approach to New Media, though rather extreme in its word- ing, remains characteristic of much contemporary theorizing about digital med- ia’s ‘participatory culture’. The differences between ‘old’ and ‘new’ media are ex- aggerated in order to praise digital technology’s ability to overcome modernity’s separation between the realms of production and consumption, and thus to cre- ate empowering forms of communication and cultural participation. Whereas in- dustrial and economic discourses describe this process as the advent of the ‘pro- sumer’ (Toffler 1980, 282ff.; Tapscott 1996, 62f.; Tapscott/Williams 2006, 124ff.), the scholarly discourse declaims a ‘participatory turn in culture’ and ‘the blurring of boundaries between the categories of production and consumption’ (Uricchio 2004, 139). Online networks such as Napster, Slashdot, or serve as the chief witnesses of this ‘participatory turn’ in our media culture, in which the con- sumer gains control over the production and distribution of media content.1

49 In opposition to this approach and less prominent, the dystopian discourse on the social and cultural effects of digital media focuses on corporate industry’s ability to exploit the interactive potential of participatory cultures. As Mark Andre- jevic (2003; 2004) points out in his seminal, -Marxist critique of interactive reality television, digital media allow for a new economic format that redefines interactivity and participation in terms of an enforced capitalist exploitation of the interactive consumer:

[T]he contemporary deployment of interactivity exploits participation as a form of labor. Consumers generate marketable commodities by submitting to comprehensive monitoring. They are not so much participating, in the progres- sive sense of collective self-determination, as they are working by submitting to interactive monitoring. The advent of digital interactivity does not challenge the social relations associated with capitalist rationalization, it reinforces them and expands the scale on which they operate (Andrejevic 2003, 197, em- phasis original).

Andrejevic’s critique aims at what I would call the naïve embrace of digital med- ia’s interactive potential and the uncritical assumption that any form of interactiv- ity gives consumers more control over media and allows for culturally more valu- able forms of participation. According to Andrejevic, television shows such as Big Brother and American Idol, or online video-sharing sites such as YouTube, are exam- ples of how the corporate media industry invests in digital technologies to rede- fine the relationship between the spheres of production and consumption: by seducing the audience to contribute to a television show or website, new sources of revenue are created; users pay fees to participate in a television show or to gain access to encrypted live streaming; users contribute their own content without monetary compensation; and whenever they do go online and interact, users pro- duce data valuable for targeted marketing and mass customization. Both perspectives, the utopian and the dystopian, address relevant dimensions of the ongoing redefinition of the relationship between the realms of production and consumption in the digital mediascape, but neither can sufficiently grasp the current transformations. The opposition between these two perspectives seems to reiterate the ‘annoying’ debate between cultural studies’ active audience approach and the critical political economy of media in the 1980s (see Garnham 1995; Grossberg 1995). While the utopian perspective highlights examples of participa- tion that show exceptionally committed, often fan-based communities creating their own virtual spaces in order to contribute to the production or distribution of knowledge and culture, the dystopian perspective focuses on forums, in which the well-established media industry adopts digital technologies in order to open up new markets and to create even more sophisticated forms of consumer seduc- tion and exploitation. While the utopian perspective draws on theories of the ac-

50 digital material tive audience and therefore tends to overestimate self-determined and subversive cultural practices, the dystopian perspective refers to critical theory and political economy and therefore tends to overestimate corporate industry’s power to deter- mine cultural production and the circulation of meaning. While the utopian per- spective discusses interactive reception and production of media content on the level of micro politics, the dystopian perspective addresses institutional and eco- nomic transformations on the macro level. In other words, there is actually no debate between the two perspectives at all: in the course of their argument, both perspectives draw on different examples, theories and approaches, and thus cre- ate two different fields of study; however, at the same time, both generalize their claims and findings as characteristic of the new participatory culture (in the words of the utopian approach) or the new online economy (in the words of the dystopian approach). More current accounts, such as ’s Convergence culture (2006), which acknowledges the competing top-down and bottom-up powers defining digital media’s participatory culture, do not manage to cover both perspectives. Although Jenkins adequately states in the book’s introduction that ‘corporations (…) still exert greater power than any individual consumer or even the aggregate of consumers’ (2006, 3), in his analysis he focuses specifically on subversive and resistant activities performed by dedicated fans. Simultaneously, in his analysis of user participation in television shows and online communities, he downplays the top-down powers that structure even fan-based participatory cultures. In contrast, Andrejevic’s (2004) rather differentiated analysis of resistant cast behavior in the Big Brother house and of related fan practices ultimately comes to the conclusion that all of the cast’s and fans’ efforts to determine the outcome of the reality game show, according to their own self-created rules, merely served the producers’ in- terests.

Against the background of the reversed blind spots apparent in these two differ- ent accounts of participatory media, I will discuss how three different examples of participation television – America’s Most Wanted (Fox since 1988), Big Brother (CBS since 2000), and YouTube (after its acquisition by Google in October 2006) – institutionalize ‘spaces of participation’ and how participation becomes ‘for- matted’ within these spaces. I call this process ‘formatting’ in reference to the adaptation of internationally circulating television programs, in which the format details how a program should be produced but at the same time allows producers to adapt it to the local culture. The term thus indicates a characteristic tension between the predefinition by conceptual structures and the redefinition by prac- tices. In a similar manner, the concept of ‘institutionalization’ (Berger/Luckmann 1967) as ‘socially constructed templates for actions, generated and maintained through ongoing interactions’ (Barsley/Tolbert 1997, 94) helps to analyze the re- lation between the interface, as offered by a television program or website, and formatted spaces of participation 51 the routinized forms of user interaction. In the following, the term ‘interaction’ refers to actual, physical acts of interaction between a television program’sor website’s interface and users, whereas the term ‘participation’ will be used as a concept to address the social, political and cultural characteristics of what I call ‘spaces of participation’. I suggest a spatial metaphor to indicate that television programs or website interfaces form the frameworks within which users who access and ‘inhabit’ such a space perform their actions. Unlike ethnographic practice theory, which focuses on the observation of ‘publicly accessible practices’ (Swidler 2001, 76), I do not think that practices as such are the starting point for an individual’s ac- tions within real or virtual spaces. Rather, practices are structured by pre-existing socially and ideologically defined spaces within which actions are performed. These actions may negotiate and transform the very conventions and limits of a given, in this case mediated, space; however, the social power to construct such spaces and to define the frameworks for action is not shared equally within a society. Particularly in the realm of media, the power to create frameworks of communication is not distributed democratically, but instead is controlled by a multinational industry, and in this regard digital media are no exception (see also Resnick 1998). The crucial question remains how various powers structure such spaces of cultural participation, because the interconnected question about whether digital forms of interaction allow for more self-determined forms of par- ticipation will be determined in this manner. Against this background, a comparative historical approach to different frame- works and spaces of participation is useful: it helps to avoid naive accounts that proclaim new forms of participation to be radically different when they are actu- ally linked, to a much greater extent than the utopian perspective acknowledges, to traditional forms of culture and cultural conventions.

Aktenzeichen XY: participation as ‘nation watching’ Television shows that invite members of the audience to participate in a program are not a new phenomenon in the history of television. Prior to the advent of digital media, there were very few shows that initiated audience interaction by implying the possibility for viewers’ participation in the show while they were simultaneously watching at home. One of the earliest examples of participatory television shows was the West-German reality crime show, Aktenzeichen XY… unge- löst (ZDF, beginning in 1967), which became the prototype for America’s Most Wanted (Fox, beginning in 1988) and can, therefore, be seen as a key forerunner for a certain brand of reality programming (see also Jermyn 2007; Pinseler 2007; Müller 2009). Aktenzeichen XY transformed the television studio into a stylized po- lice department, presented reconstructions of real criminal cases as short filmic

52 digital material narratives, solicited the audience to call in live and thus to help in solving the cases. This show’s distinctive combination of dramaturgic elements made the pro- gram an immediate and long-lasting international success. In the US, as in many European countries, the program has been especially criticized for its power to address the national audience as police informers (see also Cavender 2004; Jer- myn 2007). As the German psychoanalyst Claus-Dieter Rath (1985) commented furiously in an essay entitled The invisible network, this program is ‘a perverse reali- zation of Brecht’s theory of radio, which called for the distribution system of radio to be turned into a communications apparatus in which everyone is in- volved. (…) The TV-citizen becomes a member of the police, the restorer of “law and order”, the eye of the law. The state and the police force merge into the audience, into a community around the broadcast, made up of the invisible elec- tronic network between isolated homes and dwellings which (…) serves to arrest the errant and the deviant. Thus the social arena functions as a hunting ground, the living room as a hunter’s hide’ (1985, 200). This critique could be translated into the more optimistic language of the uto- pian approach to participatory media, which focuses on the ‘blurring of bound- aries’ while neglecting questions of power: The ‘hybrid combination’ of television and telephony breaks down modernity’s separation of public and private, of citi- zens and state authorities, of information and entertainment. It turns the pas- sively consuming mass audience of traditional television programming into active users of the interactive possibilities of a multimedia environment that allows the ‘collaborative intelligence’ of broadcasters, the police and the audience to fight crime and make the world a safer place. This patently unreasonable translation of Rath’s dystopian account misses the central question about power relations, which are implied in the program’s specific setup and structure the interaction of the participating parties. Aktenzeichen XY and its international adaptations define a very narrow ideological space of participation: not only does this show allow for a very limited range and depth of interaction2; the broadcaster, in collaboration with the police, remains in control of the production of the television text, while the show forces the interacting audience to subscribe to the ideological position of the program, as defined by the conservative call for law and order. This might explain the polarizing effect characteristic of this and subsequent forms of television programming that drew on actual audience participation: whereas the ‘passive’ viewer has the freedom to negotiate or resist the ideology of a program (as described in active audience theory), the interactive participant ne- cessarily affirms the program’s ideological stance: the interactive viewer engages in this televisual form of nationwide ‘neighborhood watching’. Aktenzeichen XY and its international adaptations provoked two different, if not quite opposite, reac- tions: one can be described as the affirmation of citizenship, in a conservative sense, by those who were willing to interact and forward information to state formatted spaces of participation 53 authorities via television and telephone; the other, as embodied in a flood of cri- tical commentaries and parodies, can be described as a progressive form of citi- zenship that questions the legitimacy of the collaboration between state author- ities and public television in a civil society. Though one could argue that, for most viewers, the participatory potential of the program remains only virtual, the criti- cal reception of the program teaches us to not only examine the technological interface of digitally enhanced forms of television and participatory websites, but also to critically analyze how their dramaturgical and ideological setups structure actual forms of interaction in any specific ‘space of participation’.

Big Brother: participation in a cross-media spectacle Although Aktenzeichen XY and its international adaptations made use of a hybrid media ensemble, they remain examples of how television structured the relation- ship between the spheres of production and consumption as developed by broad- cast media in the : the range and depth of possible interactions were limited and ideologically defined. However, at the end of the ‘century of broad- casting’, another highly controversial television program redefined the genre of reality programming. For the first time in television history, the Dutch reality for- mat Big Brother systematically employed a hybrid combination of television, tele- phony and the internet to create enhanced forms of audience participation. In addition to a daily episode, this cross-media spectacle made unedited live stream- ing from cameras in the house accessible, which covered the life of the cast 24 hours a day. In addition to this, Big Brother invited the audience to discuss the cast and the events on the program’s official website and (in its original version as broadcast in 1999/20003) to decide every other week which of the two nominated cast members should be expelled from the house. Any viewer with access to a phone or a networked computer could literally make his or her choice between the two options every other week, and it is well documented that many viewers did so and further attempted to define the program’s development by communicating their vote. While the ‘traditional’ audience used the old media, television and telephone, as a means for communication, a more media-savvy group of users began - ing Big Brother on the Internet and employed this medium as a communicative space, which allowed for alternate means of relating to the development of the program and its reception (see also Mathijs/Jones 2004). Online, fans commented on contestants, speculated about future developments in the house or about the outcomes of nominations and votes, formed fan groups supporting individual contestants, and advised producers about possibilities for further development of the program. For this group of active fans, differences between the edited sixty- minute episodes on television and the live streaming on the Internet became cru- cial, as the live feed allowed this audience to watch life in the house indepen-

54 digital material dently of the producers’ choices, and thus to accumulate knowledge and generate interpretations that were uninfluenced by the edited and dramatized narratives that were broadcast on television. According to comments by online fans, these edited episodes misrepresented the events in the house in order to manipulate the television audience’s decisions and bring them into accordance with the produ- cers’ economic calculations (see Andrejevic 2004, 117-141; Tincknell/Raghuram 2004; Wilson 2004). The online fans’ critique raised two crucial questions: who actually exercised editorial control over the program, and whether the range and depth of Big Brother’s interactivity were as meaningful as the producer’s promotion for the program had claimed. As a cross-media platform, Big Brother created an enhanced, but at the same time still restricted, ‘space of participation’. In his neo-Marxist approach to reality television, Mark Andrejevic (2004) sug- gested that the space of participation, as created by Big Brother, can be described as ‘a commodified example of procedural authorship: the producers craft the set of rules whereby cast members (and sometimes audiences) shape the show’ (2004, 49). Compared to Aktenzeichen XY, this form of procedural authorship does allow for more complex contributions by the audience, particularly on the inter- net. Nevertheless, possible moments and the dramaturgical depth of potential contributions by the audience are still limited. Beyond that, the range of participa- tion is formatted by the program’s setup and is structured by the program’s ideol- ogy. Therefore, Andrejevic in his analysis claims that ‘the result has not been a transfer of power and control from the power elites of Hollywood to the masses, but rather a shift in the burden of labor from paid actors and writers to the view- ers, from whose rank the cast is drawn and whose free labor of fan sites helps add value and interest in often lackluster performances’ (2004, 89). Andrejevic points to a problem that is characteristic of the intermediate step located between a merely consuming audience and the evolution of interactive users in the realm of digitally networked media: whenever the audience stops simply watching and consuming, whenever viewers start to interact with and con- tribute to a program or to a program’s ‘overflow’ (Brooker 2001) on the Internet, whenever users share their views or content online, they perform unpaid labor and submit to extensive monitoring. This generates a surplus value that only the producers can control and exploit. Arguing within the tradition of critical theory and political economy, Andrejevic tends to equate any act of interaction in the cross-media space of participation with the economic rationale of the industry; however, his critical analysis of reality television highlights aspects of the new media economy that many of the utopian approaches neglect or downplay. In a more comprehensive approach, one could address this as the ‘condition of parti- cipation’. On the one hand, active users do perform unpaid labor and produce exploitable data. At the same time, members of the Big Brother audience become active contributors to the program, and some of them do move, as fans, critical

formatted spaces of participation 55 commentators and creative contributors on the Internet, beyond the limits of the space of participation as formatted by the producers.

YouTube: Participation in a digital bazaar Compared with Aktenzeichen XY and Big Brother, which represent two different types of producer-formatted participation, video-sharing sites such as YouTube, Google Video or Revver create a completely different space of participation, one in which users maintain more control over the space. These sites allow users to upload and distribute any video file that does not show adult or offensive content, or violates . As Wired magazine has commented, ‘any amateur can record a clip’ and can, by following the six easy steps as recommend by Wired, ‘look like a pro’ (Feely 2006). Generally speaking, any one who owns the technological means to record and upload a video film can share his or her self-made clips online. The rapid increase in the number of video clips uploaded to and watched on YouTube, by far the most popular of all online video-sharing sites,4 appears to prove the claim that the ease of access to digital means of production and distribution dis- rupts the traditional regimes of television production and distribution. This sub- stantiates the aforementioned statements, which have indicated that the bound- aries between the spaces of production and consumption are becoming increasingly blurred (e.g. Uricchio 2004; Anderson 2006; Jenkins 2006). Nevertheless, video-sharing sites remain something distinctly unlike utopian spaces of communication that are free of any technological, legal, economic or cultural constraints. The first restrictions are posed by ‘protocols’ (Galloway/ Thacker 2007, 28ff.) and copyright regulations such as the Terms of Use and End- User License Agreement. In addition, Google’s 1.85 billion dollar acquisition of You- Tube in October 2006, and the subsequent adjustments to the site, demonstrate the new online economy has identified video-sharing sites such as YouTube as important markets for customized advertising. The corporate media industry has begun to incorporate and redefine the ‘cooperative non-market production of in- formation and culture’ (Benkler 2006, 2). In sheer economic terms, video-sharing sites are not completely different from traditional systems of commercial broad- casting. As Dallas Smythe (1977) has expressed: commercial broadcast television is in the business of producing audiences for advertisers. Video-sharing sites offer not only content that attracts peers, because many clips are produced by peers, it also provides the advertisers with data that reveal any individual user’s online activities, his or her cultural preferences, and the communities in which he or she participates. Therefore, online video-sharing sites may perform the economic function of television in the future, even more effectively than commercial televi- sion has in the past. Beyond this still-developing economic framework, the interfaces of video-shar- ing sites and the routinized forms for accessing and using these sites have cultur-

56 digital material ally transformed them into highly structured spaces of interaction and participa- tion. In an attempt to characterize online video-sharing sites, José van Dijck (2007) suggests that their institutional form can be characterized as ‘homecast- ing’, in contrast to broadcasting and narrowcasting, and that the cultural form of user-generated clips can best be understood as ‘snippets’: ‘prerecorded, rerecorded, tinkered, and self-produced audiovisual content’ that is not finished like a traditional broadcast television program, but invites users to appropriate, tinker with and respond to it. This characterization of ‘homecasting’ and the ‘snippet’ highlights the differences between traditional television and online vi- deo-sharing sites. However, in terms of institutionalization and cultural forms, there are also many similarities between these two types of audiovisual content with regard to production, distribution and reception. As a matter of fact, the traffic on YouTube demonstrates that the number of users and downloaded clips far outnumbers the quantity of individual contribu- tors and uploaded clips. Figures as published in July 2006 might still be indicative of the ratio between incidental ‘producers’ and sheer ‘consumers’ of content on YouTube: whereas 65,000 clips were uploaded per day, a total of 100 million clips were watched, which represents a ratio of 1:1,538.5 In other words, most YouTu- bers do not employ YouTube as a means for publishing and distributing their clips, but rather view it like traditional television, as ‘consumers’ of a ‘tube of plenty’ (Barnouw 1990). At the same time, there are an extraordinary number of users who do contrib- ute video clips to YouTube. Prior to uploading clips, users have to create an ac- count where they can then post their videos. This account becomes visible as an identifiable ‘channel’ to which other users can subscribe. Even those who do not upload their own clips can still create a channel by choosing clips already avail- able on YouTube. Thus, as in traditional broadcast television, the concept of ‘channels’ structures the way clips are distributed online, and many users actually try to brand their channel to attract a larger audience. When uploading a video, the user is required to create a title and a description for the clip, enter keywords, and choose one category from a list of fourteen to characterize the clip’s genre, such as ‘education’, ‘how to & style’,or‘people and blogs’. Although the sheer number of videos available on YouTube functionally prevents the exhaustive categorization of the content, handbooks such as YouTube 4 You (Miller 2007) and YouTube for Dummies (Botello/Sahlin 2007) reflect routi- nized methods for accessing and using YouTube. Miller differentiates between nine prototypes of users, namely the ‘recorder/sharer’, the ‘historian/enthusiast’, the ‘home movie maker’, the ‘video blogger’,the‘instructor’,the‘reporter’, the ‘performer’, the ‘aspiring film director’ and the ‘online business’ (2007, 76-86). Both the genre categories, as defined on YouTube, and the types of users, as described by Miller, indicate that tinkering with the ‘snippets’ of other contribu- tors is actually not the first and foremost practice performed on YouTube. formatted spaces of participation 57 Though it is true that there are many examples where the content of other users is reused and tinkered with, these still form the exception rather than the rule, which is that clips on YouTube, even if not well structured in terms of drama- turgy, are primarily meant to be watched. The interface offers no indication as to how often a clip has been reused, but instead how often it has been watched, and how it has been rated. As in any other mass medium, an implicit imperative of YouTube is to create so-called ‘viral videos’, which will themselves be embedded in many channels, blogs and websites, and thus will be watched by a larger audi- ence.6 Handbooks include sections such as: ‘What makes a great YouTube vi- deo?’, ‘Sell product placement in your videos’,or‘How to increase your YouTube ratings – and your potential profits’ (Miller 2007, 87, 166, 172). Again, these re- main approaches that are characteristic of commercial broadcast television and function to structure YouTube’s space of participation according to its rationale. However, as Van Dijck correctly points out, YouTube’s interface in general, and many clips in particular, ask users to respond to the clips. The interface specifi- cally invites users to post comments on clips; further, users can respond to the comments themselves, or users can post another video in response to a clip. As compared to traditional broadcast television, in which only a few formatted mo- ments existed in specific programs when members of the audience can literally respond, a dialogic structure is characteristic of online video-sharing sites, which links YouTube to traditions of oral cultures. There is a huge diversity of the types of comments on YouTube: some commentators express that they share experi- ences or tastes; some tutor the maker of a clip and give tips on how to improve the quality; others articulate what a viewer of a regular television show might shout at his set when watching a program at home; some try to create attention for their own clips on YouTube; and there are myriad other responses. Character- istic of most such comments is their use of everyday language, as if users were just chatting in an informal context. On YouTube and other video-sharing sites, this appears to be the cultural norm, the routinized practice. Again, although different from broadcast television, YouTube and other video-sharing sites gener- ate their own (as far as the interface is concerned) explicit and (as far as recurrent practices are concerned) implicit rules and conventions, which format the space of participation YouTube offers. Both the framework and the rules and conventions that define this space of participation have to be analyzed in much more detail. My point here is that vi- deo-sharing sites are formatted by a cultural framework that defines a video-shar- ing site’s space of participation. This framework is partly generated by the web- site’s interface and partly by the users’ recurrently performed and thus ‘highly institutionalized actions’ (Zucker 1977, 727). Regarding YouTube, concepts that are characteristic of broadcast television and conventions that are characteristic of oral cultures combine to format the space of participation. On the one hand, these concepts reveal the difference between producers and consumers, the con-

58 digital material struction of channels, the notion of genres as a framework for production and reception, the worship of high ratings and their implicit commercial potential. On the other hand, these conventions form the dialogic structure and traditions of oral culture define this space. This is, although video-sharing sites allow for far more diverse forms of participation than the examples of interactive television programs analyzed in sections one and two, even video-sharing sites structure possible acts of participation, and they do so by drawing on well established con- ventions that then may become transformed and redefined. A user who decides to upload clips to a video-sharing site subscribes to partici- pating in what could best be described as a ‘bazaar’,7 in which television is rede- fined as part of an amateur culture. This non-professional approach to television draws on dialogic structures and oral traditions, but at the same time is geared to its professional and commercial form, which formats this specific space of parti- cipation. Although YouTube and other video-sharing sites differ from broadcast television; broadcast television and online video-sharing sites do not embody dia- metrically opposed concepts, but different institutionalizations of television on a spectrum of cultural forms of television that mutually define each other.8 There- fore, one should not underestimate broadcast television’s power to shape what I call the participatory space of video-sharing sites.

Formatted spaces of participation In the past decade, it appears as though we have witnessed what Bruno Felix and Femke Wolting titled The end of television as we know it (2000), in their documentary on the emerging online economy. Television ‘as we know it’ will remain powerful in shaping participatory practices on cross-media and digital platforms. As Henry Jenkins in Convergence culture has correctly argued, we have to consider ‘ever more complex relations between top-down corporate media and bottom-up participa- tory culture’ (2006, 243). However, I doubt that his romanticizing vision of top- down vs. bottom-up forces provides an adequate account of the economic, social, and cultural processes that are shaping and reshaping the relationship between the spheres of television production and consumption. The romantic metaphor of ‘top-down versus bottom-up’, very much like the opposition between the utopian and the dystopian account of digital media as discussed at the beginning, evokes a morally tinted opposition that characterizes non-professional and non-commer- cial media practices by definition as authentic, democratic and empowering, whereas professional and commercial media practices are marked as repressive and manipulative. As I have demonstrated in my historically comparative account of three different forms of interactive television and video-sharing sites, any of these forms creates institutionally and culturally structured spaces of participa- tion. These are not merely imposed upon users by the industrially created inter- faces. Particularly in cross-media and in digital setups, such as Big Brother and formatted spaces of participation 59 YouTube, these spaces are co-created and shaped by the recurrent and thus routi- nized practices of users. Instead of simply praising the ‘blurring of boundaries’ between the spheres of production and consumption, the concept of ‘formatted spaces of participation’ allows for a more differentiated and adequate analysis of the technological, economic, social and cultural powers and conventions that structure the diverse participatory practices which these spaces allow for and also provoke. In this emerging field of research into interactive television, online vi- deo-sharing and participatory culture, the concept of ‘formatted spaces of partici- pation’ helps to move beyond the technologically defined range and depth of in- teractivity. It asks us to critically address the routinized practices within these spaces that make these spaces into individualized institutions with their own spe- cific, cultural conventions and ideologies.

Notes 1. In discourses on media and citizenship (e.g. Couldry, Livingstone and Markham 2007), cultural policy (e.g. Blokland 1997), and traditional art (e.g. Arns 2004), the word ‘par- ticipation’ refers to acts of engaging in culture and art by actively receiving culture, i.e. reading, attending performances, visiting exhibitions, etc. However, the meaning of the word ‘participation’ has changed: people characteristically ‘participate’ not only through active reception of culture and art but also, and primarily, through the active contribution of content to the culture in which they engage. See, for example, Ebare (2004) or Jenkins (2006; 2007). 2. I employ here Jenssen’s (1999) theoretical approach to interactive television, in which he favors a quantitative model of interactivity that allows for distinctions between dif- ferent levels of interaction, which are allowed within a medium or application. 3. The rules for the format vary from season to season, not only to keep the format fresh and attractive for the audience, but also to redesign the possible forms of audience interaction. Generally speaking, the show’s producers increasingly attempt to control the ‘space of participation’, which was much less restricted in the first season. 4. YouTube itself does not reveal exact data; however, data published by ComScore Media Matrix, for September 2007, demonstrate the consistent popularity of YouTube as one of the top ten overall websites: 75% of all internet users in the US watch streaming video online, 27.6% of all users log on to YouTube. As ComSocre Media Matrix reports, ‘nearly 70 million people viewed more than 2.5 billion videos on YouTube.com. Online viewers watched an average of slightly more than three hours of online video during the month (181 minutes). The average online video duration was 2.7 minutes. The average online video viewer consumed 68 videos, or more than two per day’ (http://www.com- score.com/press/release.asp?press=1929; April 2, 2008). Stelter (2008) reports more than 3.4 billion video downloads in February 2008. 5. USA Today, July 16, 2006 (http://www.usatoday.com/tech/news/2006-07-16-youtube- views_x.htm; April 2, 2008). 6. Success stories, like Apple buying and remaking 17-year-old British college student Nick Haley’s self-made commercial for the iPod Touch (Elliot 2007), not only demon- strate that YouTube functions as a space where professional and amateur cultures meet, but also that acknowledgment by many viewers and professionals is an implicit objec- tive on YouTube.

60 digital material 7. The metaphor ‘bazaar’ employed by Raymond (1999) for open software develop- ment might serve as a metaphor for online video-sharing sites (as opposed to the ‘ca- thedral’ of broadcast TV), if one takes into account that a bazaar, although accessible to anyone who can walk, is an institutionally and culturally highly structured space where people not only meet to sell and buy, but additionally where there are different roles, hierarchical structures, and conventions of conduct, all of which remain more or less impregnated by the economic rationale of a bazaar. 8. Roepke (2006) shows that the boundaries between home moviemaking, - making and the professional film world have remained blurred ever since.

Acknowledgements I am grateful to Johannes von Moltke and Martina Roepke for their advice and suggestions and to Rebecca L. Garber for her careful revision of this text.

References Anderson, Chris. 2006. People power: Blogs, user reviews, photo-sharing – The peer pro- duction era has arrived. Wired, July 14, 2006. http://www.wired.com/wired/archive/ 14.07/people.html. Andrejevic, Mark. 2003. The webcam and the digital enclosure. In MediaSpace: Place, scale and culture in a media age, eds. Nick Couldry, and Anna McCarthy. London/ New York: Routledge. Andrejevic, Mark. 2004. Reality TV: The work of being watched. Lanham: Rowman, and Little- field. Arns, Inke. 2004. Interaction, participation, networking: Art and . Media Art Net. http://www.mediaartnet.org/themes/overview_of_media_art/communication/1/. Barsley, Stephen R., and Pamela S. Tolbert. 1997. Institutionalization and structuration: Studying the links between action and institution. Organization Studies 18 (1): 93-117. Barnouw, Eric. 1990. Tube of plenty: The evolution of American television. Oxford: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Benkler, Yochai. 2006. The wealth of networks: How social production transforms markets and free- dom. New York: Yale University Press. Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1967. The social construction of reality. New York: Doubleday. Blokland, Hans. 1997. Publiek gezocht: Essays over cultuur, markt en politiek. Amsterdam: Boom. Botello, Chis, and Doug Sahlin. 2007. YouTube for dummies. Hoboken: Wiley Publishing. Brooker, Will. 2001. Living on Dawson’s Creek. Teen viewers, cultural convergence, and tele- vision overflow. International Journal of Cultural Studies 4 (4): 456-472. Cavender, Gray. 2004. In search of community in reality TV: America’s Most Wanted and Survivor.InUnderstanding Reality Television, eds. Su Homes, and Deborah Jermyn, 154- 172. London: Routledge. Couldry, Nick, Sonja Livingstone and Tim Markham. 2007. Media consumption and public engagement. London: Palgrave. Ebare, Sean. 2004. Digital music and subculture: Sharing files, sharing styles. First Monday 9 (2). http://firstmonday.org/issues/issue9_2/ebare/index.html. formatted spaces of participation 61 Elliot, Stuart. 2007. Student’s ad gets a remake and hits a big time. New York Times, October 26. http://www.nytimes.com/2007/10/26/business/media/26appleweb.html. Feely, Jim. 2006. Lights! Camera! Vodcast! How to make your own viral hit. Wired, May 14. 2006. http://www.wired.com/wired/archive/14.05/howto.html. Felix Bruno, and Femke Wolting. 2000. It’s the end of TV as we know it. Video documentary. Hilversum: VPRO. Garnham, Nicholas. 1995. Political economy and cultural studies: Reconciliation or di- vorce? Critical Studies in Mass Communication 12: 62-71. Grossberg, Lawrence. 1995. Cultural studies vs. political economy: Is anyone else bored with this debate? Critical Studies in Mass Communication 12: 72-81. Jenkins, Henry. 2006. Convergence culture: Where old and new media collide. New York: New York University Press. Jenkins, Henry. 2007. Confronting the challenges of participatory culture: Media education for the 21st century. Chicago: MacArthur Foundation. Jenssen, Jens F. 1999. The concept of ‘interactivity’ in ‘interactive television’ and ‘interactive media’.InInteractive television: tv of the future or the future of TV? eds. Jens F. Jensen, and Cathy Toscan, 25-66. Aalborg: Aalborg University Press. Jermyn, Deborah. 2007. Watching ‘Crimewatch UK’. London: Clarendon Press. Mathijs, Ernest, and Janet Jones, eds. 2004. Big Brother international: Formats, critics and publics. London, New York: Wallflower Press. Miller, Michael. 2007. YouTube 4 you. Indianapolis: Que Publishing. Müller, Eggo. 2009. Crime watch EU: Transnational circulation of formatted television. Media History 15 (3). Pierce, Cecilia. 1997. The interactive book: A guide to the interactive revolution. Indianapolis: Mac- millan. Pinseler, Jan. 2007. Fahndungssendungen im deutschsprachingen Fernsehen. Cologne: Herbert von Halem Verlag. Rath, Claus-Dieter. 1985. The invisible network: Television as an institution in everyday life. In Television in transition: Papers from the first international television studies conference, eds. by Phillip Drummond, and Richard Paterson, 199-204. London: BFI. Raymond, Eric S. 1999. The cathedral and the bazaar: Musings on and . Sebasto- pol: O’Reilly Media. Resnick, David. 1998. Politics on the Internet: The normalization of cyberspace. In The politics of cyberspace, eds. Chis Toulousee, and Timothy W. Luke, 46-68. New York: Rout- ledge. Roepke, Martina. 2006. Privat-Vorstellung: Heimkino in Deutschland vor 1945. Hildesheim: Olms. Smythe, Dallas. 1977. Communications: Blind spot of Western Marxism. Canadian Journal of Political and Social Theory, 1 (3): 1-28. Stelter, Brian. 2008. You’ve seen the YouTube video; now try the documentary. New York Times, May 10, 2008. http://www.nytimes.com/2008/05/10/arts/television/10kruger.html? scp= 1&sq=youtube&st=nyt. Swidler, Ann. 2001. What anchors cultural practices? In The practice turn in contemporary theo- ry, eds. Theodore R. Schatzki, Karin Knorr Cetina, Eike von Savigny, 74-92. New York: Routledge.

62 digital material Tapscott, Don. 1996. The digital economy: Promise and peril in the age of networked intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill. Tapscott, Don; Williams, Anthony D. 2006. Wikinomics: How mass collaboration changes every- thing. New York: B&T. Tincknell, Estella, and Parvati Raghuram. 2004. Big Brother: Reconfiguring the ‘active’ audience of cultural studies? In Understanding reality television, eds. Su Homes, and De- borah Jermyn, 252-269. London: Routledge. Toffler, Alvin. 1980. The third wave. New York: William Morrow. Uricchio, William. 2004. Cultural citizenship in the age of P2P networks. In European Culture and the Media, eds. Ib Bondebjerg, and Peter Golding, 139-164. Bristol: Intellect. Van Dijck, José. 2007. Homecasting: The end of broadcasting? Vodavone Receiver Magazine 18. http://www.receiver.vodafone.com/18-homecasting-the-end-of-broadcasting. Wilson, Pamela. 2004. Jamming Big Brother: Webcasting, audience intervention, and narra- tive activism. In Reality TV: Remaking television culture, eds. Susan Marray, and Laurie Ouellette, 323-343. New York: New York University Press. Zucker, Lynne G. 1977. The role of institutionalization in cultural persistence. American Sociological Review 42: 726-743.

formatted spaces of participation 63

Digital objects in e-learning environments

The case of WebCT

Erna Kotkamp

Higher education in the 21st century is challenged by changes, many of them instigated by the promising potential of new technologies in teaching, especially the Internet and web-based tools. These web-based tools are often clustered in so-called e-learning environments, or Learning Management Systems, that aim to support and even improve learning. In these environments different components and tools like bulletin boards and online syllabi are put together into one applica- tion, usually set up so that these tools can be used in separate courses. Well- known and heavily used environments in higher education are WebCT, Black- board, Moodle, FirstClass, N@tschool and Claroline. In higher education these environments are put to use in different ways, extending from supporting face- to-face teaching with an additional online component, to supporting full online courses where all learning activities take place within the e-learning environment (Kotkamp et al. 2005). E-learning or web-based learning is heralded by some for being able to serve an important pedagogical function, especially supporting teaching and learning from a social-constructivist perspective (Littlejohn 2003; Jochems et al. 2004; Downes 2006). The rise of these environments is even considered by some to be the reason for the increase in popularity of a social-constructivist philosophy in debates on learning theories (Anderson and Garrison 2006). However, when looking at the actual use of these integrated e-learning environments, the most important function they seem to serve is an administrative one. Christaan Dal- gaard argues that especially when teaching from a social-constructivist perspec- tive, large, integrated e-learning environments can only play a minor role (Dal- gaard 2006). In this article I want to look at those aspects of social constructivism that are significant in this discussion on the pedagogical potential of e-learning environ- ments. I will analyze and show how this potential is not yet being fulfilled, by using WebCT as a case in point. In the last part I will move on to various technical

65 and design aspects of e-learning environments that might account for some of the observed discrepancies between the aim to design for a social-constructivist learning process and the actual outcome.

Social-constructivist philosophy Much has been written about social constructivism and its meaning for learning processes. Ideas like collaborative learning, student-centered learning, self-gov- erned learning, authentic learning, and peer review are associated with the dis- cussion on social constructivism and e-learning. Many of these ideas can be traced back to the work of educational reformist John Dewey at the beginning of the 20th century. A central element of his work is the idea that learning will be improved by reflection. Reflective thought for Dewey meant ‘active, persistent, and careful consideration of any belief or supposed form of knowledge in the light of the grounds that support it and the further conclusion to which it tends’ (Dewey 1910, 6). Learning is not so much a process of transmitting information, but a process of recreation and giving meaning (Dewey 1938). Hence, learning is considered a constructive process that will turn out different for every learner. This is related to the importance Dewey assigns to previous experience and prior knowledge. According to Dewey, ‘all genuine education comes about through experience’ (Dewey 1938, 13). In a classroom setting this means that the experience of a learner has to be incorporated in the teaching to improve the learning process. Dewey proposed a theory of experience, consisting of two principles: continuity and interaction. Continuity pertains to the impor- tance of past experiences for a person’s future, and to the need for continuous embedding in the learning experience. Interaction pertains to the influence of the context and the situation in which these experiences occur. It becomes the re- sponsibility of the teacher to create space for the incorporation of continuity and interaction (Dewey 1938). Dewey’s theory of experience is still relevant today, as it provides the basis of the concept of authentic learning. Within authentic learning it is considered of great importance that learners link what they are learning to a context where this newly acquired knowledge actually has a function (Volman 2006). Learning has to reflect actual practice and meaning, and this can only be accomplished by includ- ing experience and adhering to the two principles of continuity and interaction. Related to this notion of experience is the acknowledgment of power relations at work in knowledge production and teaching processes. Knowledge is not ob- jectively ‘discovered’ but created in a power-charged social relation (Haraway 1988; Freire 1970/1996). Although not explicitly mentioned in Dewey’s work, this principle is implicated in the social values and norms by which experiences are shaped and knowledge is constructed. Taking these power relations into account and including them in a learning experience enables reflection on the relation

66 digital material between teacher and student. A teacher is seen as an expert in her field but should also function as a coach of the learning process. The teacher should be pedagogi- cally competent at both tasks (Garrison and Anderson 2006, 4). This also implies that, in some regards, the relation between teacher and student should be hori- zontal: a teacher can learn from a student, too. This becomes especially important when new media are being used in teaching and learning. In a traditional higher education setting, students are often more competent than their teachers in deal- ing with new media, and teachers could learn this from their students (Holm Sørensen 2006). Another important element of Dewey’s theory is the idea that thinking should be considered as ‘a state of perplexity, hesitation, doubt’ (Dewey 1910, 9). Accord- ing to this principle, effective learning should be troublesome, should involve a phase of uncertainty and disturbance. Learning is not a stable process that starts and ends with clarity and security. According to Dewey and others after him, a certain amount of insecurity and chaos is crucial for an effective learning process. The social aspect of social-constructivist thinking is also reflected in Dewey’s work. He once stated, ‘I believe that the individual who is to be educated is a social individual and that society is an organic union of individuals’ (Dworkin 1959, 22). From this follows the current notion of the importance of collaborative learning. This can take many forms and can serve different goals. A small ex- plorative study amongst higher education teachers I conducted at different facul- ties revealed that many teachers valued collaborative learning, but that they did so for different reasons. Some teachers saw it as an extra skill to be learned, a goal in itself; other teachers saw it as an inherent part of the knowledge construction process, by which students can learn from each other’s knowledge and experi- ence. The latter concurs with social-constructivist learning: in collaboration dif- ferent experiences and social contexts can be combined to achieve a richer learn- ing experience. From these principles of a social-constructivist pedagogy, we can derive some requirements for an e-learning environment. It should cater to the complexity of learning processes and their contents, and it should create room for a diversity of learners and their prior experience and knowledge. This notion of diversity implies that interactivity occurs not only between learners and content, but also among the learners. All in all, this calls for an environment that is in itself dynamic, but also capable of facilitating dynamic and complex learning processes in which insecurity and doubt can have a place.

The case of WebCT In the following section I will measure these notions of complexity, diversity, inter- activity and dynamics against a concrete e-learning environment, WebCT, as it claims to accommodate these principles. digital objects in e-learning environments 67 WebCT, one of the first large e-learning environments, came right out of a higher education teaching practice around 1995, instigated by computer-science instructor Murrey Goldberg at the University of British Columbia. Goldberg was a firm supporter of the idea that education would benefit from using online tools. In his opinion the greatest advantage and added value of such tools was commu- nication independent of place and time. The possibility of asynchronous commu- nication was thus at the heart of the first prototypes. As he stated, ‘In the studies we have done, it is the communication tools that have the greatest impact on the educational experience, not the on-line content’ (Goldberg 2000a). Though Gold- berg did not elaborate on how these communication tools and the communica- tion itself could influence the learning experience, we may assume that his em- phasis on communication implies acknowledgment of interactivity, collaborative learning, and social context as beneficial for education. Moreover, Goldberg developed the environment together with his students, as a learning experience for them but also in order to incorporate their ideas. In doing so, he in fact put into practice the idea that students are a source of knowl- edge themselves. As a teacher Goldberg opened himself to learning from his stu- dents, thereby establishing a more horizontal relation between teacher and stu- dents. Goldberg also pointed at the added value of self-reflection by the teacher: ‘It requires you to reevaluate both the content you are teaching and the way in which you teach’ (Goldberg 2000b). This implies that Goldberg saw teaching as a dynamic process that needs constant evaluation and adjustment. By the end of the 1990s, WebCT became a commercial company. The e-learn- ing environment gained popularity with the increase of web-based teaching in general. It was one of the few large integrated environments available, and its multitude of possibilities attracted many universities.1 However, this multitude of possibilities was also at the core of the criticism that the product was difficult to use. WebCT company claimed that this was mostly due to the flexibility and the number of features. According to WebCT, other e-learning environments, such as Blackboard, were simpler as they only presented a single way of organizing course material. WebCT presented itself as a genuine attempt to offer more op- tions, by which individual instructors could have more freedom to design the course environment. WebCT’s vision claimed ‘to support a broad range of peda- gogical and learning styles’.2 Hence, WebCT was not intended to be used as just a repository for the course material, but should function as an environment where collaboration and interac- tion can play a crucial role in the e-learning experience, and where the environ- ment itself can influence the learning process in a constructive manner. However, when scrutinizing the functionalities in WebCT, there seems to be a discrepancy between the underlying pedagogical views and the technological modeling of the environment.

68 digital material Take for example the so-called roles available in WebCT: what functionalities and possibilities are implied in these roles, and what implications does this entail for the teaching process? WebCT Vista 3.0 offers role types that have been defined by the IMS Global Learning Consortium and are indicated in Table 1 (WebCT 2004).

Administrators Manage settings, enrolment, files and templates Help Desk User Receives a subset of administrator permissions Designers Build courses or templates Instructors Deliver courses and assign grades Teaching assistants Assist instructors in delivering course and grading Students Take courses and receive a final grade Auditors Take courses but do not receive a final grade

Table 1: Roles in WebCT Vista 3.0

These different role types function in what WebCT calls different learning con- texts (ibid.) (Table 2).

Learning Context Includes These Role Types Role Name for Your Installation

Server administrator Server Administrator

Domain administrator Domain Administrator designer Domain Designer

Institution administrator Institution Administrator help desk Institution Help Desk User Institution Designer designer

Group administrator Group Administrator help desk Group Help Desk User designer Group Designer

Course designer Course Designer instructor Course Instructor

Section designer Section Designer instructor Section Instructor teaching assistant Section Teaching Assistant student Section Student auditor Section Auditor

Table 2: Learning contexts in WebCT Vista 3.0

All of these roles have different forms of access to different tools and possibilities within their Learning Context. Traditional courses in this learning context are placed on the level of a Section. This is due to WebCT’s decision that ‘learner digital objects in e-learning environments 69 roles exist only within sections and get the student version of whatever the de- signers have designed for the section plus some of their own personal tools, like My Progress or My Grades’ (ibid.). This means learners in the Student role receive access only on the level of a section, and in a course-centered teaching setting this also applies to the roles of Instructor and Designer. The Designer is the role that can actually ‘design’ the course and the learning process: manage online content and determine which tools can be accessed by the other roles of Instructor, Teaching Assistant, Student and Auditor. It is the only role that can create assignments, assessments, we- blinks and can upload files in a generally accessible area within the section. Re- markably, a Designer cannot interact with Students; this role has no access to the mail tool or the discussion forum. The Instructor does have that kind of access, but this role cannot remove or add tools, though it can edit some of the settings of the tools. The Student can only view the course material but cannot add or alter content. This role only grants access to assignments and assessments to hand them in, and allows for participation in the discussion forum and chat. Only the main Instructor can enroll users into roles. It is possible to combine the role of Instructor and Designer but not the role of Instructor and Student, nor Designer and Student. Functions cannot be separated from the roles; as Administrator it is not possible to assign specific functionalities to a role.

From the perspective of the aforementioned social-constructivist principles, this strict division into roles and attached functionalities is problematic. Though the roles of Instructor and Designer may be combined, a teacher who is seen as a guide and coach in a flexible learning process should have the ability to alter the design of the course throughout the course to ensure this flexibility. More impor- tantly, the Student role is limited to only viewing what the Instructor or Designer has created. This is in sharp contrast to the different pedagogical visions WebCT claims to support. How can you embed previous knowledge and experience into the current learning process? The Student role is not allowed access to the File Manager, and thus cannot add content to the course environment except through attachments on forum postings. The same applies to the Media Library, where Instructors can upload content of different formats, and link them to other con- tent. The Student role is not allowed to provide additions, nor to make connec- tions to or from the Library. With these limitations, learners assigned the Student role become restricted in their interaction with the content, as they lack adequate space for connecting pre- vious knowledge and experience into the course. It furthermore limits the possi- bility of sharing their knowledge construction, obscuring insight into their learn- ing process for both the teacher and other learners. This entails a partial loss of the social in social-constructivist education.

70 digital material Roles and functionalities As mentioned before, an obstacle to a social-constructivist use of WebCT is the inflexible one-to-one relation between role and functionality. It is not possible to separate access to certain functionalities from the roles they are connected to. Learners in the Student role cannot be given the right to add to or alter entries to the Media Library. Or to personalize or create their own learning space by giving them access to an Organizer Page, where course content can be clustered to- gether on a single page. A management of specific functionalities detached from roles would enable a more flexible learning environment where students could have some or even all the rights and possibilities now restricted to the Instructor and Designer roles. This division reveals and reinforces a hierarchical and binary structure between learner (Student role) and teacher (Designer/Instructor role). Again, this limits the use of the environment as a place for knowledge construction. A learner is not given the opportunity to create, produce, add or alter content, and the teacher is not allowed to grant the learner these rights. Neither linking to previously up- loaded material nor connecting to other courses or resources is possible in the Student role. The principles of diversity of content and learners cannot be en- acted; in fact, the principle of contextualized learning is disabled. Not being able to assign a diversity of rights and functionalities to a learner makes it difficult to dynamically construct knowledge and to have a learner be responsible for and in control of his/her own content and learning process. As there is little room to introduce and share previous knowledge, the continuity of the learning process runs the risk of being interrupted. This also applies for the starting page of each course (called Section in the WebCT Learning Context). This is a fixed entity to which only predefined objects can be added. None of the roles can personalize this page to accommodate the individual learning process. The Designer role can add content here, but this con- tent is limited to the objects available in WebCT, such as (links to) an Organizer Page, Content Module or communication tools like Discussion Forum and Mail. The starting page has a predefined layout format; neither images nor text can be placed on the main page. The more tech-savvy users in the Designer role discov- ered a workaround for this inflexibility: the header and footer of the main page appeared to be amenable by some basic HTML, and this made it possible to in- clude other objects than the ones defined by WebCT.

These examples reveal WebCT’s closed (and closeted) way of shaping and accom- modating the learning process. After all, the design of WebCT seems to be aimed at serving as a repository of information with only very limited possibilities of interaction with the material and each other. There is a severe lack of flexibility, which is necessary to create a dynamic learning environment that does justice to digital objects in e-learning environments 71 the complexity of a learning process supporting a diversity of learners and learn- ing styles. This is surprising in the light of WebCT’s history and the reply to the criticism of user-unfriendliness. Indeed, a high degree of functionalities and choices renders the environment complex, but this does not make the environ- ment automatically more suitable for a diversity in pedagogy and learning styles. Since WebCT does claim to have this intention, the loss may be due to the technical translation of these aims, that is, to choices made in the early stages of developing the application. At least, there seems to be a tension in the conceptua- lization of what an environment might support and the technical output of this. In the next section3 I will explore this tension by addressing how human interac- tion is conceived within , and what this entails for the technolo- gical translations.

Computer science and object orientation Since the beginning of computation and computer science, the focus has been on data and the processing of data between machines. This means that information is translated into mathematical expressions and procedures that are understood by machines. From this perspective, interactions between software and hardware are modeled as causal procedures linking senders to receivers. The actions (mes- sages) of the sender are the impulses for the actions/reactions of the receivers. The important element in this structure is the clear and unambiguous relation between these impulses and their reactions. Interaction, then, is fully structured and planned in these systems. By the end of the last century, a shift had taken place from the processing of information between hardware systems to offering ready-made interactions with humans. These actions were aimed at automating and/or enhancing human ac- tion; first focused on calculating, later on text and image editing, and in an even later stage learning. However, within computer science the way of dealing with interaction re- mained the same as when dealing with machine-machine interaction. Interaction is handled in a clear and formalized manner, excluding any ambiguity. As pointed out by several technology theorists, the modeling of complex interaction patterns between humans is still based on the transmission model used for the representa- tion of data-exchange between artificial senders and receivers (Crutzen 2001; Suchman 1994; Leigh Star 1991; Laurel 1991). In other words, the modeling of software applications aimed at human interaction is based on the generalization of information, communication and interaction. This generalization has increased with the paradigm of object orientation (OO). The development of object-oriented programming (OOP) started out in the beginning of the 1960s with the programming language Simula developed by Dahl and Nygaard (2001). In OOP, predefined objects make up the basic structure

72 digital material of the software. Software is seen as a collection of objects that work together. These objects relate to and act upon each other, and the interaction between these objects in the form of passing messages is the core of this programming para- digm. The difference between OOP and other paradigms is that within OOP, data and the operations that can manipulate these data are placed in one object instead of being separated. This meant a break with the paradigm of procedural program- ming. Within procedural programming software behavior is defined by proce- dures, functions, and subroutines. In OOP these behaviors are contained as meth- ods in the object itself. A method is a foundational element of an object class and is inextricably merged with the object itself. Methods can only be invoked by sending an appropriate message to the object (Weisfeld 2004). The object thus becomes the basis and starting point of the interaction. To illustrate this OO principle, let’s look again at the roles in WebCT. These roles function as predefined object classes. These classes are the highest level within OOP. In WebCT it is likely that a class is created for ‘student’. In this class general properties and methods are defined, and relations to other classes are established. When a class is instantiated, an object emerges in which these prop- erties are built in. Basically, a class can be seen as an empty form with predefined form fields; an object comes into existence when filling in or activating this form. The class ‘student’ then becomes an object with a name and other specific prop- erties, such as a student number. Within the class the object ‘student’ could be defined to have different methods at its disposal, for example ViewPage() or Re- trieveMediaLibraryObject(). It is also possible that the class ‘student’ may not have many methods itself but can be used as the basis for invoking methods of other classes such as the class ‘discussionforum’, in which methods like AddPosting(), DeletePosting(), etc. can be defined. By combining objects and methods, an inseparable assemblage is made be- tween an object (in this case ironically a human subject) and its possible interac- tions. This implies that there is only room for preplanned actions. Humans or other entities (objects) can only act if a preprogrammed plan exists and its execu- tion conditions are being met. Data and the manipulation of data are contained within the object itself, and changes in interactions are only possible when pre- programmed within the object. Interaction and the representation of interaction is located within the objects, and not on a procedural level. In doing so the beha- vior of humans can only be represented as fixed. Ad hoc interactions are usually not represented and thus become excluded. In software like WebCT, where flexibility in the form of the possibility for un- planned interactions is of great importance, this way of programming creates tension, to put it mildly. Moreover, this tension is not limited to the actual pro- gramming. As several scholars have shown, this is already at stake in the first stages of conceptualizing and modeling the software. As argued by Cecile Crut- digital objects in e-learning environments 73 zen for example, OOP has grown from a programming paradigm towards a broader field: an object-oriented approach and methodology for the interpreta- tion, representation and analysis of human interaction in computer science (Crut- zen 2001). This extended object-oriented approach (OOA) has gained popularity since the early 1990s, as shown by numerous publications on the topic and its use in computer science education (Booch 1993; Jacobson, Jonsson and Övergaard 1992; Rumbaugh et al. 1991). As Crutzen points out, the OO approach transferred the fear of doubt, as opposed to security, to the designed interaction model (Crut- zen 2001). Dominant ideas in software engineering are that software should be unambiguous and should have mastered complexity. When transferring this to a real world analysis, as it is called in computer science, complexity and ambiguity appear as problems which have to be tamed by abstraction. Abstraction techniques, such as generalization, classification, specialization, division, and separation, are fundamental for most modeling methods. According to Jacobson, such techniques are used to ‘decrease complexity on the object level’ (Jacobson et al. 1992, 254). Abstraction is seen as unavoidable when projecting and representing dynamic real world processes into modeling structures, but this implies a loss. Jacobson mapped out different (human) interaction diagrams, and showed how the use of abstraction techniques yields to ignoring dynamic aspects of the world. Hoare suggested, ‘Abstraction arises from recognition of similarities between certain objects, situations or processes in the real world and the decision to concentrate upon these similarities and to ignore for the time being the differ- ences’ (Hoare 1972, cited in Booch 1992, 39). In other words, these modeling methods force a search for similarities between human actors and processes, while ignoring the differences. Differences thus are downplayed, since they are technically hard to handle, especially when they tend to ambiguity. Ambiguity is precisely what has to be reduced in technical modeling. As Alan Davis puts it,

As systems become more complex however, it becomes increasingly difficult to explain behavior in an unambiguous manner. (...) A model simply provides us with a richer, higher level, and more semantically precise set of constructs than the underlying natural language. Using such a model reduces ambiguity, makes it easier to check for incompleteness, and may at times improve under- standability (Davis 1993, 213-214).

Hence, models based on the OO approach as the methodology for interpreting and analyzing human behavior are aimed at dissolving any doubt and ambiguity. In this approach, models appropriate for interaction analysis on a technical level are used for constructing planned interaction by humans, without proper consid- eration of the differences. From the OO perspective, the ambiguities that come with human interaction are inconveniences that have to be straightened out on the technical level.

74 digital material This fear of the ambiguity, complexity, and unpredictability of human behavior is at odds with a flexible learning environment that accommodates social-con- structivist learning. While the acknowledgment of complexity and unpredictabil- ity is of great importance, precisely these aspects are being abstracted and re- duced, at the expense of being able to cater to a social complexity. To return to the examples of roles in WebCT: once you are assigned a role, you will not be able to take on another role, or use methods (interactions) from other roles. There is no possibility for interactions that are not preconceived during the modeling stage of the environment and its objects. One may wonder whether a meaningful learning environment along the lines of social constructivism can be created at all, if this environment already presupposes what and how we learn in a very specific and static way, with predefined actions and objects. It would be interesting to get access to the actual process of how WebCT has been conceptualized and modeled, how the objects came to be defined, and which methods are contained in which objects with what consequences. How was the action/interaction planned, what pedagogical-based choices were made, and how did this influence both the programming paradigm and the modeling approach? An in-depth analysis of these issues could advance a next generation of learning environments beyond the sole use as course administration and repo- sitory. It may then eventually live up to its potential to transform learning pro- cesses in higher education.

Notes 1. Blackboard was at that time working on their first release of Blackboard CourseInfo, later renamed the Blackboard Learning System. 2. See the archived website of WebCT 1999 at http://web.archive.org/web/19991012032600 /http://www.webct.com/vision. 3. Parts of this section are a reworking of the article ‘Object Orientation’ by Cecile Crutzen and Erna Kotkamp (2008), in Software studies: A lexicon, edited by Matthew Fuller (Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press).

References Alexander, Dey. 2006. An accessibility audit of WebCT. Ausweb 08: The Fourteenth Australasian World Wide Web Conference. http://ausweb.scu.edu.au/aw02/papers/refereed/alexander/pa- per.html. Booch, Grady. 1994. Object-oriented analysis and design, with applications. Second edition. Red- wood City: Benjamin/Cummings. Chandler, Daniel. 1995. The act of writing: A media theory approach. Aberystwyth: University of Wales. Crutzen, Cecile. 2001. Interactie, een wereld van verschillen: Een visie op informatica vanuit het perspectief genderstudies. Dissertatie Open Universiteit Nederland, Heerlen.

digital objects in e-learning environments 75 Crutzen, Cecile, and Erna Kotkamp. 2008. Object orientation. In Software studies: A Lexicon, ed. Matthew Fuller. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dahl, Ole-Johan. 2001. The birth of object orientation: The Simula languages. http://heim.ifi.uio. no/~olejohan/papers/Birth-of-S.pdf. Davis, Alan M. 1993. Software requirements: Objects, functions and states. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Dalgaard, Christiaan. 2006. Social software: E-learning beyond learning management sys- tems. European Journal of Open, Distance and E-Learning 9 (2). http://www.eurodl.org/mate- rials/contrib/2006/Christian_Dalsgaard.htm. Dewey, John. 1910. How we think. Boston: D.C. Heath. Dewey, John. 1938/1998. Experience and education: The 60th anniversary edition. West Lafayette, India: Kappa Delta PI. Dworkin, M.S. 1959. Dewey on education. New York: Teachers College Press. Garrison, D.R., and Terry Anderson. 2003. E-learning in the 21st century: A framework for re- search and practice. London: Routledge Falmer. Goldberg, Murray. 2000a. Modest beginnings. http://www.webct.com/service/ViewCon- tent?contentID=2339374. Goldberg, Murray. 2000b. Alternative beginnings. http://www.webct.com/service/ViewContent?contentID=2339414. Freire, Paulo. 1972. Pedagogy of the oppressed. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Illinois Center for Information Technology Accessibility. 2008. WebCT Accessibility Inter- est Group. http://cita.disability.uiuc.edu/collaborate/webct/evaluations.php. Jacobson, Ivar, Magnus Christerson, Patrik Jonsson and Gunnar Övergaard. 1992. Object- oriented software engineering: A use case driven approach. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Pub- lishing Company. Kirkup, Gill. 2003. Cyborg teaching. In ICT’s in teaching and learning women’s studies: Perspec- tives and practices in Europe, eds. Sara Goodman, Gill Kirkup and Magda Michielsens. ATHENA/Universiteit Utrecht/Centre for Gender Studies, Lund University. Kotkamp, Erna, Sandra ten Horst and Pierre van Eijl. 2005. Online learning: (work) in progress. The case of European women’s studies & feminist pedagogies. Utrecht University/Athena/IVLOS. Laurel, Brenda. 1991. Computers as theatre. Boston: Addison-Wesley. Michielsens, Magda. 2003. Feminist pedagogy. In ICT’s in teaching and learning women’s stu- dies: Perspectives and practices in Europe, eds. Sara Goodman, Gill Kirkup and Magda Mi- chielsens. ATHENA/Universiteit Utrecht/Centre for Gender Studies, Lund University. Oudshoorn, N. and T. Pinch, eds. 2003. How users matter. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Richards, Jan. 2001. Conformance of WebCT v3.6 to W3C’s authoring tool accessibility guidelines 1.0. World Wide Web Consortium http://www.w3.org/WAI/AU/2002/WebCT3_6. html. Star, Susan Leigh. 1991. Invisible work and silenced dialogues in knowledge representa- tion. In Women, work and computerization: Understanding and overcoming bias in work and education, eds. Inger V. Eriksson, Barbara A. Kitchenham, and Kea Tijdens. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers. Sengers, Phoebe and Bill Gaver. 2005. Designing for interpretation. Proceedings of Human- Computer Interaction International. http://cemcom.infosci.cornell.edu/papers/sengers-ga- ver.design-for-interpretation.pdf.

76 digital material Simons, Robert-Jan. 1999. New learning: Three ways to learn in a new balance. Lifelong Learning in Europe 4 (1): 14-23. Sørensen, Birgitte Holm. 2006. When teachers become knowledge leaders. DPU Quarterly Newsletter: Knowledge, ideas, inspiration http://www.dpu.dk/site.aspx?p=8649&newsid1= 3965. Suchman, Lucy. 1994. Working relations of technology production and use. Computer Sup- ported Cooperative Work (CSCW) 2 (1-2): 21-39. University of Tasmania. 2006. Is WebCT Vista Accessible? http://www.utas.edu.au/accessibility/webct/is_webct_accessible.html. Volman, Monique. 2006. Jongleren tussen tradtie en toekomst. Inaugural speech. Amsterdam, Free University. WebCT. 2004. Administrators’ guide WebCT Vista™ 3.0: Technical communications. April 8. Weisfeld, Matt. 2004. Moving from procedural to object-oriented development. http:// www.developer.com/design/article.php/3317571.

digital objects in e-learning environments 77

Memory

The vanishing points of mobile communication

Imar de Vries

At the beginning of the 21st century, mobile communication devices are virtually ubiquitous. The attraction of their ability to potentially connect anywhere, any- time, to anyone or anything in the informational network, combined with an ongoing emphasis of the individual as the nexus of communication and enter- tainment, has sculptured the apparatuses into vital cultural artefacts. Their perva- siveness has rendered them ordinary and, in a sense, invisible; they seamlessly blend into almost every social activity imaginable. As such, they represent the strangest breed of new media we have come to study in the past ten years: instead of being subject to initial feverish ‘buzzification’, mobile communication devices have steadfastly insinuated themselves among us, and in contrast to the wide- spread academic enthusiasm that for instance the Internet generated in the 1990s, they sparked very little scholarly interest. However, in a remarkable reversal of the steps from hype to reality, mobile communication devices have increasingly been framed in utopian terms during the last few years. This is primarily visible in how dominant mobile communica- tion discourses advance a very specific notion of the all-important place that mo- bile devices should take in the overall media landscape. A detailed analysis of such discourses would show that what is stressed are the potential gains to be made in productivity, sociability, efficiency, safety, reassurance, and mutual un- derstanding; in other words, they stress communication improvement and its benefits, and present wireless communication technologies as the ultimate facil- itator. In many ads, press releases, and expressions of popular culture, a similar reasoning process can be distinguished, one that is repeated as a guiding mantra: mobile communication devices are the self-evident technological expressions of a presumed ‘natural’ progression in the quest for perfected communication. So, the pressing question that confronts us today is to what extent the infra- structures and everyday practices that co-construct the ways in which we experi- ence mobile communication actually sustain idealized ideas of communication. In one rather straightforward sense, the adoption speed alone suggests that there is a large overlap between what dreams of ideal communication prescribe and what mobile communication devices can offer. A quick glance at their break-

81 neck-paced integration into everyday life could easily lead to the conclusion that the age-old desire to bridge distances and instantaneously communicate with anyone and anywhere, which has expressed itself countless times in predictions and glorifications of new media, is now for many people more fulfilled than ever. But such an explanation would obscure the different reasons why people in var- ious demographic categories adopt mobile communication technologies, and ne- glect the inevitable problems and challenges that arise out of a shift towards a radical wireless connectedness. Mobile communication devices may indeed facil- itate the kinds of contact that fit idealized conceptions of the zenith of commu- nication, but do we experience them as such? Where are the kinks in the ideals, what are the paradoxes in today’s mobile communication condition? In this chapter, it is therefore my aim to make an analytical cut along the dis- courses of what I perceive as three of the most striking characteristics of current- day mobile communication, namely those of facilitating ubiquitous connectivity, fluid sociability, and real-time relief of anxiety. In these analytical cuts I will de- scribe how the various aspects of idealized communication run into paradoxes when confronted with everyday communication, and I will support my claims by using illustrative examples of research conducted by media and communication scholars who set out to empirically measure and gauge the impact of mobile com- munication devices. In the conclusion I will argue that the feverish embracement of mobile communication technologies forces both mobile telephone users and media scholars to realign their notions of concepts such as connectivity, , accountability, and information flows, if they are to understand the latent conse- quences of the dreams that are deeply rooted in media evolution.

Ubiquitous connectivity The obvious and single most defining characteristic of wireless communication technology, one that precedes and co-defines its other specific features, is that it renders space almost irrelevant as a variable in constituting mediated contact. And, due to contributing factors such as the standardisation of communication protocols, the ease of construction of basic technological frameworks, the port- ability of devices, the intuitive use of mobile telephones, and the high social and cultural value of personal communication devices, wireless services are steadfastly becoming truly ubiquitous indeed. What is significant about this process is that the supporting infrastructure is often made virtually invisible, as a conscious at- tempt to create and uphold the illusion that the wireless connection is ‘just there’, to be invoked at will to magically synchronise different space and time co-ordi- nates. As in early seventeenth-century fantasies of magnetised compass needles that would move in communicative rapport wherever they were, a certain sense of – and need for – telepathic immediacy pervades modern wireless communication

82 digital material technologies; just turn on the mobile device, and a connection will be guaranteed to exist almost instantly. With their omnipresence, wireless communication technologies thus facilitate the further compression of geographical space into what Manuel Castells (1996) calls the space of flows. In the space of flows, people, goods, and information are in a constant state of flux, moving between physical locations while being part of a dynamic network that is linked together through the use of communication tech- nologies. Because wireless communication devices radically alter the long-lasting relationship between communication nodes and fixed locations, in the space of flows, spatial vectors become increasingly heterogeneous, and thus simultaneous social interaction at a distance turns into a pervasive activity that can be engaged in anywhere, at any time. What follows is that we become more and more im- mersed in what Kenneth Gergen identifies as the ‘relational net’, in which every- one and everything can potentially link up (Gergen 2003, 111). Having a wireless communication device like a mobile telephone at one’s disposal implies having access to ever-present, real-time communication channels, and thus to the means to engage in dialogue or to disseminate information whenever and wherever one wants. A mobile telephone therefore provides a very strong psychological fix by supplying the abundant availability of communicative choice, the freedom to electro- nically connect and mediate knowledge, opinions, and desires; it is an apparatus of opportunity, a potential-rich portal. The tendency to depict mobile telephones as powerful devices that possess an unlimited connective potential is reflected by the strong emotional and cognitive investments that people make in wireless communication technologies. Mobile telephones have become considered as essential and vital extensions of the body, which is for instance vividly illustrated by their naming conventions. In many countries they are called ‘hand phones’, or their names refer to the fact that com- munication is ‘always on’ and can always be carried along on the body (Townsend 2002, 68-69). In one particular case, the name quite dramatically expresses the urge to attribute magical powers to the body extension: in Israel, a mobile tele- phone is called pelephone, after the name of Israel’s first cellular communications company, which literally means ‘wonder-phone’ (Thompson 2005, 21). Also, mo- bile telephones and their invisible but potentially present connections have now become so intimately integrated into our being, that many people experience feel- ings of panic when they find they have not brought their mobile telephone with them, or think it is lost (Vincent 2003, 220). The severance of the Hertzian umbi- lical cord is felt like an amputation that many would like to avoid.1 There are some paradoxical ramifications, however. True, from a socio-psycho- logical standpoint, wireless communication devices can be said to be perceived as the latest candidates to gratify the yearnings for wholeness and completeness that have continuously risen from our collective ‘technological imaginary’. And in- deed, at first, a perpetually connected state seems to be a perfect point of depar- the vanishing points of mobile communication 83 ture for establishing and managing all kinds of successful communication situa- tions, and thus for reaching the ideal goal of a common understanding. But a closer inspection of what is at hand reveals that merely increasing the opportu- nities to connect might actually not help in bringing people closer together in a utopian . George Myerson, for instance, comes to the conclusion that what he calls the process of ‘mobilisation’ is predominantly geared towards just making ‘basic contacts’ (Myerson 2001, 27). And indeed, there are research find- ings that can be interpreted as supporting Myerson’s claim: people generally spend less time calling on mobile telephones than they do on fixed phones (Li- coppe 2003, 175), they think of asynchronous as ‘quicker and more convenient than voice telephony’ (Ling 2004, 150), and they sometimes lock themselves in ‘tele-cocoons’ from which they only keep in touch with their most intimate friends, refraining from communicating with the outside world (Ito et al. 2005, 10-11). While some of these phenomena can be explained as user strategies aimed at managing billing systems and keeping costs low, the sugges- tion remains that mobile telephony and its infrastructure offer affordances that primarily invite what Christian Licoppe calls a ‘connected’ practice of interaction instead of a ‘conversational’ practice (2003, 174; 183). The ‘anywhere, anytime’ paradigm so much pervades interaction in everyday life, Licoppe found, that users prefer to think of their mobile communication practices mostly as intuitive when- ever-you-feel-like events, which often primarily serve to acknowledge the connec- tion that people share (ibid., 180-181). While such short communicative gestures are important elements in the shap- ing and maintenance of what can be called a ‘performative value’ in social rela- tionships (Green 2003, 207), they do add to swelling flows of information, mes- sages, and data, all of which affirm one’s connectedness up to a highly redundant level. If always being connected is what brings pure communication a step closer, it is also what foregrounds the communication paradox, and forces us to realize that pure communication is relentless in its intrusive nature. Studies have shown that when, for whatever reason, the times and places at which people can be con- tacted are extended to all possible environments, and those contacts become more frequent, a tension arises between on the one hand the desire and expec- tancy for immediate and unlimited access to others, and on the other hand the need to filter out and restrict incoming access requests in increasingly variable circumstances. Hence, the presence of a perpetual connection pressures users of wireless communication devices into managing all kinds of complicated commu- nication schemes (Sherry and Salvador 2002, 114-115), into employing inventive ways to cope with awkward social situations caused by disruptive incoming calls (Ling 2004, 123-143), and even into being deprived of sleep when they are kept awake at night by calls or text messages (Turrettini 2007). Discourses of wireless communication technologies, then, reflect how the compression of space by making connection nodes ubiquitous is of constitutive

84 digital material importance in the transformation of our understanding of communication. Across a wide range of demographic compositions, many social activities that used to rely on physical proximity or on the pre-arranged coordination of interac- tion are now reshaped into ad-hoc patterns of de-spatialised and heterogeneous contacts. With the shift towards more connectedness, we experience faster and more often than before that the desire for pure communication brings us both pleasure and discomfort. As Michael Arnold holds, the mobile telephone is Ja- nus-faced, a socio-technical system that is ‘not reducible to a direction or valence tipped with a single arrowhead, but better understood as a conflation of tangen- tial implications, at least some of which can be read as ironically and paradoxi- cally self-contradicting phenomena’ (Arnold 2003, 234). Because of mobile tele- phony, the paradox hiding in the desire for ideal communication becomes more articulated than ever.

Fluid sociability User accounts of reconfigurations of connectedness can provide a good view of how people seek to exploit the range of communicative affordances of wireless communication devices, and subsequently of how they experience what are pre- supposed to be idealized ideas of communication sparked by a desire for perpe- tual contact. This is especially visible in one particularly poignant theme that runs through these user accounts, which is the theme of social coordination, or rather what Richard Ling and Birgitte Yttri (2002) distinguish as a combination of ‘mi- cro- and hyper-coordination’. Micro-coordination is the type of nuanced instru- mental coordination typical of a significant part of mobile telephone use: trips that have already started can be redirected, people can call or send a text message to say they will be late, and meetings can be scheduled at a rather loosely defined time or location, only to become more definite when those who want to meet call each other while they are on their way (Ling and Yttri 2002, 143-144). Hyper-co- ordination adds an expressive layer to this instrumental use, both in the form of social and emotional communication (chatting, gossiping) and in the form of mobile etiquettes telling where mobile telephones should not be used or which models are in fashion (ibid., 140). Both types, then, are specifically about how to manage increasingly connected social networks: micro-coordination in a logisti- cal way that makes full use of enhanced communicative availability, and hyper- coordination in a cultural way that establishes the mobile telephone as today’s ne plus ultra means to create, maintain, and express social bonds and values. In user accounts of both types, elements of ideas of fulfilment through improved com- munication seep through voiced expectations and desires. First examining micro-coordination, Ling and Yttri find for instance that a strong need for connectedness is conveyed in many comments about the motives for using mobile telephones, aimed at making instrumental communication pro- the vanishing points of mobile communication 85 ceed as smoothly as possible. This instrumental approach to mobile telephony is widespread, if not constitutive. Ling and Yttri retrieved their data mainly from interviewing Norwegian teens, but similar attitudes towards the importance of being connected for instrumental reasons have already been registered in the ear- liest social analyses of the adoption of mobile telephones – most notably by Ko- pomaa (2000) – and have been identified as largely age-indifferent and cross-cul- tural phenomena (cf. Castells et al. 2007; Katz and Aakhus 2002) The emphasis in such mobile communication lies on orchestrating each other’s movements and positions in the space of flows to the point where they ultimately overlap and merge. This is only possible, however, if permanent availability is guaranteed and is incorporated in the ideology of mobile communication. The main motivation for using wireless communication devices in such cases lies in the assumption that if there are more opportunities to connect, it means that there will be an improvement in how we arrange social interactions, and thus in how social groups function as a whole. Of course, this assumption only holds when there is an agreement on how social interactions should actually be arranged, but in the mobile vision – availability solves everything, together is good – the mere possi- bility to contact anyone from anywhere is enough to suggest that such problems can easily be dealt with, simply by making another call or sending another text message. In hyper-coordination, the value of being connected is less related to efficient planning or dealing with practical issues, and more to achieving a certain status and maintaining intimate social bonds. Such communicative activities are about sharing experiences and confirming personal links, and can take the form of gos- siping, catching up on each other’s adventures, or exchanging symbolic gifts (see Johnsen 2003). These practices have been around for a long time, but the ubiqui- tous connectivity that the mobile telephone promises to deliver represents a new and particularly potent means to establish one’s identity and earn a meaningful place in the social hierarchy of family members and friends. A cross-cultural study done by Scott Campbell (2007) showed that people find that through mo- bile telephones, group connections are enhanced, conversations gain in intimacy, and opportunities for emancipatory praxis increase. The mobile telephone thus acts as an apparatus that ‘liberates’ expressive communication, largely because it makes opportunities for mediated dialogue and dissemination available to demo- graphic groups which did not readily enjoy that privilege before the age of wire- less communication devices, and because those people use mobile communica- tion as a way to actively establish and manage their own social position in relation to others. In addition, compared to the fixed telephone, the mobile telephone offers far more direct and individualised links to other people, properties that have quickly turned the device into the primary locus where one’s collection of social connections resides. Because mobile telephony is perceived as extending access to others to virtually infinite dimensions, the thought of being perpetually

86 digital material connected in the symbolically charged mobile network gives an increased existen- tial significance to relational ties. However, increased social connectedness comes with some unintended conse- quences that do not readily fit within idealized ideas of improved communication. The fact that mere connectivity has come to engulf present-day conceptions of communication has a compelling effect on our relational self, changing the per- ception of what it means to co-exist and communicate with others. The people we interact most with – those who reside in our more intimate social circles, like family members, friends, and colleagues – are now always only a phone call or text message away. As Kenneth Gergen has aptly diagnosed this social condition, we find ourselves continuously in a state of ‘absent presence’: physically absent, but electronically at hand (Gergen 2002). While the arrangement of absent pre- sence offers a psychologically reassuring feeling of closeness, perpetual connect- edness does not necessarily guarantee reaching a global coming together; Gergen notes that because communication with absent present others takes place via readily available channels, and therefore does not require a lot of effort or time in setting up, it tends to become simpler, shorter, and distributed among several fragmented micro-communities (Gergen 2003, 106-107). In addition, when peo- ple are inclined to enclose themselves in connections to their absent present so- cial network, they exhibit a diminished care for those outside of their communi- cative bubble (ibid., 109). What does markedly happen while the mobile network grows is that mediated communication is brought more out in the open, which presents us with new scenarios for experiencing being-with-others and strengthens the notion that anyone carrying a wireless communication device can, potentially, become part of anyone else’s technology-mediated network. The drawback of the ‘invasion’ of the public by the private, however, is that mobile communication behavior in public spaces often invades and disturbs social events and face-to-face conversa- tions with what is perceived as trivial and redundant chitchat or gossip. Now, gossip is the hard-wired social glue with which humans build and maintain social bonds, and mobile telephones are very apt at facilitating it anywhere and round- the-clock (see Fox 2001), but when experienced intrusively and only one-sided, it tends to aggravate companions, bystanders, and eavesdroppers, causing them to feel disempowered (Plant 2001, 31) or convinced that communication in the mo- bile age has become tawdry (Palen, Salzman and Youngs 2000, 207). This strained intermingling of public (outside) space with private (inside) space is what Kathleen Cumiskey (2005) calls the paradox of techno-intimacy: to our- selves, our mobile telephone is a highly convenient personal item and our own mobile communication behavior is perfectly acceptable, but we tend not to ap- preciate the same behavior and attitude towards the valuation of mobile commu- nication in others. I would argue that techno-intimacy, the ambivalent relation- ship between the desire to be connected and know all on the one hand, and the the vanishing points of mobile communication 87 need to stand apart from the multitude on the other, is itself a typical exponent of the paradox of idealized communication: an achieved complete togetherness will necessarily entail the loss of individuality, and mobile telephony will continue to stress this phenomenon.

Real-time relief of anxiety If we are to see mobile telephones as personal apparatuses full of communicative potential that, through their capability to transgress space and time, can maintain and strengthen bonds with primary social group members and make coordina- tion activities more ad-hoc and prominent, one of the following observations must be that the psychological fix attached to wireless communication relies heavily on the involvement of feelings of reassurance. For many, the emotional immediacy of the device has registered itself as an indispensable part of their everyday life, like the aura of a talisman worn for good luck and protection. And indeed, research has shown that a need for security, safety and reassurance is high on the list of initial reasons why people decide to buy wireless communica- tion devices, either for themselves or for their children and other loved ones. In a 1999 qualitative survey of 36 focus groups in six European countries, Richard Ling reports,

respondents were asked to what degree they agreed or disagreed with the statement ‘The mobile telephone is useful in an emergency’. We found that approximately 82% of the respondents were in complete agreement. There was no other attitudinal indicator with regard to mobile telephony that had such an extreme score (Ling 2004, 37).

Similar results were obtained from studies in the United States and Australia (ibid., 38) and from cross-cultural field studies undertaken in Berlin, San Fransis- co, Shanghai, and Tokyo (Chipchase 2005). The human fear for calamities evidently provides a sound reason why feelings of security and safety play a significant role in the adoption of wireless commu- nication technologies. The many folk-stories that tell of amazing rescue missions that involve the use of mobile telephones are adamant examples of how strong the desire is to stress that increased connectedness is a Good Thing. Idealized ideas of communication thrive on compelling anecdotes that ‘prove’ that progress has been made, and arguably nothing provides more conclusive evidence than accounts of lives saved or loved ones protected thanks to new communication technologies. So, we read in The Guardian that two British climbers caught in a blizzard on a Swiss mountain texted five friends, one of whom received the mes- sage in London at 5 am and immediately notified the rescue services in Geneva, who then finally rescued both climbers (Allison 2003). Similar stories tell of peo-

88 digital material ple being lost in a pass, shipwrecked on a boat off the coast of Indonesia, or stranded in the outback of Australia, who were all able to alert friends or family through their mobile telephones and consequently receive life-saving help (Tur- rettini 2004). Such stories readily feed myths of improved communication: with- out the new mobile communication devices, lives could have been severely im- paired, or even lost. However, increased security through networked wireless communication tech- nologies can only be guaranteed if people are willing to sacrifice some or even all control over when they can and should be reached, and by whom. Forceful evi- dence of this highly charged problem created by the need to relieve anxiety can be found in one of the more common social relationships where reassurance plays an important role, namely that between parents and adolescents. On the one hand, the mobile telephone offers parents the ability to let their children discover the world on their own, with the added safety of knowing that the teenagers can always call in case of an emergency. But, on the other hand, notions of surveil- lance and accountability are sure to follow from a heightened absent presence of others. When one’s whereabouts and activities are continuously under potential scrutiny, the mobile telephone becomes a mobile leash, exerting a strong influ- ence over its carrier. Thus, in their adolescent quest for independence and in response to overly concerned parents, teenagers often develop ‘parent manage- ment strategies’ with which they regulate their reachability (Green 2002, 39). While Green notes that the dominant association of terms like ‘surveillance’ and ‘accountability’ with state-controlled law enforcement does not do justice to the new ways in which individuals gather and share information, she holds that the proliferation of wireless communication technologies has ‘normalized’ the activity of checking up on others (ibid., 33). Through mobile devices, Green says, individuals ‘engage in routine monitoring of themselves and each other (...), and assume that others are self-regulating and accountable for their use of devices in both co-present and tele-present contexts’ (ibid., 43). Thus, everyday notions of what it means to feel reassured increasingly come to rely on knowing what others are up to, because the technological means to gain that knowledge are at one’s disposal at all times. As a result, questions of privacy become more manifest. As sociologist James Rule asserts, compared to older, mass media systems, today’s infrastructures of perpetual contact inherently generate more personalized infor- mation available to large institutions, corporations, and groups of individuals, making a future world of ‘total surveillance’ a conceivable reality (Rule 2002, 247). Although, like Green, Rule does not want to attach a specific value connota- tion to the term ‘surveillance’, he does point out that we should be cautious not to dismiss the dangers of this outlook too easily, or think that we can always escape observation by simply turning off our connections when we want to (ibid., 248). In the mobile age, perpetual contact becomes the norm, and participating without it difficult indeed. the vanishing points of mobile communication 89 These observations of ambivalence in mobile ‘reassurance technologies’ high- light the pitfall of the desire for pure communication: the more opportunities are created to connect and communicate, the more struggle there will be to hold on to established boundaries between the private and the public, between what can be known, should be known, and needs to be known. Wireless communication devices may be able to function as symbolic crowbars, breaking open social pat- terns of communicative behavior, but they can only do so at the expense of dis- closing a lot more information than people might care to consider. What is more, there will always be the nagging uncertainty whether extra information is truly enough for one to be relieved of all anxiety. In fact, by seeking reassurance through radical connectedness, another type of anxiety is created, one that stems from simultaneously being connected to someone far away and knowing that that distance cannot be bridged physically. This spatial discrepancy may not be so problematic when a call is made for trivial reasons, but when related to an emer- gency, the state of being ‘distant but present’ can instil overwhelming feelings of isolation and powerlessness. A fickle balance between fear and relief manifests itself in the continuous search for reassurance; when Henrietta Thompson for instance states that mobile ‘phones offer the best peace of mind it is possible to get’, she does this in the context of Israel’s continuous preparedness for terrorist attacks, where with ‘the fear of [terrorism] always present, the need to commu- nicate is paramount [and] people need to be able to check-up on their loved ones on short notice’ (Thompson 2005, 55). So, not only does the longing for perpetual contact create privacy issues, it also multiplies instances in which people are connected in extreme emotional circum- stances while being physically apart. The torment of such ‘intense immediacy’,as James E. Katz (2006, 104) calls it, becomes adamantly clear in situations of life and death. Imagine, for instance, the conversation between the stranded moun- taineer and his wife, whom he had called to say he was going to die (Cusk 2001). Or think of those other, highly profiled accounts of mobile calls in which Eros met Thanatos, made during and after the terrorist attacks in New York on Sep- tember 11, 2001. People in the hijacked planes and those trapped inside the struck towers called family members to tell them that they loved them, sometimes right up to the moment when they died. After the towers had collapsed, rescue workers could hear people from under the wreckage use their mobile telephones to call for help, not seldom in vain. Most dreadful are the accounts of unanswered mo- bile telephones ringing in the rubble, or even in body bags.2 All these cases vividly illustrate how feelings of reassurance and distress can come palpably close to merging into a single sentiment, how wireless communication technologies can augment both intimacy and isolation to such a degree that pure communication is indeed virtually reached, in all its real-time glory and ugliness.

90 digital material Conclusion As I aimed to show in the analyses of three of the most striking characteristics of mobile communication, a complex, ambivalent pattern can be distinguished in the ongoing process of mobilization. By increasing connectedness, transforming sociability, and opening up access to and the production of personal information, mobile communication devices fervently confront us with the paradoxes of pure communication, bringing us closer to the technological fulfilment of the desire for immediate togetherness, but at the same time letting us experience its ruthless blending of all actors involved. In all their ordinariness, mobile communication devices have showed and continue to show the potential to stealthily yet radically alter our perception of what it means to co-exist with others in a connected so- ciety. This also means that our traditional understandings of concepts such as avail- ability, privacy, accountability, safety, and security, which are all in particular ways dependent upon dominant modes of media deployment, will inevitably have to be rethought in order to reflect what it means to be in perpetual contact. In today’s mobile communication condition, where the ability to ‘just call’ or ‘just look up’ is increasingly perceived as the primary solution to all kinds of problems, it becomes difficult – or even nonsensical – to think of people not being con- nected, or of information not being available. Not only will the social and politi- cal-economic pressure to join the growing interconnected communication net- work become more intense, the prevalent ideal of a fully transparent society will also force us to realize that everyone and everything is becoming subsumed with- in a single, all-encompassing communication regime, when it continues to be used as the fundamental guiding principle for new media developments. Unless we come to grips with the profound consequences inherent in the proliferation of mobile communication, we will fail to adequately address concerns of privacy, accountability, and safety in the connected society.

Notes 1. To illustrate this further, during the short-lived offer in 2000 by several mobile tele- phone operators to provide free calls in the evenings and on weekends, some people even chose to maintain a constant connection through their mobile telephones, and listen to each other sleeping (Licoppe 2003, 177). 2. Similar stories of ‘ringing body bags’ could be heard after the Madrid terrorist attacks in 2004 (BBC News 2004) and the Virginia Tech shootings in 2007 (King 2007).

References Allison, Rebecca. 2003. Climbers on Alpine ridge rescued by text message. The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/uk_news/story/0,3604,1057271,00.html. the vanishing points of mobile communication 91 Arnold, Michael. 2003. On the phenomenology of technology: The ‘Janus-faces’ of mobile phones. Information and Organization 13 (4): 231–256. BBC News. 2004. European press ask ‘Why?’. BBC News International. http://news.bbc.co.uk/ 2/hi/europe/3504032.stm. Campbell, Scott. 2007. A cross-cultural comparison of perceptions and uses of mobile telephony. New Media & Society 9 (2): 343-363. Castells, Manuel. 1996. The information age: Economy, society and culture, Volume 1: The rise of the network society. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Castells, Manuel, Mireia Fernandez-Ardevol, Jack Linchuan Qiu, and Araba Sey. 2007. Mo- bile communication and society: A global perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chipchase, Jan. 2005. Why do people carry mobile phones? Future perfect. http://www.jan- chipchase.com/blog/archives/2005/11/mobile_essentia.html. Cumiskey, Kathleen. 2005. ‘Can you hear me now?’: Paradoxes of techno-intimacy result- ing from the public use of mobile communication technology. In A sense of place: The global and the local in mobile communication, ed. Kristóf Nyíri, 151-158. Vienna: Passagen. Cusk, Rachel. 2001. Finding words. The Guardian. http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2001/ sep/14/september11.politicsphilosophyandsociety1. Fox, Kate. 2001. Evolution, alienation and gossip: The role of mobile telecommunications in the 21st century. Social Issues Research Centre. http://www.sirc.org/publik/gossip.shtml. Gergen, Kenneth. 2002. The challenge of absent presence. In Perpetual contact: Mobile com- munication, private talk, public performance, eds. James E. Katz and Mark Aakhus, 227-241. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. —. 2003. Self and community in the new floating worlds. In Mobile democracy: Essays on society, self and politics, ed. Kristóf Nyíri, 103-114. Vienna: Passagen. Green, Nicola. 2002. Who’s watching whom? Monitoring and accountability in mobile relations. In Wireless world: Social and interactional aspects of the mobile age, eds. Barry Brown, Nicola Green, and Richard Harper, 32-45. London: Springer. —. 2003. Outwardly mobile: Young people and mobile technologies. In Machines that become us: The social context of personal communication technology, ed. James E. Katz, 201-217. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Ito, Mizuko, Daisuke Okabe, and Misa Matsuda. 2005. Personal, portable, pedestrian: Mobile phones in Japanese life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Johnsen, Truls Erik. 2003. The social context of the mobile phone use of Norwegian teens. In Machines that become us: The social context of personal communication technology, ed. James E. Katz, 161-169. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Katz, James, and Mark Aakhus, eds. 2002. Perpetual contact: Mobile communication, private talk, public performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Katz, James. 2006. Magic in the air: Mobile communication and the transformation of social life. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. King, John. 2007. Cell phones of dead still rang. CNN.com – Anderson Cooper 360° Blog. http:// edition.cnn.com/CNN/Programs/anderson.cooper.360/blog/2007/04/volunteer-contri- butes-what-he-can-body.html. Kopomaa, Timo. 2000. The city in your pocket: Birth of the mobile . : Gaudeamus.

92 digital material Licoppe, Christian. 2003. Two modes of maintaining interpersonal relations through tele- phone: From the domestic to the mobile phone. In Machines that become us: The social context of personal communication technology, ed. James E. Katz, 171-185. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Ling, Richard. 2004. The mobile connection: The cell phone’s impact on society. San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann. Ling, Richard, and Birgitte Yttri. 2002. Hyper-coordination via mobile phones in Norway. In Perpetual contact: Mobile communication, private talk, public performance, eds. James E. Katz and Mark Aakhus, 139-169. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Myerson, George. 2001. Heidegger, Habermas and the mobile phone. London: Icon Books. Palen, Leysia, Marilyn Salzman, and Ed Youngs. 2000. Going wireless: Behavior & practice of new mobile phone users. Proceedings of the 2000 ACM conference on computer supported cooperative work, 201-210. Plant, Sadie. 2001. On the mobile: The effects of mobile telephones on social and individ- ual life. Motorola. http://www.motorola.com/mot/doc/0/234_MotDoc.pdf. Rule, James. 2002. From mass society to perpetual contact: Models of communication technologies in social context. In Perpetual contact: Mobile communication, private talk, public performance, eds. James E. Katz and Mark Aakhus, 242-254. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press. Sherry, John, and Tony Salvador. 2002. Running and grimacing: The struggle for balance in mobile work. In Wireless world: Social and interactional aspects of the mobile age, eds. Barry Brown, Nicola Green, and Richard Harper, 108-120. London: Springer. Thompson, Henrietta. 2005. Phone book: A handy guide to the world’s favourite . Lon- don: Thames & Hudson. Townsend, Anthony. 2002. Mobile communications in the twenty-first century city. In Wireless world: Social and interactional aspects of the mobile age, eds. Barry Brown, Nicola Green, and Richard Harper, 62-77. London: Springer. Turrettini, Emily. 2004. Lost hikers use text messaging to gain help. Textually.org. http:// www.textually.org/textually/archives/2004/07/004683.htm. —. 2007. Cell phones cause insomnia. Textually.org. http://www.textually.org/textually/ar- chives/2007/08/016895.htm. Vincent, Jane. 2003. Emotion and mobile phones. In Mobile democracy: Essays on society, self and politics, ed. Kristóf Nyíri, 215-224. Vienna: Passagen.

the vanishing points of mobile communication 93

The work of art in the age of digital recombination

Jos de Mul

Artists, from the prehistoric painters who engraved and painted figures on cave walls to new media artists whose work depends on computer technologies, have always used media. Media, used here in the broad sense as ‘means for presenting information’1, are not innocent instruments. Ever since Kant’s Copernican revolu- tion, we know that experience is constituted and structured by the forms of sensi- bility and the categories of human understanding, and after the so-called linguis- tic and mediatic turns in philosophy, it is generally assumed that media play a crucial role in the configuration of the human mind and experience. Media are interfaces that mediate not only between us and our world (designation), but also between us and our fellow man (communication), and between us and ourselves (self-understanding). Aesthetic experience is no exception: artistic media are in- terfaces that not only structure the imagination of the artist, but the work of art and the aesthetic reception as well.2 In this paper I aim to contribute to this reflection by analyzing the way the computer interface constitutes and structures aesthetic experience. My point of departure will be Walter Benjamin’s ‘The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction’, first published in the Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung in 1936. In this epochal essay Benjamin investigates how mechanical reproduction transforms the work of art, claiming that in this ontological transformation the cult value, which once characterized the classical work of art, has been replaced by exhibition value. The thesis I will defend in this paper is, first, that in the age of digital recombination, the database constitutes the ontological model of the work of art and, secondly, that in this transformation the exhibition value is being replaced by what we might call manipulation value. Before I turn to Benjamin’s notions of cult value and exhibition value, I want to make a short remark concerning the scope of Benjamin’s essay. Though the title of his work promises an analysis of art, the scope is actually much wider. It is also an essay on economics, politics and religion. And on a deeper level, connecting these and yet other domains, it deals with a fundamental ontological change, a transformation of human experience, closely connected to the of the reproduction of nature and culture. Likewise, the scope of my continuation of

95 Benjamin’s analysis in the age of the digital recombination is broader than art or aesthetics. It deals with the digital manipulation of nature and culture that char- acterizes the present ‘age of informatization’ (De Mul 1999).

Cult value vs. exhibition value Although Benjamin emphasizes at the beginning of his essay that the work of art in principle has always been reproducible, in principle he states that mechanical reproduction presents us with a new phenomenon. With the emergence of wood- cut graphics, engraving and etching in the Middle Ages and lithography in the beginning of the 19th century, mechanical reproduction became a major artistic technique. However, it was only with the invention and the swift dissemination of photography and film that mechanical reproduction became the dominant cultur- al interface. Before that time the work of art’s dominant type was characterized by unique- ness (Einmaligkeit) and singularity (Einzigkeit) in time and space. The original work of art is here and now: ‘Even the most perfect reproduction of a work of art is lacking in one element: its presence in time and space, its unique existence at the place where it happens to be’ (Benjamin 1969). There is only one Mona Lisa, and when we want to see this painting, we have to go to the Louvre in Paris (Figure 13). According to Benjamin the unique existence of the work of art determines the history to which it is subject throughout the time of its existence. This includes, for example, the changes which it may have suffered in its physical condition over the years as well as the various changes in its ownership.

The traces of the first can be revealed only by chemical or physical analyses which it is impossible to perform on a reproduction; changes of ownership are subject to a tradition which must be traced from the situation of the origi- nal. The presence of the original is the prerequisite to the concept of authenti- city. (…) The authenticity of a thing is the essence of all that is transmissible from its beginning, ranging from its substantive duration to its testimony to the history which it has experienced.

Another word that Benjamin uses to designate the material and historical authen- ticity and authority of the unique work of art is ‘aura’. Because of this aura, the unique work of art can easily become an object of a magical or religious cult.

We know that the earliest art works originated in the service of a ritual – first the magical, then the religious kind. It is significant that the existence of the work of art with reference to its aura is never entirely separated from its ritual function. In other words, the unique value of the ‘authentic’ work of art has its

96 digital material basis in ritual, the location of its original use value. This ritualistic basis, how- ever remote, is still recognizable as secularized ritual even in the most profane forms of the cult of beauty.

In a footnote Benjamin introduces the concept of cult value, and he connects it with its aura. In this context he also gives an intriguing definition of the latter concept:

The definition of the aura as a ‘unique phenomenon of a distance however close it may be’ represents nothing but the formulation of the cult value of the work of art in categories of space and time perception. Distance is the opposite of closeness. The essentially distant object is the unapproachable one. Unap- proachability is indeed a major quality of the cult image. True to its nature, it remains ‘distant, however close it may be.’ The closeness which one may gain from its subject matter does not impair the distance which it retains in its appearance.

When we – anachronistically – apply a key concept of the new media studies to Benjamin’s analysis, we might say that the auratic work of art acts as an interface between the sensible and the supersensible, that is: between the physical materi- ality of the work of art and its meaningful history. Although it may be close in its material presence – we could even touch the Mona Lisa if there were no glass separating it from its visitors in the Louvre – and as such it brings us in close contact with its history, at the same time we experience the historical tradition in which it is embedded and from which it derives its meaning as an unbridgeable distance. It is important to notice that in the auratic work of art the sensible and the supersensible, the material signifier and the spiritual meaning, are inseparably linked with one another. As such, the auratic work of art, as Gadamer states in The relevance of the beautiful in connection with a short but illuminating discussion of Benjamin’s essay, can be conceived of as a symbol.4 The destruction of an aura- tic work destroys the distant presence of its history as well. For that reason the destruction of an auratic work of art is generally understood as an act of blas- phemy – independent of whether it has a religious content or not. It is also important to notice that for Benjamin the experience of aura is not restricted to historical objects such as works of art. Benjamin also applies the concept of aura to natural objects. When we watch a mountain range on the hor- izon or a branch casting its shadow over us, we also experience the aura – in this case: the natural history – of those mountains, of that branch. We could also think about the historical sensation we experience when we look at, or touch, a fossil, for instance the skeleton of a dinosaur.

the work of art in the age of digital recombination 97 One of the basic claims of Benjamin’s ‘The work of art’ is that in the age of mechanical reproduction by means of print, photography and film, we experience a radical loss of aura:

That which withers in the age of mechanical reproduction is the aura of the work of art. This is a symptomatic process whose significance points beyond the realm of art. One might generalize by saying: the technique of reproduc- tion detaches the reproduced object from the domain of tradition. By making many reproductions it substitutes a plurality of copies for a unique existence. And in permitting the reproduction to meet the beholder or listener in his own particular situation, it reactivates the object reproduced.

One might say that mechanical reproduction of images brings things closer, spa- tially and temporally. In order to watch the Mona Lisa, I no longer have to travel to Paris, I can look up a reproduction in an art magazine or on my mobile phone with an Internet connection, immediately, here and now (Figure 2). Uniqueness and permanence of the auratic object are being replaced by transitoriness and reproducibility. In a reproduction of the Mona Lisa, the reproduction still refers to the original work of art – something Andy Warhol smartly capitalizes on in his reproductions of Leonardo’s famous painting (see Figure 3). Actually, in the media of mechan- ical reproduction the whole distinction between original and copy loses its mean- ing. No copy of a photo or a movie is more original than the others. Whereas traditionally things were first produced and then reproduced, in the age of me- chanical reproduction things are being made directly with an eye to reproduction: ‘To an ever greater degree the work of art reproduced becomes the work of art designed for reproducibility’ (ibid). According to Benjamin, together with the aura, the cult value of artworks will gradually vanish. For emotional or economical reasons one can, of course, try to conserve the cult value. For example by printing a photograph in a limited edi- tion, having the photographer put his signature on it, or by promoting an actress as a unique movie star. Actually these ‘cheats’ only confirm the loss of the aura of the work itself. That does not mean, however, that the mechanical copy doesn’t have value at all. Rather, in photography and film, the cult value gives way to exhibition value, which is precisely situated in the endless reproduction of the co- pies. This especially becomes clear in the case of celebrities like Paris Hilton, who do not have any unique talents but are just ‘famous for being famous’. In the same vein, the success of politicians strongly depends on how mediagenic they are, that is: on their exhibition value. The fact that in the USA even a B-film actor like Reagan can become president is an ironic illustration of Benjamin’s fore- sight.

98 digital material Benjamin’s essay has melancholic undertones. When he states that the aura emanates for the last time from the early photographs in the fleeting expression of a human face, he not only mourns the loss of the ‘incomparable beauty’ and ‘melancholy’ of these early photographs, but also the notion that we experience the human being itself as losing its aura. However, at the same time – and this shows the fundamental ambiguity of the essay – Benjamin also expresses his be- lief that the ‘mechanical media’ possess a fundamental democratic and even revo- lutionary potential. Not only do they enable ‘access for all’, they also enable the progressive artist to ‘politicize the arts’ and mobilize the masses against the fas- cist ‘aesthetization of politics’ (ibid.). By now we know that mass media can in- deed mobilize masses, though more often in the direction of the shopping mall than in the direction of the government building. The development of mechanical reproduction can neither simply be hailed as cultural progress nor simply doomed as cultural decline. Mechanical reproduc- tion discloses the world in a new way, bringing along both new opportunities and new dangers. We should keep this fundamental ambiguity of the develop- ment of media in mind when we turn our attention to digital recombination.

Database ontology No other text has been quoted so often in new media studies as Benjamin’s ‘The work of art’ (Davis 1995; Harvey 1989; Thomson 1995; Gumbrecht and Marrinan 2003; Benjamin 2005). This is not surprising, as his prophetic vision only seems to have gained in relevance in the age of digital recombination. However, although the computer is still a mechanical machine, we should not simply equate digital reproduction with mechanical reproduction (and for that reason I prefer the phrase ‘digital recombination’). Although the computer can simulate all kinds of classical mechanical machines and media, such as a , a sound recorder, or a device for the montage of images, it has some unique med- ium-specific characteristics that justify the claim that it represents a new stage in the development of media. Understood as a medium, the computer is not one but many. Artists use com- puters in many different ways to produce, store, display and distribute so-called ‘new media art’. As a means of production, for example, computers enable them to create digital images and sounds, to build interactive installations, to design multimedia websites, or to program self-evolving art forms. However, the thesis I want to defend is that on a fundamental level all media art works share some basic characteristics. Although concrete media art works may differ from each other in many different respects – and for that reason show a family resemblance rather than a single essence – on a fundamental level they all share the four basic operations of persistent storage, an integral part of almost all computer software. This ABCD of consists of the operations Add, Browse, Change, and the work of art in the age of digital recombination 99 Destroy.5 Together these four operations – which correspond to the structured query language (SQL) commands Insert, Select, Update, and Delete – constitute the dynamic elements of what we might call a database ontology. In a basic sense the word ‘database’ can refer to any collection of items that is ordered in one way or another. In computing, a database can be defined as a structured collection of data records that is stored in a computer, so that a soft- ware program can consult it to answer queries. With the four basic operations all possible combinations of records can be retrieved in principle. Database ontology is dynamic, because the data elements can be constantly combined, decombined, and recombined. In reality, not all databases are that flexible. The traditional ‘flat’ paper data- base, a phone book for example, is rather inflexible. The alphabetic order of the names is fixed, and to update the list you have to reprint the entire book. A card- index box, consisting of cards with a limited number of fields for the input of information (for example name, address, and phone number) would already be more flexible regarding updating. Reorganizing this database – for example to group the records per country for a mailing – is possible, but would consume a lot of time. Although an electronic version of a flat database – a spreadsheet – could speed up the sorting of the data, it remains inflexible with regard to the creation and exploration of structural relationships between the data. From the on new types of electronic databases have been developed, the hierarchical model in the 1950s, the network model in the 1960s and the rela- tional model in the 1970s. The last model, which is based on predicate logic and set theory (Codd 1970), contains multiple tables, each consisting of a ‘flat’ data- base of rows and columns. The relational database as a whole is multidimen- sional, and for that reason its complexity cannot be represented on a flat plane and often not even in a three-dimensional model. One of the strengths of the relational model is that, in principle, any value occurring in two different records (belonging to the same table or to different tables) implies a relationship between those two records. Relational databases are extremely flexible, because they en- able the users to define queries that were not anticipated by the database de- signers. The current development of database models shows a tendency to even more flexibility and a rapidly growing range of applications. Database applications nowadays span virtually the entire range of computer software, ranging from mainframe databases for administrative purposes and multimedia encyclopedias on cd-roms to search engines, wikis and other Web 2.0 applications on the Inter- net. However, the impact of databases is not restricted to the world of computing. Databases often function as material metaphors. This happens when they evoke acts in the material world (Hayles 2002). Examples of these are biotechnological data- bases used for genetic engineering, or databases implemented in industrial ro-

100 digital material bots, enabling mass customization. In addition, databases may create a surplus of meaning, on top of their instrumental function (cf. Van den Boomen, in prepara- tion). In that case the database functions as a conceptual metaphor which structures our experience of ourselves and of the world. The psychologist Maslov once noticed that for those who only have a hammer, everything appears to be a nail. In a world in which the computer has become the dominant technology – worldwide more than 50 billion processors are doing their job – everything is becoming a database. As Manovich states, databases have become the dominant cultural form of the computer age (Manovich 2002, 219).6 They are ‘onto-logical machines’ that shape both our world and our world view. Benjamin argues in his essay that in the age of mechanical reproduction, everything becomes an object for mechanical reproduction. This has contributed to what is sometimes called a mechanization of the world view. In the age of digital databases, everything – nature and culture alike – becomes an object for recombination and manipulation. Let us take genetic engineering as an example. The evolution of life on earth is no longer regarded as a natural history determined by the struggle for life and the survival of the fittest (as in classic Darwinism), but rather as one possible (contin- gent) trajectory through the gene pool. Actually, this biological database contains an infinite number of virtual organisms and life forms (trajectories), which in principle can be actualized. Although not yet as spectacular as in Spielberg’s Jur- assic Park or in science-fiction films such as Robocop, our world is increasingly being populated with life forms created with database technologies. Why not, for example, create a mouse with a human ear on its back or design a fluorescent rabbit to watch it (Figures 4 and 5)? Unlike Jurassic Park and Robocop, these examples are not the products of mere digital imaging. The mouse with the engineered human ear implanted on its back is the result of a medical experiment, carried out by Charles Vacanti at the Uni- versity of Massachusetts Medical Center in 1995, whereas the fluo rabbit was ‘cre- ated’ by the Brazilian artist Eduard Kac, who commissioned the ‘transgenic’ bun- ny from a French lab, where scientists injected green fluorescent protein (GFP) of a Pacific jellyfish into the ovum of an Albino rabbit (Vesna 2007). Both Vacanti’s and Kac’s experiments have lead to heated ethical debates. In the case of Kac’s fluo rabbit, the question was also raised whether this ‘work’ can be called a work of art. In this sense the rabbit provokes similar questions as did, about ninety years ago, Duchamp’s ready-mades, such as L.H.O.O.Q., a cheap postcard-sized reproduction of the Mona Lisa, upon which Duchamp drew a mus- tache and a goatee (Figure 6). Both Duchamp’s L.H.O.O.Q. and Kac’s fluo rabbit raise the question of whether they are a work of art since they both employ a new, seemingly non-artistic medium of production as a means for artistic expression, questioning the very distinction between artistic and non-artistic objects. While this may elucidate the reason for posing this aesthetical question, it does not the work of art in the age of digital recombination 101 provide an answer to it. As Benjamin’s essay suggests an answer, we will return to it once more.

Database aesthetics and politics In ‘The work of art’ Benjamin remarks that there is no timeless answer to the question of whether a particular object should be regarded as a work of art. An object that was once an instrument of magic could later come to be recognized as a work of art. In the same way, Benjamin suggests, ‘by the absolute emphasis on its exhibition value the work of art becomes a creation with entirely new func- tions, among which the one we are conscious of, the artistic function, later may be recognized as incidental’ (Benjamin 1969). Whereas in the age of mechanical reproduction it was already becoming diffi- cult to distinguish between the artistic and non-artistic functions of the reproduc- tion – hence, for example, the aesthetization of politics and the politization of art which plays such an important role in Benjamin’s essay – in the age of digital recombination, the distinction seems to get blurred altogether. Let me illustrate this by discussing a recent database work of the Dutch computer artist and video jockey Geert Mul. Commissioned by the Dutch Photo Museum in Rotterdam, he built the interactive installation W4 (WHO, WHAT, WHEN, WHERE).7 This installa- tion consists of a database containing 80,000 photographs from the digital ar- chive of the museum and four posts that function as a filter (Figure 7). With the help of the functions who, what, when and where, the user can explore the entire digitalized collection. For example, one can investigate all photographs of flowers made in Germany in 1936. Or all pictures of the Mona Lisa made between 1900 and 1920. The installation can be regarded as an interface designed to enable the visitors to display the collection. Every visitor of the museum becomes a curator, able to create her own exhibitions. At the same time it is a powerful interactive artwork which transforms the visitors into VJs who create rhythmic compositions of photographs. What makes this installation both a brilliant example of human-computer in- terface design and an autonomous work of art is its manipulation value. In the age of digital recombination, the value of an object depends on the extent of its open- ness for manipulation.8 For a contemporary scholar, a ‘databased’ version of the collected works of a philosopher is of much greater value than a traditional paper edition, because it enables her to execute all kinds of sophisticated searches, to investigate implicit relationships between the texts, and to make new recombina- tions of existing texts (De Mul, 2008). The aesthetic quality of a work strongly depends on the elegance of the structure of the database and its user interface.9 As soon as the database play becomes a goal in itself, the database becomes an autonomous work of art. As W4 shows, a database can be both an instance of applied user interface design and an autonomous work of art.

102 digital material As the number of recombinations of a database is almost infinite, the work of art in the age of digital recombination brings about a return of the aura. Espe- cially in those cases where the user is enabled to change the contents of the data- base and to insert new elements in the database, each query becomes a unique recombination. And as a consequence, the digitally recombined work of art re- gains something of its ritual dimension. It becomes an interface between the sen- sible and the supersensible again, now no longer located in the history of the work, but in its virtuality, that is: the intangible totality of possible recombina- tions. In the domain of culture we could think, for example, of websites such as Mega Mona Lisa, where vistors are being invited to create and discuss their unique own version of Leonardo’s Mona Lisa (Figure 8). In these versions we witness ‘the return of the aura’. However, it is a return with a twist: what we experience is a series of ‘original, auratic copies’ (Davis 1995). The return is also twisted because digitally manipulated objects are even more transient than mechanical reproduc- tions. Because of their manipulability, digital objects seem to be inherently un- stable, like the performing arts process rather than product (cf. Bolle 1992). As already noted, database ontology is not restricted to the domain of culture, but applies to nature as well. In both domains database ontology shows a post- historical character. In the age of digital recombination, dinosaurs are no longer exclusively extinct species, they have become a future possibility as well.10 Again, the result will be a series of ‘auratic copies’. After all, as they will appear in a drastically changed environment, they will unavoidably be a different species. Like Benjamin we may ask how such digitally recombined works can function as political works of art. Digital recombination as a means of production is no less political than mechanical reproduction. Power, political power included, is becoming increasingly dependent on the ability to manipulate information. One of the most prophetic claims in Benjamin’s essay is that in the age of mechanical reproduction, the success of political leaders became increasingly dependent on their exhibition value. However, in the western world Ronald Reagan was prob- ably the last president who could still mainly rely on his exhibition value. In the age of digital manipulation, politicians are becoming more and more dependent on their manipulation value. We could think of Bush’s intended manipulation of computer-mediated elections, or the rhetorically motivated recombination of images in Geert Wilders’s propaganda movie Fitna, but also of the non-criminal everyday recombination of data in order to create, control and evaluate financial, economical and social policies. Yet for a work of art to be political, it is not enough to be digitally recombined. Digitally recombined works of art differ from other digitally recombined objects because they have a reflective quality as well. A work of art challenges its recipi- ents by directing their attention to the medium itself. Works of art are not politi- cal because they manipulate politics, but because they reflect (on) the politics of

the work of art in the age of digital recombination 103 manipulation. Only insofar as the fluo rabbit makes us reflect on such media politics can it be called political art.11 A work that invites the spectator to political reflection is Geert Mul’s Match of the day (2006), part of an art works database series, entitled Split Representations.In the case of Match of the day, ‘a computer collects images from about thirty interna- tional satellite television channels at random intervals. During the night, image- recognition software analyzes the recorded images. It compares television news with television commercials. The software compares every image with every other single image stored in the computer, checking 5000 specified characteristics in each image. After 1,000,000,000 comparisons, the computer generates a list. Images that share the most characteristics appear in pairs at the top of this list. The artist then selects a few pairs of images out of the hundreds of pairs of images, which according to the computer make a good visual match. In a daily e- mail-series subscribers receive this selection: the match of the day’ (Figure 9, Mul 2006). By combining television news with television commercials, the matches of the day represent the current socio-economic situation of the western world. On this level it is a representation and manipulation of politics. However, the recipient also gradually becomes aware of the politics of representation and manipulation. ‘The computer does not “understand” the images, it just applies pixel statistics. For the human eye visual similarity is something else than pixel statistics. Because of our inability to “see” without interpretation we attach “meaning” to everything we see. This becomes especially evident when similar images appear to have a different or even contrary meaning. The “matches” found by the computer and selected by the artist, trigger sensations of poetry, humor, beauty or disgust’ (Mul 2006). Gradually, we become aware of the inapproachability of the workings of a tech- nology that we have invented. And we might even start to reflect on the non-hu- man and maybe even inhuman character of this new medium. Or on the possibil- ity that it will gradually outstrip our skills to add, browse, change and destroy. And that we might become the ultimate object of digital manipulation. In ‘The work of art’ Benjamin worries about the fact that mechanical reproduction alie- nates human beings. Realizing the possibility that we might be the first species that creates its own successors in the evolution of life and by doing so makes itself redundant, Benjamin’s worries may soon become an object for nostalgia.

Notes 1. We should realize that the concept ‘media’ covers many different categories by which we define media and differentiate them from other media. Even when we restrict our- selves to so-called ‘new media’, the word ‘media’ might refer to a variety of different things, such as material carriers, production technologies or distribution apparatus.

104 digital material 2. This view does not imply media determinism. ‘Technology does not determine society: it embodies it. But neither does society determine technological innovation: it uses it’ (Castells 1996, 5). In other words: media develop in a constant dialectical interplay with other cultural domains, such as science, economy and politics, and cannot be ab- stracted from human action and decisions. 3. The illustrations are available online: http://www2.eur.nl/fw/hyper/illustrations.htm. 4. ‘I propose that the symbolic in general, and especially the symbolic in art, rests upon an intricate interplay of showing and concealing. In its irreplaceability, the work of art is no mere bearer of meaning – as if the meaning could be transferred to another bearer. Rather the meaning of the work of art lies in the fact that it is there’ (Gadamer 1986, 33). 5. These four basic operations are also referred to with the acronyms CRUD (Create, Read, Update, Delete) and ACID (Add, Change, Inquire, Delete). 6. Manovich defines the database as ‘an unstructured collection of images, texts, and other data records’ and claims that ‘the database in its most purest form’ is ‘a set of elements not ordered in any way’ (Manovich 2002, 219, 238, italics JdM) and for that reason op- poses the database to the cultural form of the narrative, which ‘creates a cause-and- effect trajectory of seemingly unordered items’ (ibid, 225). I would argue, rather, that narrative and database structure our often chaotic world in a different way. Whereas a narrative is linear and structures the world through linking events (predominantly past) by narrative causality, the non-linear tabular structure of the database enables the user to manipulate future events. The narrative is not so much an antagonist of the database, but rather one particular trajectory through a database, as Manovich himself acknowl- edges: ‘The “user” of a narrative is traversing a database, following links between its records as established by the database’s creator. An interactive narrative (which can be also called a hypernarrative in an analogy with hypertext) can then be understood as the sum of multiple trajectories through a database’ (ibid., 227, cf. De Mul 2005). 7. See http://www.geertmul.nl/Geert_Mul/NederlandsFotomuseum.html. 8. A similar point has been made by William J. Mitchell: ‘If mechanical image reproduc- tion substituted exhibition value for cult value as Benjamin claimed, digital imaging further substitutes a new kind of use value – input value, the capacity to be manipulated by computer – for exhibition value’ (Mitchell 1994, 52). 9. Cf. Daniel 2000: ‘A “conception” of the “beauty” of a database is not located in the viewer’s interpretation of a static form but in the dynamics of how a user inflects the database through interaction with its field or frame. A database incorporates contradic- tion; it is simultaneously recombinant and indexical, precise and scaleable, immersive and emergent, homogeneous and heterogeneous. It is a field of coherence and contra- diction. The aesthetic dimensions of the database arise when the user traverses this field of unresolved contradictions. (...) Continuously emergent ontological states re- solve as new subfields from each interaction and are integrated into the field – chang- ing and transforming the content and structure of that field and constituting the “art object” as a continuously evolving and fluid system. These are the conditions of possi- bility of a “database aesthetics”’ (Daniel 2000). 10. In this sense the database ontology combines virtual reality (understood as the infinite number of possible recombinations) with real virtuality (the recombinations that are actually being realized). 11. Although the intention of the artist is not decisive, in the case of Kac the aim without doubt is political: ‘My work doesn’t visualize science, it is not meant to duplicate the information that circulates from science to media to the public. It is meant to intervene, to change, to criticize, point out, reflect and modify’ (quoted in Allmendinger 2001). the work of art in the age of digital recombination 105 References Allmendinger, Ulli. 2001. One small hop for Alba, one large hop for mankind. NY Arts Magazine 6 (6). Benjamin, Andrew E. 2005. Walter Benjamin and art. London/New York: Continuum. Benjamin, Walter. 1969. The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction. In Illumina- tions. New York: Schocken Books. Bolle, E., ed. 1992. Book for the unstable media. Den Bosch: V2. Boomen, Marianne van den. In preparation. Transcoding the Internet: How metaphors matter in digital praxis. PhD thesis, Department of Media and Culture Studies Utrecht University, Utrecht. Castells, Manuel. 1996. The rise of the network society. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Codd, E.F. 1970. A relational model of data for large shared data banks. Communications of the ACM 13 (6):377-387. Daniel, Sharon. 2000. Collaborative systems: Evolving databases and the ‘conditions of possibility’: Artificial life models of agency in on-line interactive art. AI & Society: The Journal of Human-Centered and Machine Intelligence 14: 196-213. Davis, Douglas. 1995. The work of art in the age of digital reproduction: An evolving thesis. Leonardo 28 (5):381-386. Gadamer, Hans Georg. 1986. The relevance of the beautiful and other essays. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich, and Michael Marrinan, eds. 2003. Mapping Benjamin: The work of art in the digital age. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Harvey, David. 1989. The work of art in the age of electronic reproduction and image banks. In The condition of postmodernity. Oxford: Basic Blackwell. Hayles, N. Katherine. 2002. Writing machines. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Mitchell, William J. 1994. The reconfigured eye: Visual truth in the post-photographic era. Cam- bridge: MIT Press. Mul, Geert. 2006. Match of the day. http://www.geertmul.nl/Geert_Mul/MATCH-OF-THE- DAY.html. Mul, Jos de. 1999. The informatization of the worldview. Information, Communication & So- ciety 2 (1):604-629. —. 2005. The game of life: Narrative and ludic identity formation in computer games. In Handbook of computer games studies, eds. J. Goldstein and J. Raessens. Cambridge: MIT Press. —. 2005. Résonances de la mort de Dieu, après les fins de l’art. Figures de l’Art. Revue d’Études Esthétiques No X: 265-277. —. 2008. Wittgenstein 2.0: Philosophical reading and writing after the mediatic turn. In Wittgenstein and information theory, eds. A. Pichler and H. Hrachovec. Wien: AWLS. Thomson, Douglass H. 1995. The work of art in the age of electronic (re)production. http:// www.erudit.org/revue/ron/1998/v/n10/005805ar.html. Vesna, Victoria, ed. 2007. Database aesthetics: Art in the age of information overflow. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

106 digital material The design of world citizenship

A historical comparison between world exhibitions and the web

Berteke Waaldijk

In this article I propose to compare the web, and especially Web 2.0, with world exhibitions organised in the second half of the 19th century.1 Such a historical and intermedia comparison may raise new questions that analyse processes of inclusion and exclusion and the role of the medium in these processes, especially regarding the way in which political and commercial aims are purposefully com- bined in both instances. The Internet and world exhibitions both provide assemblages of information, entertainment, commerce, social cohesion and possibilities for political participa- tion. At the world exhibitions, political objectives (popularisation of imperialism, educating inhabitants into national citizens), commercial goals (profits by selling food, drinks, and entertainment), and educational aims (informing citizens of new developments in technology, promoting knowledge of the world) comple- mented each other (Rydell 1984; Greenhalgh 1989; Grever and Waaldijk 2004). The historical comparison helps me to ask new questions about the citizenship that is created in the context of digitally mediated environments. World exhibitions constituted a new medium in the 19th century. Exhibitions were fenced-off spaces wherein experiments in new forms of representation took place. It is therefore possible to study the connections between external exclusion and the hierarchies produced within the gates of the exhibition. It is this inter- connection that I want to compare to the ways by which digital information and communication technology exclude and include people, set them free, entertain and mobilise them.

Historical comparisons Historical comparisons have quite a tradition in new media research. Reaching back to historical predecessors and forerunners is a significant narrative structure in understanding the digital revolution. John Barlow (1996), who dismisses all forms of governmental interference in the ‘new world’ of digital communication,

107 wrapped this message in a rewriting of the United States Declaration of Indepen- dence for cyberspace. Hakim Bey (1991) compared autonomous internet commu- nities in the 1990s to 18th-century pirate zones. Several studies have shown that such comparisons carry undertheorized assumptions regarding class, gender and ethnicity. Richard Barbrook and Andy Cameron (2001) pointed out that the digital freedom claimed by the ‘Founding Fathers’ from Silicon Valley was modeled on a system of slavery with . Laura Miller (1995) showed how the image of cyberspace as the Wild West irrefutably leads to representations of wo- men and children as weak creatures who need protection. Lisa Nakamura (2002) argued that, contrary to the idea of ‘leaving our bodies behind’ in this supposedly unmarked new country, racial stereotypes are hardwired into online interactions. Historical comparisons have also been employed to research specific aspects of the introduction of new media. Comparisons between form and extent of govern- mental support for the introduction of radio allowed Robert McChesney (1999) to describe the interactions between public space and commercial objectives in digi- tal media. Lisa Gitelman (2006) described how recorded sound and digitally net- worked text each emerged as local anomalies embedded within the logic of public life and public memory. Liesbet van Zoonen (2000) pointed to the introduction of the telephone to indicate the gender specificity of a new medium. Lev Manovich (2002) compared the rise of digital media to early cinema, and through literary studies, Marie-Laure Ryan (2006) compared the ways immersion and interactivity are created in classic literary texts and in computer games. Historical comparisons may allow us to see elements in new (and old) media and forms of representation that were not (yet) explicit. In order to play that role, historical research should go beyond producing either timeless similarities be- tween all forms of representation or teleological stories of progress or decline. This article is meant as a push for more historical comparative research in order to understand better the possibilities and limitations of new media in processes of inclusion and exclusion.

Utopia or nightmare? The boom of the Internet in the 1990s has given rise to heated debates with dia- metrically opposed perspectives. Those adhering to the emancipatory and demo- cratic potential of the new medium hailed the coming of a ‘cyberutopia’ with un- limited participation and opportunities to speak one’s mind (Lanham 1993; Barlow 1996; Landow 1997). These optimists foresaw the democratisation of all communication, as well as the erosion of traditional authorities and power rela- tions. Alternately, pessimists saw heightened exclusion. According to them, the development of the Internet enforces white men’s power and their financial inter- ests, and strengthens the renewed exclusion of groups that were already margin-

108 digital material alised on the basis of gender, skin colour, poverty or sexual preference (Luke 2000; Barbrook and Cameron 2001). Hence, on the one hand, digital culture and communication were praised as the cradle of total democratisation; on the other hand, they were condemned as the newest form of social division. The current debates about Web 2.0 are also marked by these opposites. Web 2.0 is praised as ‘the architecture of participa- tion’ (O’Reilly 2005; Jenkins 2006) and as final democracy in the form of ‘wisdom of the crowds’ (Surowiecki 2004; Leadbetter 2008). Others warn that Web 2.0 sites like Hyves, MySpace, YouTube and Flickr constitute just another way to com- mercially exploit interhuman communication, now by extracting data and free labor from users (Terranova 2004; Lovink 2008). It can be observed that cyberoptimists focus primarily on the internal functions of the medium, whereas cyberpessimists are predominantly tainted by external structures, such as unequal access in the 1990s or business models in the era of Web 2.0. Optimism is easier when the authors limit themselves to the inside of the medium: non-hierarchical forms of communication are visible within the con- fined spaces of virtual communities, and unequal access can easily be forgotten. Conversely, pessimistic views tend to neglect the fact that digital communication has also resulted in the creation of counter publics. The anti/alter- movement, many grassroots movements, but also the survival of the alternative music scene have profited from digital connectivity (Sassen 1999; Franklin 2001). The enthusiasm about the increase in the percentage of women who have access to computers and the Internet alternates with apocalyptic visions of child porno- graphy and trafficking in women mediated by the Internet (Miller 1995; Green and Adam 2001). The connections between external and internal aspects, how- ever, are hardly ever explored in the same context. A historical comparison with world exhibitions may begin to address this problem. In this chapter I focus on three fields of similarities between the web and world exhibitions. Firstly, I discuss what I call the ‘immersion’ that is created when images, texts, and sounds are assembled together. Secondly, I focus on the fact that both media are non-linear: the millions of visitors have the relative freedom to choose which sites they visit and in which sequence. Lastly, visitors of both types of representation are part of the spectacle viewed: they listen and are lis- tened to; they see and are being seen; they follow digital tracks and leave their marks. As a pamphlet from the world exhibition in St. Louis in 1901 warned the visitors: ‘Please remember: the moment you enter the gates, you are part of the show’ (Bennett 1995, 68-69).

Immersion Digital-optimists as well as digital-pessimists describe how the anonymity of surf- ing the web is crucial to the experience of cyberspace (Trend 2001; Weinberger the design of world citizenship 109 2002). Seducing visitors in this anonymous mass is crucial: attractive design, well-chosen images, catchy texts and interactivity are supposed to create ‘sticky websites’ to which visitors keep returning. By constantly introducing new combi- nations, the boundaries between communication, entertainment, commerce, and information fade: advertisements on informative sites, information on game sites, and games on informative pages. Davenport and Bradley (1997) compare the web to an amusement park. The visitor to the latter is surrounded by attractions, temporarily allowing her to forget the limiting daily reality of embodiment and social relations. On the roller coaster she forgets gravity; in gambling halls the necessity to work for money; and magi- cal parks allow her to believe that fairies exist. The visitor constantly shifts roles. The same observation can be made for Internet users. Online games perfect the sensation of navigating in another world, but also the ‘regular’ web search for information or entertainment entails opening yet another window, and entering into a different world. According to some, this experience leads to new forms of self-awareness and identity. The Internet-using subject is not unitary, coherent and stable, but can be seen as fluctuating, fluid and rhizomatic (Plant 1998; Brai- dotti 2002). For feminist critics, aware of the dangers of essentialist notions of gender and ethnicity, this aspect of the Internet looks promising. The digital re- volution may end previous forms of cultural exclusion, enabling people to enact new identities (Turkle 1997; Landow 1997). However, critics describe how what appears to be free entertainment, efficient gathering of information, or easy buy- ing is in fact commercial profiling; corporations have found yet another aspect of human existence to exploit (Luke 2000; Terranova 2004; Lovink 2008). However, no matter whether the end of univocal identity is welcomed as a de- sired transformation or disqualified as a way to create superficial consumers, the question remains of whether this process is a direct result of the creation of digi- tal worlds. At this point, a comparison with the experiences of world-exhibition visitors in the second half of the 19th century may be useful. In such spaces visi- tors could lose themselves in many different worlds by traveling into virtual spaces. Just like the surfer clicking from website to website, performing different roles – as customer, information searcher, or participant in a political discussion – the world exhibition visitor’s role altered when moving from pavilion to pavi- lion. Sometimes she was a student being taught about the world, other times a customer at a mischievous show, sometimes a colonial ruler imagining herself in imperialist power structures. Just like the web, world exhibitions constructed all- encompassing experiences, where visitors could lose themselves in images, sounds, and information. The first world exhibition took place in London in 1851. Millions of visitors flocked to the glass palace where the glory and the power of the British Empire were celebrated (Hobsbawm 1975). France, having a long tradition of national industry exhibitions, soon followed (Paris 1855, 1867, 1889, 1900), alternating

110 digital material with the United States (1876, 1893) and other European cities. The last decades of the 19th century beheld an immense array of international and colonial exhibi- tions (Rydell 1984; Gudehus 1992). The First World War implied a decrease in frequency but not in scope. Soon, a fixed design for world exhibitions was established. In the central sec- tion of the venues several countries exhibited, and systematic attention was paid to raw materials, industry, crafts, art, and social relations. The intention was to enlarge international prestige and status. The organising countries constructed large building projects and infrastructure. The Eiffel Tower is the most famous example, but also in Chicago, Barcelona and Vienna the remains of the buildings and terrain of the world exhibitions are still to be found. The enterprises were often joint ventures of national authorities and corporations. The Krupp firm dis- played their newest cannons; Edison revealed the possibilities of electricity; and the new medium of film was introduced to the larger public (Grever and Waaldijk 2004). Millions of people visited these events, paying a substantial entrance fee, but the exhibitions did not derive their success from just national and company pro- paganda. The entertainment industry that emerged in the margins soon became the economic core through which exhibitions remained afloat. The operation of restaurants, cafes and a wide range of attractions such as dance and theatre shows (the Wild West Shows by Buffalo Bill, the shows by Barnum and Bailey), and fairground attractions (the roller coaster, the Ferris wheel) yielded the orga- nisers a vast sum of money (De Cauter 1993; Kasson 2000). To the visitors, these attractions often constituted the core of the exhibition experience (Greenhalgh 1989). The accompanying attractions provided a range of sensorial experiences that heightened the sensation of entering new worlds: the visitor smelled, felt, tasted, and heard strange things. The visitor was immersed in another world; one needed to travel to get there and had to cross the turnstile to enter. Visiting the world exhibition was also a virtual visit to a different part of the world. Timothy Mitchell (1989) described the effort made by designers to entice visitors to feel as though they were in Egypt while being in Paris. Even the paint on the Egyptian houses was artificially made to flake off. Annie Coombes (1987) showed how the feeling of being lost in an unknown jungle was often used to sell the imperialist idea of the ‘white man’s burden’ to British working class visitors. Such observations reveal that the visitors’ experiences were carefully orche- strated. The displays and attractions that constituted the world exhibition were purposefully designed. This was clear to the visitors; they saw the backside of the decor and read the accompanying pamphlets. In that sense, the difference be- tween the representation and the represented was affirmed. In his analysis of colonial exhibitions, Mitchell asserts that even though the representations yield to full immersion, simultaneously a strict division was created between exhibition and visitor: ‘the more the exhibit drew in and encircled the visitor, the more the the design of world citizenship 111 gaze was set apart from it, as mind (in our Cartesian imagery) is said to be apart from the material world’ (Mitchell 2000, 301). According to Mitchell, Western visitors were trained to view the world from a colonial perspective. They learnt to look at the world as a collection of representations from which they could dis- tance themselves. Mitchell stresses the confusing multitude of impressions imposed on the visi- tor, but he also showed how this paradoxically contributed to a heightened feel- ing of distancing and control. Especially the visitors’ capacity to know exactly what was real and what make-believe affirmed their ‘Cartesian judgement’ and the omnipotent fantasy of Western imperialism. At exhibitions they learnt to look at the entire world as a representation, and to imagine themselves as superior, more capable than others of understanding what was represented. Visitors of world exhibitions were thus not completely engrossed in the representation; their immersion was bound up with Cartesian distance. Applying Mitchell’s thesis to the digital domain begs the question of how Inter- net users experience immersion. Do they immerse completely in a transparent medium, or is their immersion connected to the capability to switch from one role or window to the next, thus producing a sense of distanced control? In this context I wish to refer to the comparison with ‘forgetting oneself’ that occurs according to literary theorist Ryan (2001) when reading literary texts. She argues that a reader may lose herself in a text even when aware of the literary techniques. A detective novel may be especially thrilling when the reader is conscious of the author’s textual techniques to hide clues. Modernist authors like Brecht and Woolf experimented with ways to make readers conscious of the literary means employed, and postmodern novels often use these techniques as the core of the construction. From that observation one can compare the experiences of exhibition visitors and surfers. A lot points to the fact that exhibition visitors were both impressed by what was represented and by the technical ingenuity involved. As they had at their disposal visual reconstructions (villages, real cannons, live performances) as well as printed meta-information, visitors switched between immersion and dis- tancing. In the colonial sections, partly serious and partly amusing, this double focus was strikingly apparent. Visitors were invited to lose themselves in watching exotic performances and could later feel themselves colonial officials who super- iorly overlooked the colony. This phenomenon resembles the results of game studies research which claim that computer gaming is marked by a double consciousness. In the game the player is immersed as a hero, discoverer, or town planner aiming for victory or success, but she is simultaneously aware of the rules of play and the developers’ strategies (Copier 2007). In short, gamers too oscillate between immersion and distancing.

112 digital material It seems plausible that the combination of immersion and distancing is present in other computer and Internet practices as well. Several new media scholars (Turkle 1997; Bolter and Grusin 2000; Manovich 2002) stress the importance of the metaphor of the plurality of windows, enabling a less defined subject posi- tion: the user can see and relate to several things simultaneously, alternating be- tween immediacy and hypermediacy, between transparency and opacity, between immersion and distance. The historical comparison between the web and world exhibitions enables a deepening of the understanding of the relation between power and immersion. Just like world exhibition visitors, web visitors do not languidly succumb to the commercial goals of entrepreneurs – immersion and distance go hand in hand. Users (viewers, readers) do not indiscriminately swallow what is offered; they construct a useful meaning while being aware of the rules of the genre. Access to the web not only requires hardware and a connection, but also knowledge of the medium, such as skills in browsing, searching and selecting, and acquaintance with end user license agreements. In that sense the web visitors’ set of capital, knowledge and skills is comparable to the entry tickets and pamphlets of the ex- hibition that reminded the visitors time and time again of the technical ingenious- ness of the designers. I argue that in both cases the entrance conditions guide the visitors in their experiences of both power and immersion.

The end of linearity The next question is what this temporary immersion implies for the visitor’s self- image. Characteristic of both modes is that the visitors participate in an experi- ence in which different behavioural aspects alternate. On the Internet another genre is always within reach, subsequently and simultaneously, by opening an- other window. A teenager may visit gamezone.com while chatting on MSN, si- multaneously downloading music, and casually searching for the latest episode of her favourite TV show. The combination of ‘seriousness’ and ‘entertainment’ at world exhibitions meant that political goals, whether to popularise British imperialism or to cele- brate women’s emancipation, always took place in the context of the touristic and consumptive pleasure of a trip. World exhibitions were one of the first occur- rences of modern mass tourism (Hobsbawm 1975, 47). Visitors could choose in which sequence and order of priority to indulge in the various aspects of the world exhibition. A visit to the exhibition was not a linear experience like listen- ing to a speech, reading an essay, or visiting a museum. For the first generation of cyberoptimists such as Lanham (1993) and Landow (1997), the non-linear structure of digital texts was one of the most promising aspects of the digital revolution. Landow mentions the convergence of post-struc- turalist deconstruction and digital technology, whereas Lanham argues that hy- the design of world citizenship 113 pertext echoes Barthes’s view on text as the result of the interplay between reader and author. According to these writers, the disciplining power of print dissolves in digital hypertext: the power that forces the reader to start at the beginning of a sentence and follow the author to the full stop, thus abiding by the author’s authority. Non-linear texts were supposed to create responsible and independent readers, and even turn them into writers themselves since their reading strategies produce a new text. Weinberger (2002) describes the technology of hyperlinks as a revolution comparable to the transition of oral to written culture. This liberatory aspect of hyperlinking is celebrated even more by Web 2.0 advocates, who claim that a collective intelligence is emerging through non-linear patterns of tagging and linking (Leadbetter 2008; Shirky 2008). However new this may seem, modes of representation which do not force the viewer or reader into a linear tunnel have existed for a long time. I consider world exhibitions an important example of this. Though directed and carefully scripted, often by a national committee, the focus of such control was limited. Organizers could not contribute more than marginal suggestions. The exhibition terrain was characterised by far-reaching freedom, thus markedly different from its contem- porary museums, which directed sequence, hierarchy and meaning for its visitors (Coombes 1987; Greenhalgh 1989). Visitors to exhibitions used such liberties extensively. Documented accounts suggest that visitors enjoyed the knowledge they gained about the structure of the exhibition. They advised others about attractive routes and not-to-be-missed exhibits. From financial reports we know that the success of the exhibitions was largely due to visits to the entertainment sections, though official reports remarkably lack these accounts; the organisers were especially proud of their educational suc- cesses. They described how groups of laborers (often at their employers’ expense) learnt about industry and the colonies (Grever and Waaldijk 2004). The fact that most visitors fondly remembered the entertainment rather than the official aims of the exhibition was not mentioned in the official reports. These were strongly biased by the hierarchical distinction between education (raising good citizens) and entertainment (selling to consumers). The visitors’ experience of freedom to choose sequence and priority is crucial to understanding the success of world exhibitions. This freedom resembled the freedom of customers in a market or a department store: they watched, tested, and weighed. The comparison between world exhibitions and department stores was taken up by both Walter Benjamin (see Buck-Morris 1999) and Mitchell (1989). In department stores customers could ‘vote with their feet’. They went to sections that interested them the most and stopped in front of shop windows that attracted their attention. Mitchell points out that the glass of the shop window transformed merchandise into objects. Through the distance and the glass that separated viewer from object, the consumer article changed into an object, and

114 digital material the visitor into viewer. Anne McClintock (1995) further extends this comparison and describes how advertising techniques and the popularisation of imperialism strengthened each other. World exhibitions place the world in a shop window, turning Western visitors into window shoppers, and thereby altering their world view. World citizenship came to include the consumers’ freedom to choose. Historians’ focus on the consumption and amusement side of exhibitions can be useful for a nuanced insight into the identities constructed by such freedom. By showing how the combination of being a citizen and a consumer was an indis- pensable element of visiting exhibitions, it urges us to take consumerism ser- iously. This also holds true for the Internet. Websites are deeply marked by adver- tising. Yet, focusing on commerce as the sole dimension of the web is insufficient. Just like world exhibitions, Internet meeting places combine com- mercial entertainment with serious instruction, with education, and with propa- ganda. It is precisely this combination which enables visitors to constantly oscil- late between identities: one moment citizen, the other consumer. The political effects of this switching mechanism are profound and need to be analysed in terms of gender, class and ethnicity. The world exhibitions turned imperialism into nationally supported projects. Inhabitants who had never set foot in a colony suddenly felt connected with overseas officials and entrepreneurs by buying products and enjoying colonial arts and crafts (Legêne and Waaldijk 2001). This meant a rearrangement of gender and colonial citizenship. Since wo- men in the colonial metropolis were supposed to be experts in the field of food and clothing, they could relate to and identify themselves with colonial projects of the mother country (Grever and Waaldijk 2004). The exhibitions also offered possibilities for opposing political identities. Sec- tions dealing with the position of women were often featured, and advanced the international infrastructure of the women’s movement (Waaldijk 1999; Grever 2000). At the world exhibition in Chicago in 1893, Fredrick Douglas and Ida B. Wells protested against the discrimination of black Americans in the US (Douglas 1893; Carby 1987). The socialist Second International was established during the world exhibition in Paris in 1889. These examples raise the question of interaction between consumption-based entertainment and emancipation movements: how did these political minority movements succeed in foregrounding their goals, while being surrounded by fairground attractions? Lauren Rabinovitz (1998) pro- vides a new perspective on this issue as she points out that world exhibitions, together with department stores, were the first public spaces in which women could look and inspect. According to Rabinovitz, the new role of women as con- sumers of the entertainment industry was a crucial moment in the history of the emancipation movement. Research into how Internet users combine political par- ticipation with consumption and entertainment may profit from analyses of such spectacular events as world exhibitions.

the design of world citizenship 115 Being part of the show Many cyberpessimists stress the unprecedented possibilities of digital communi- cation for surveillance and control. The almost unlimited potential of the state and business to gather details of people’s lives and the subsequent loss of privacy is regarded as too high a price for the convenience of the Internet. Conversely, many forms of digital activism show that digital control can be reversed or other- wise subverted. Again, it is illustrative to establish the comparison with exhibition visitors’ resistance and critique. Men and women from the colonies and other non-western regions were pre- sent at the world and national exhibitions, as human showcases. The visitors were invited to look at them, but of course the empire looked back. Fascinating moments occur when the gaze is reversed. The initial logic of representation was interrupted when the people on display gazed back. Fredrick Douglas’s protest exemplifies this. Other examples are the strikes by Dutch carpet weavers and Java- nese dancers at the Dutch National Exhibition of Women’s Labour in The Hague (Grever and Waaldijk 2004). Because world exhibitions reached for the sky in representing the world, large parts of the world were indeed present at the exhibition. The people who were there to ensure that the represented countries looked ‘real’ did actually originate from those countries. They were the ones who performed shows and presenta- tions. Time and time again they resisted confinement in a virtual world. They bridged the gap between the actual space of the exhibition and the representation of other spaces. They approached visitors, asked for money, and voiced their opi- nions (Rony 1998). The perfection of the life experience of visiting an unknown culture or foreign country reaches a limit when viewers and the viewed realise that the one who looks can also be looked at. Though the power differentials between viewers and viewed were unsymmetri- cal, they did allow for this relation to be subverted. Cracks in the image appeared: visitors felt exposed, ill at ease in their roles, wondered what the exhibited people thought of them, and established contact in some instances (Grever and Waaldijk 2004). Fatimah Rony (1996) described how exhibited people at ethnological exhi- bitions in the beginning of the 20th century could escape their imposed role of exotic ‘other’. They returned the gaze, approached visitors, tried to collect money, established sexual contacts, and became involved in conflicts taking place across the fence. Moreover, visitors ogled not only the exhibited people but also each other. The slight feeling of unease that people felt when facing the exhibited ‘other’ caused them to realise they were part of the show. Rabinovitz (1998, 50) analysed the intersecting gazes on the exhibition terrain. In a meticulous analysis of images and drawings of the world exhibition in Chicago, 1893, she showed that visitors of exhibitions were always watched. Gender and ethnicity play a crucial part in

116 digital material these processes. White women looked at other visitors and at exhibited (mostly non-Western) men and women. In turn, these white women were looked at by men. Such analyses show that the traditional gender inequality between looking men and to-be-looked-at women may in some ways become subverted at exhibi- tions. How do the insights into the directions of gazes at world exhibitions contribute to insight in the uses of Internet and Web 2.0? The visitor of websites is in a way invisibly visible by digital traces. Studies into these issues are generally conducted in the light of concerns about state surveillance and privacy (Lyon 1994). But the surfer is not only the object of political monitoring by governments and investiga- tion services, but also of marketing strategies and market surveillance. Website visits dissolve the boundary between consuming, gathering information, and po- litical participation. Presumably not every Internet user knows about IP numbers, a unique identification number assigned to every device connected to the Internet, or cookies, small packets of user data stored on the user’s computer, allowing websites to track surfers’ exact behaviour and choices. Combined with the data of other users, this results in personally targeted advertisements: ‘People who ordered this book were also interested in...’ Most Web 2.0 services are based on collecting and reassembling such user-generated data, and derive their business models on these principles of ‘harnessing collective intelligence’ (O’Reilly 2005). Those whose information is gathered may demand goods or services in return; in fact, you pay with your privacy. This ‘customer-card model’ turns surfers into consumers, and their protests into consumer strikes, even when the service seems to be free of charge. The sense of being free to see anything on the web has its counterpart in being viewed. In some ways this requires knowledge – just as ex- hibition visitors had to be warned that they themselves were part of the show, web surfers should be educated about the risks of their visibility.

The historical and intermedia comparison I have conducted in this article helps me to formulate new questions about the citizenship that is being created in web- based environments. As in world exhibitions, a visitor in a web context is not just ‘losing herself’ in immersion but also exercising the power of a navigator who knows the rules of the genre. To a certain degree both kinds of visitors can create their own trajectories, swapping the identity of a citizen for the identity of a con- sumer and back again. If we want to understand the participation and citizenship that results from these alternating roles, it is crucial to see how this implies a close link between political participation and consumerist ‘picking and choosing’. When citizenship and consumer experiences become so deeply intertwined, the crucial question is what happens to those who do not share in the power of con- sumption? Will political participation be the privilege of those who know how to consume?

the design of world citizenship 117 Finally, the comparison of contemporary web environments with world exhibi- tions of a century before allows us to explore the implications of the connection between seeing and being seen. The fact that visitors know themselves to be the object of the gaze of others is not just a price to be paid for entertainment, it becomes part of a sense of power and authority. Again, this shows how the divi- sion between the political and the commercial cannot be maintained, either at world exhibitions or in web environments. Choosing a YouTube video is a social, commercial, and political act. These cannot be understood within the limits of sociological, economic or political analyses. Citizenship in multimedia contexts consists of civil, political, economic and cultural elements, and understanding citizenship requires studying the interactions between these elements. Without such an approach, it seems impossible to understand how external access and internal freedom interact.

Note 1. This article is an updated version of ‘Wereldtentoonstellingen en het World Wide Web: Een historische vergelijking’, published in Dutch in Tijdschrift voor Genderstudies 6(1) (2003). I want to thank Marianne van den Boomen for her generous and perceptive advice about references to the critical debate on Web 2.0. I profited from discussions about citizenship in several contexts. Special thanks are due to the working group Teaching Empires of the ATHENA3/Socrates Network, and the colleagues and students in the Utrecht University Graduate Gender Programme.

References Barbrook, R. and A. Cameron. 2001. The Californian ideology. In Crypto anarchy, cyberstates, and pirate utopias, ed. P. Ludlow, 363-87. Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Barlow, J.P. 1996. A declaration of the independence of cyberspace. http://www.eff.org/~barlow/ Declaration-Final.html. Bennett, T. 1995. The exhibitionary complex. In The birth of the museum, ed. T. Bennett, 59- 88. London: Routledge. Bey, H. 1991. The temporary autonomous zone. http://www.t0.or.at/hakimbey/taz/taz.html. Bolter, J.D., and R. Grusin. 2000. Remediation: Understanding new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Braidotti, R. 2002. Metamorphoses: Towards a materialist theory of becoming. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Buck-Morris, S. 1999 (1991). Walter Benjamin and the arcade project. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Carby, H. 1987. Reconstructing womanhood: The emergence of the Afro-American woman novelist. New York: Oxford University Press. Cauter, L. de. 1993. The panoramic ecstasy: On world exhibitions and the disintegration of experience. In De panoramische droom: Antwerpen en de wereldtentoonstellingen 1885, 1894,

118 digital material 1930 / The panoramic dream: Antwerpen and the world exhibitions of 1885, 1894, 1930, eds. M. Nauwelaerts, 46-50. Antwerpen: Antwerpen 93 VZW. Coombes, A. 1987. The Franco-British exhibition: Packaging empire in Edwardian Eng- land. In The Edwardian era, eds. J. Cherry Becket and D. Cherry Becket, 152-66. Oxford: Phaidon Press. Copier, M. 2007. Beyond the magic circle: A network perspective on role-play in online games. PhD thesis, Universiteit Utrecht. Davenport, G. and B. Bradley. 1997. The care and feeding of users. IEEE MultiMedia 4 (1): 8- 11. Douglas, Fredrick. 1893. Lecture on Haïti: The Haitian pavilion dedication ceremonies de- livered at the world’s fair, in Jackson Park, Chicago, Jan. 2d, 1893 African American Per- spectives: Pamphlets from the Daniel A.P. Murray Collection, 1818-1907. Franklin, M. 2001. Inside out: Postcolonial subjectivities and everyday life online. Interna- tional Feminist Journal of Politics 3 (3): 387-422. Gitelman, L. 2006. Always already new: Media, history, and the data of culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Green, E. and A. Adam, eds. 2001. Virtual gender: Technology, consumption and identity. Lon- don: Routledge. Greenhalgh, P. 1989. Education, entertainment and politics. In The new museology, ed. P. Vergo. London: Reaktion Books. Grever, M. 2000. Reconstructing the fatherland: Comparative perspectives on women and 19th century exhibitions. In A fatherland for women, eds. M. Grever and F. Dieteren, 13-29. Amsterdam: IISG-beheer. Grever, M. and B. Waaldijk. 2004. Transforming the public sphere: The Dutch National Exhibition of Women’s Labor in 1898. With an Introduction by Antoinette Burton. Durham & Lon- don: Duke University Press. Gudehus, B.S. and A. Rasmussen. 1992. Les fastes du progrès: Le guide des expositions universelles 1851-1992. Paris: Flammarion. Hobsbawm, E. 1975. The age of capital, 1848-1975. London: Abacus. Jenkins, H. 2006. Convergence culture. New York: New York University Press. Kasson, J. S. 2000. Buffalo Bill’s Wild West: Celebrity, memory, and popular history. New York: Hill and Wang. Landow, G. 1997. Hypertext 2.0: The convergence of contemporary critical theory and technology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University. Lanham, R. 1993. The electronic word: Democracy, technology, and the arts. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Leadbetter, C. 2008. We-think: The power of mass creativity. London: Profile Books Ltd. Legêne, S. and B. Waaldijk. 2001. Reverse images – patterns of absence: Batik and the representation of colonialism in the Netherlands. In Batik drawn in wax, ed. I. van Hout, 35-69. Amsterdam: KIT-publisher. Lovink, G. 2008. Zero comments: Blogging and critical . New York: Routledge. Luke, T. 2000. Dealing with the digital divide: The rough realities of cyberspace. Telos, Winter 2000. Lyon, D. 1994. The electronic eye: The rise of surveillance society. Cambridge: Polity Press. Manovich, L. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

the design of world citizenship 119 McChesney, R.W. 1999. Rich media, poor democracy: Communication politics in dubious times. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. McClintock, A. 1995. Imperial leather: Race, gender and sexuality in the colonial contest. New York: Routledge. Miller, L. 1995. Women and children first: Gender and the settling of the electronic fron- tier. In Resisting the virtual life: The culture and politics of information, eds. J. Rook and I.A. Boal, 49-59. San Francisco: City Lights. Mitchell, T. 1989. The world as exhibition. Comparative Studies in Society and History (31): 217- 36. Mitchell, T. 1998. Nationalism, imperialism, economism: A comment on Habermas. Public culture: Bulletin of the Society for Transnational Cultural Studies 10 (2): 417-24. Nakamura, L. 2002. Cybertypes: Race, ethnicity and identity on the Internet. New York: Rout- ledge. O’Reilly, Tim. 2005. What is Web 2.0: Design patterns and business models for the next generation of software. O’Reilly Net. http://www.oreillynet.com/pub/a/oreilly/tim/news/ 2005/09/30/what-is-web-20.html. Plant, S. 1998. Zeros and ones: Digital women and the new technoculture. London: . Rabinovitz, L. 1998. For the love of pleasure: Women, movies, and culture in turn-of-the-century Chicago. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press. Rony, F.T. 1996. The third eye: Race, cinema, and ethnographic spectacle. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Ryan, M.L. 2001. Narrative as virtual reality: Immersion and interactivity in literature and electronic media. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Ryan, M.L. 2006. Avatars of story: Narrative modes in old and new media. Minneapolis: Univer- sity of Minnesota Press. Rydell, R. 1984. All the world’s a fair: Visions of empire at American international expositions, 1876- 1916. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sassen, S. 1999. Digital networks and power. In Spaces of culture, city, nation, world, eds. M. Featherstone and S. Lash, 49-62. London: Sage. Shirky, Clay. 2008. Here comes everybody: The power of organizing without organizations. London: Allen Lane. Surowiecki, J. 2004. The wisdom of crowds: Why the many are smarter than the few and how collec- tive wisdom shapes business, economies, societies and nations. New York: Doubleday. Terranova, T. 2004. Network culture: Politics for the information age. London: Pluto Press. Trend, D. 2001. Welcome to cyberschool: Education at the crossroads in the information age. Lanham, ML: Rowman & Littlefield. Turkle, S. 1997. Life on the screen: Identity in the age of the Internet. London: Phoenix. Waaldijk, B. 1999. Colonial constructions of a Dutch women’s movement: 1998. In Differ- enzen in der Geschlechterdifferenz – Differences within genderstudies: Aktuelle Perspektiven der Ges- chlechterforschung, eds. K. Röttger and H. Paul, 286-299. Hamburg: Erich Schmidt Verlag. Weinberger, D. 2002. Small pieces loosely joined: A unified theory of the web. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Publishing. Zoonen, L. van. 2000. Virtuele vrouwen: Constructies van gender online. Oratie Universiteit Maas- tricht: Centrum voor Gender en Diversiteit.

120 digital material ‘And machine created music’

Cybergothic music and the phantom voices of the technological uncanny

Isabella van Elferen

And God saw everything that he had made and behold: it was good And God created man And man created Machine And Machine created music And Machine saw everything it had created and said—behold

As many of the chapters in this book show, technology and culture cannot be separated from one another in early 21st-century daily life. New media technolo- gies shape the way we perceive and interact with the world around us: since they guide our perception and have acquired their own agency, they are also actors in the networked structure of our day-to-day activities. Digital music is an interest- ing example of these two aspects of technological mediation: not only do we hear this music through the digital media of keyboards, samplers and MIDI – and we might download it in mp3 format via P2P networks – we also interact with it with the help of digital agents such as iPods, Internet radio and club turntables. The lyrics to Apoptygma Berzerk’s ‘Kathy’s Song (Come Lie Next to Me)’ quoted above ponder the possibility that technology has even acquired its own creative agency: it is Machine, not God or man, that created music, and Machine that observes the human perception of and interaction with it. The possibility of autonomous technological agency has given rise to utopian as well as doom scenarios in literature, film and music since Mary Shelley’s Fran- kenstein (1818). With the rise of digital technology and artificial intelligence, the number of such scenarios has increased. Characters such as Star Wars’ Darth Va- der, Agent Smith in The Matrix trilogy and even the dreaded ‘millennium bug’ all signify that although the seemingly limitless possibilities of technology open fas- cinating new perspectives, they could simultaneously threaten some of the bor- ders of humanity and even morality that we always thought were stable. In a simi- lar vein, the autonomous agency of music technology has evoked enthusiasm as well as resistance among music lovers. If electronic and digital genres such as

121 house, trance, industrial and minimal explore the possibilities of computer-gen- erated noise to its utmost borders, other genres such as rock, indie and singer- songwriting explicitly prefer human voices over digital ones. The infamous public rejection of Bob Dylan’s electric guitar was followed by the distrust of synthesi- zers and drum computers in the early 1980s, and of digitally produced house and electro in the 1990s and 2000s. Theorists such as Kodwo Eshun and Richard Mid- dleton have asked the question of whether what we hear in digital music is the voice of the cyborg, and how this cyborg music challenges the borders of ‘natural’ music as we know it (cf. Eshun 2000; Middleton 2006). In this chapter I address these aspects of digital music through the lens of Gothic criticism. I shall study the contemporary Gothic phenomenon of cyber- goth music, arguing that bands like Apoptygma Berzerk and Tanzwut mingle the technological agency of digital music with the human agency of the voice and let the resulting cyborg sound interrogate the fluid borders between these mixed agencies. This is networked music, originating from a close collaboration be- tween humans and nonhumans – it is the tune sung by the golem come to life and enjoying its technocultural origin. From the point of view of Gothic theory, moreover, cybergothic music has adopted an aesthetic that is thoroughly liminal, that is, located in a borderland: it dwells in between anthropomorphic and Fran- kensteinian sensibilities and confronts the uncanniness that such emphatically de-humanised mediation brings along. The Gothic approach to these themes al- lows for digital music and nonhuman musical agency to be studied from new angles: what does the borderland between human and nonhuman music look like? Can we distinguish the ghosts that its mediation might evoke and identify the uncanny sides of the ‘digital material’ of cybergothic music?

The Gothic dimensions of technoculture: the uncanny, ghosts, mediation The Gothic is a form of cultural criticism that foregrounds the shadow side of self and the margins of culture. By doing so, the Gothic interrogates and often perso- nifies the uncannily present subcurrents which may render a person or culture irrational, unpredictable, possibly dangerous. From the 18th-century Gothic novel to contemporary Goth subcultures,1 it has served as a signifier of cultural crises and negotiated the anxieties that accompany them through an active confronta- tion with feelings of unease (cf. Punter and Byron 2004, 39). The critical stance of the Gothic highlights the fragmentation, distortion and hidden dimensions of selfhood and reality. It works like a rearview mirror, unveiling the absent pre- sence of the past, of the Other, of the imaginary, of fear within the here and now. Thereby, it forces the one who looks into that mirror to discern such spectres roaming the spaces in between existing dichotomies. The spectres visible in the Gothic mirror are the forces that, according to Freud, give us the uneasy feeling

122 digital material that our home – that is, the domestic sphere, our perception of identity, of con- sciousness or culture – has become unhomely, unheimlich, uncanny. The uncanny may remain a paranoid feeling that we try to suppress, it may take the shape of the barely perceivable spectre of the unconscious haunting consciousness, and it may also appear in a ghost story that makes us contemplate the stability of our respective homes and discover to our dismay that perhaps it is not so stable and safe after all (cf. Smith 2007). While moving to and fro between opposites, the Gothic reaches for the uncanny borderland beyond dialectic. The Gothic is lo- cated in an eternal in-between; simultaneously dialectic and motionless, it signals and negotiates cultural crises through a radical incorporation of ambivalence. This ambivalence takes on many shapes, starting with the presence of past and future in the present that is endorsed by the Gothic’s rewriting gesture. The si- multaneously nostalgic and transgressive rewriting of past situations and atti- tudes furnishes one of the consistent links between the various historical appear- ances of the Gothic. While 18th-century Gothic novels focused on the unspoken presence of medieval and spiritual pasts in enlightened Europe, the Goth genre in contemporary popular music and subculture has rewritten texts and themes from earlier (Gothic) times ever since Bauhaus’s 1979 single ‘Bela Lugosi’s Dead’, which is often considered the first song (Hodkinson 2002, 36). In spite of the constant recontextualisations that cause slight alterations in its out- ward appearance, it is the nostalgic and transgressive gesture of the Gothic that gives it a transhistorical quality (Van Elferen 2007, 2ff). A specific type of rewrit- ing takes place in the remediation of a story from one medium into another; Bram Stoker’s novel Dracula, for instance, has been recast in paintings, films, songs, and computer games, each not only narrating the story, but also adding new layers of interpretation through the medial agencies of the (moving) image and sound themselves. Gothic rewriting can also take the practical guise of re-enact- ment. In re-enactment, the nostalgic and transgressive rewriting of the Gothic is directly embodied. Dressing up as Dracula or dancing to Bauhaus, the remedia- tion of Stoker’s protagonist through the body enables the modern Goth to act out her own interpretation – and that in turn engenders wholly new meanings in her social surroundings. Gothic rewriting, then, always endorses a chronological overlap between various historical times, and this uncanny act of (re)mediation excavates the ghosts that lie buried under the surface of the culture it originates in. Present-day techno- and cybergothic currents look into the rearview mirror of technoculture and confront the spectres that roam it. As Gothic stories from Frankenstein to the ‘millennium bug’ testify, the possibility of nonhuman agency and virtual worlds has given rise to feelings of destabilisation regarding notions of humanity and reality. Although nature-technology and information-material dichotomies are arguably obsolete in the current academic debate (Schäfer and Rieder 2008), the remains of them still seem to be alive in early 21st-century cul-

‘and machine created music’ 123 ture. Even if ambient, wireless and on-demand technology have become indispen- sible partners for our everyday activities, the (un)thinkable limits of technological autonomy still cause individuals and societies to worry. Many theorists have ar- gued that we therefore live in an age of technocultural crisis in which the pre- sence of nonhuman agents has rendered our familiar world uncanny. Building on Kittlerean media theory, Fred Botting has demonstrated how the Gothic genre offers a means to reflect upon the possibly uncanny sides of technology. The agency of technology confronts the media user with the ‘spectres, monsters and undead’ that are conjured up by magic lanterns, , digital realities and artificial intelligence alike (Botting 2005, 24). These are spectres that origi- nate in a world in which technology and culture are no longer distinct, but still those ghosts frighten us – might our own desire for clear demarcations between the two be undead? In , the uncanny borderlands beyond taxonomy are often symbo- lised by deserted houses, landscapes or cityscapes, or labyrinths. These desolate spaces are invariably haunted, as they house repressed or tabooed desires and anxieties that are otherwise safely tucked away in categorised truths. Gothic ghosts like Darth Vader, the Borg in Star Trek and the Terminator represent the concrete (and anthropomorphical) manifestation of such ambivalences regarding cyberculture. They signify the fear of posthuman agency, technologically pro- duced doppelganger, and moral vacuum, respectively; and these feelings occur simultaneously with the unbridled fascination for cyberculture that is symbolised by the characters in Gibson’s book Neuromancer, Cronenburg’s film eXistenZ, and Faithless’s hymn ‘God is a DJ’. When examined through a Gothic lens, technocul- ture – and cyberspace in particular – thus appears as a new deserted and uncanny place, simultaneously inhabited by the ghosts of enthusiasm and fright for the potencies of technology. But it is not only within the Gothic narrative that a liminal borderland comes into being. Julian Wolfreys has demonstrated that telling a story can open up a Gothic space (Wolfreys 2001, 3). The act of narration, he argues, is a kind of phantasmagoria that is not necessarily pleasant: it allows the past to enter the present, and alternative realities to overlie the known. The uncanny accompanies storytelling; it is the unrepresented lurking behind presentation, the unknown saliently present in the known. While an omniscient narrator seems to possess hidden knowledge simply because he represents the literary medium, a reader knows more than a book character because she holds the medium itself in her hand and can flip through to the end. And this holds true for more than just literary narration. Indeed, every act of mediation, be it textual, visual or auditory, can evoke a Gothic conflation of overlapping temporalities and realities, and can foreground the hiatus between fantasy and fantasist through the effects of hyper- mediacy (Bolter and Grusin 2000) or – with Botting – between medium and spec- tator (cf. Law 2006). A medium itself can function as a ‘third place’ between the

124 digital material mediated phenomenon and its audience: the mobile phone may appear as a phan- tom voice, music technology may allow ghosts from the past to sing their song, digital avatars may be perceived as disembodied spectres. Gothic narratives are thus encapsulated by the Gothic narratology of mediation and rewriting, which gives technoculture a second layer of uncanniness: not only does technology chal- lenge old taxonomies of what is real/human and what is not through its creation of third order simulacra, new media also destabilise the narratological basis of those very simulacra. Technogothic ghosts roam the borderland beyond the na- ture-technology distinction, but they simultaneously haunt the media themselves that facilitate that borderland’s existence. The protagonist Trinity in The Matrix, for instance, lives both in a computer simulation (‘the matrix’) and in what is left of the pre-technological world (‘the real world’), but she also haunts Neo as a text-based avatar on his PC during his hacking activities. The ghost is in the ma- chine as well as in the new reality that the machine creates.

Uncanny music technology and the cybergothic If every act of mediation can evoke a Gothic conflation of temporalities and reali- ties, this holds especially true for musical mediation. The medium of music itself functions as a performative ‘memory machine’ that involuntarily stirs past - tions and experiences (Benschop 2007), even in the case of hearing music one has never heard, for even the smallest entities of music – the timbre of a violin, the melody of a bass riff, the rhythm of a techno beat – will stir the memory of a similar musical experience, transport the listener into that past experience and reinscribe it with present connotations (Van Elferen and De Vries forthcoming). Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari argue that music is ‘on the side of the nomadic’ because the moment it is activated, it challenges spatial and temporal constella- tions (Deleuze and Guattari 1986, 88). These qualities render music vectral as well as spectral: music’s memory machine activates vectors into the realm of memory, emotion, and imagination, and in this capacity, like other media, it invites alter- native realities to shroud the listener’s known reality. And these musical qualities cannot but be activated. ‘The indefensible ear’ (Schwartz 2003) must hear music, the listener must embark on its lines of flight towards the spaces in between past and present, must rewrite her own history. Music can function as a Gothic med- ium par excellence: not only does it endorse an overlap of past and present, it simul- taneously foregrounds itself as the mediator of that overlap (‘This music reminds me of…’). For these reasons music’s vectors are an excellent vehicle for Gothic transgression: they provide gateways to liminal borderlands beyond the here and now. The advent of music technology has intensified the vectral and spectral facul- ties of music. Douglas Rushkoff has described how music technology engenders a timespace of its own whose effect is Dionysian: it creates a suspension of the

‘and machine created music’ 125 boundaries of everyday time and space that is nearly orgiastic in character (Rushkoff 1994, 217-18). Digital production and performance, moreover, have re- moved human agency from musical narration. Music recording is dehumanised rewriting: it is phenomenologically determined through the mechanical replaying of bits of past time in the present time, allowing past experiences to interact with present ones (Evens 2005, 53). The uncanny aspect of mediation is thereby en- larged to uneasy proportions: recording technology, sampling and digitalization, not only generates musical echoes from the past, but also doubles, transforms and distorts them. Musical mediation forces the listener to perceive the disembo- died ‘voices of the dead’ (Sterne 2003) and even phantom ‘voices from the void’ (Sconce 2000): echoes from a hollow space, presences without origin whose sole agent seems to be the technology generating their sound. Digitally produced mu- sic rubs the spectral narrative principle of the ghost story in our face, and cyber- gothic musical styles thrive on exactly that starting point. The Goth scene appropriated technological developments from an early stage. Shelley’s Frankenstein has been followed by numerous technogothic books and films, the Net.Goth communities of the early 1990s have evolved into countless Gothic web communities (Whittaker 2007), and since the mid-1990s cybergoths have incorporated technology in music, lyrics and clothing. One difference be- tween the historical Gothic and Goth subcultures is that the latter embody the Gothic spectres of their age. Dressed up like cyborgs, cybergoths enact the ghosts that haunt technoculture, and as such perform the uncanniness that per- vades our evaluation of technology. Just like those ghosts, they signify ambiva- lence; neither rejecting nor embracing technology, neither judgmental nor ec- static about it, they are a living emblem testifying that in our encounter with cyberreality, fascination goes hand in hand with fear – they enact the utopian and the shadow sides of technoculture at once. This Gothic stance is expressed in various ways in cybergoth subculture, most notably through the uncanny sound of cybergothic music. A distinct portion of Gothic music is heavily imbued with technology, with regards to instrumentation, compositional processes, and lyrics. In the 1980s, the Belgian band Front 242 created (EBM). Front 242 mixed Depeche Mode’s synthpop, ’s new wave, and Kraftwerk’s industrial noise, and garnished the resulting mechanical drones with dark lyrics celebrating undeath and science-fiction utopias/dystopias. EBM’s orchestra is the synthesizer, one of the instruments described by Richard Middleton as creators of musical doubles, non-sounds and ‘siren bodies’ (Middleton 2006). It works according to the principle of schizophonia, the separation of a sound from its origin (Schafer 1977, 273), that gives birth to second- or even third-order simulacrum sounds. The synth’s phantom voices operate as musical symbols of the themes in EBM lyrics. EBM was very influential in Goth and industrial musical scenes of the late 1980s and early 1990s; from the early 1990s onwards, bands such as Feindflug in

126 digital material Germany and VNV Nation in England started to combine EBM with the ultimately machine-made musical style, techno, into cybergothic music. This musical style typically has a high bpm (beat per minute) count, and its harmonic structure is built on the rhythmical basses of techno and trance; synthesizer chords, indus- trial and digital sounds function as characteristic fillers of the musical texture. Cybergoth replaces the lyrical melodies laid out over mainstream techno with (mostly male) low-pitched vocals, grunts, or echoed voice distortion. Musical form in cybergothic is often remarkably traditional in the sense that it consists of an intro, two or three verses, a refrain, a bridge, and an outro. The lyrics of cybergothic music show that its appropriation of technology is by no means uncritical, but rather ambivalent; in this sense, cybergoth bands give a more differentiated (if somewhat cynical) reaction to the musical cyberutopianism of artists such as Justin Timberlake and Missy Elliott (cf. McCutcheon 2007). As an example follow the intro to and very last line of ‘Kathy’s Song (Come Lie Next To Me)’ by Norwegian band Apoptygma Berzerk (from Welcome to the Earth, Metro- polis Records 2000), in which Machine is the next deity of the Genesis, who cre- ates music like God creates man:

In the beginning God created the heaven and the earth And the earth was without form and void And darkness was upon the face of the dead And God said: let there be light And there was light And God saw the light, that it was good And God divided the light from the darkness And God called the light day and the darkness he called night And God saw everything that he had made and behold: it was good And God created man And man created Machine And Machine created music And Machine saw everything it had created and said—behold

[beat sets in]

[verses and refrain describing ill-fated love]

And on the seventh day, Machine pressed stop. [music stops abruptly]

‘Kathy’s Song’ reflects the musical heritage of cybergothic music and EBM, evok- ing associations of Depeche Mode ‘gone digital’ (and as such in fact does not sound unlike Depeche Mode’s 2005 album Playing the Angel). In line with the intro

‘and machine created music’ 127 text, a drum computer, a synthesizer and digitally manipulated voices are the main determiners of the song’s timbre. These compositional choices foreground the autonomous agency of music technology: this cybercultural narrative is not only facilitated but also underlined by its own mediation, and what we perceive are voices from the borderland between biological and technocultural musical realities. The love story in the song’s core text is balanced by Machine’s powers in intro and outro, which once again stresses the cooperation of human and non- human actors in the creation of Apoptygma Berzerk’s musical universe. There are several videos available for ‘Kathy’s Song.’ The ‘official’ MTV version consists only of digitally visualised soundwaves that are entirely consistent with the band’s version of Genesis; the more popular ‘Ferry Corsten remix’ video shows a pan view of New York City interspersed with digital manipulations of growing plants in empty spaces like deserts and jungles filmed from warped cam- era angles. These videos visualise the blurred boundaries between God’s and Ma- chine’s creation that are thematized in the song’s music and lyrics. From a cyber- gothic perspective, the one grows from the other, and both the urban labyrinth and the vastness of the desert may at once appear a safe haven and an alienating wasteland. And just like the musical narrative, the video narrative uncannily fore- grounds its own mediation through the pervasive ‘absent presence’ of camera and editing. Though quite different in thematic scope, a similar instance of the uncanny echoes in cybergoth musical culture can be found in ‘Tanzwut’ (‘Dance Rage’)by the German band Tanzwut (from Labyrinth der Sinne, EMI Music 2000). Tanzwut’s members are also in the pagan Goth band Corvus Corax.2 Both parallel projects use medieval instruments such as bagpipes and medieval – or medieval conno- tated – percussion, and take either originally medieval or self-concocted Latin and German texts as the starting point for their lyrics. Whereas Corvus Corax, however, usually refrains from digital production in favour of a more traditional metal sound that is complemented by medieval bagpipes and percussion, Tanz- wut’s music is heavily imbued with technology and explores the convergence of pagan Goth, industrial techno and Neue Deutsche Härte.3 The band members usually perform half-naked, wearing only long leather or fur skirts and pagan attributes. The lyrics of their signature song ‘Tanzwut’ speak of the transgressive forces of music and dance:

Inter Deum et Diabolum Semper musica est Durch Feuer und Glut Ein Heulen, Jammern, Kreischen Klägliche Reue Satans Werk der Tanz

128 digital material Verwirren Verdammen Verführen

[Between God and Devil There is always music Through fire and glow A howling, whining, Screeching Piteous mourning Satan’s work of the dance

Confusion Doom Seduction]

If sounding music creates lines of flight towards liminal spaces of history and reality, Tanzwut’s lyrics moreover stress that music’s transgressive qualities may even lead to a space beyond morality, ‘inter Deum et Diabolum’. The pagan ele- ment in this song is represented by the bagpipe bourdon (an open fifth interval) in the refrain and basic onbeat rhythms, while distorted guitars playing power chords lay out the metal sound wall, and distorted drum computer and bass es- tablish a firm techno beat. The vocals in ‘Tanzwut’ consist of grunts and vocoder- morphed sounds. Like Apoptygma Berzerk’s ‘Kathy’s Song’, ‘Tanzwut’ is thus musically characterised by a convergence of biological and phantom voices, hu- man and nonhuman actors. Both songs in this way create uncanny echoes of technocultural futures – but the latter allows the ‘medieval’ and metal past to reverberate into such futures as well. As noted above, the nostalgic rewriting of the past has long been identified as one of the main characteristics of the Gothic. Botting describes Gothic nostalgia as the yearning for a romanticised past: ‘Gothic novels seem to sustain a nostalgic relish for a lost era of romance and adventure, for a world that, if barbaric, was (...) also ordered’ (Botting 2007, 5). However, such nostalgic rewriting often also results in transgressions of the past. Discussing the nature of nostalgia, Linda Hutcheon has argued that the nostalgic drive does not so much signify the desire to literally go back to the past, but rather reflects the will to yearn for something which is essentially irrecoverable (Hutcheon 2000). As a result of this subjective sentimental drive, she asserts, ‘nostalgia “sanitizes” the past’: by nostalgically remembering, we conjure up a past we desire to long for, and thus paradoxically transgress history itself by way of memory.4 It is precisely in this liminal space between history and memory that the Gothic roams – and the cybergothic shows that the future, too, is nostalgically and uncannily appropriated by Gothic fiction.

‘and machine created music’ 129 Anne Williams states in her evaluation of Gothic literature that it ‘offers its read- ers an imaginative space that both insists on “reality”, on historicity, on material- ity, and at the same time liberates the reader from the constrictions of that his- tory’ (Williams 1997, 122). Embracing both the freedom and the uncanniness resulting from this entrance into the borderland between the real and the virtual – the same borderland that is inhabited by cybergoths – the Gothic actively appro- priates and acts out the symbiosis of futuristic nostalgia and transgression. And it does so in the superlative: it underlines the transgressive force of nostalgia by deliberately perverting the orderly texture of the yearned-for past or future. If nos- talgia is characterised by the retrospective or prospective creation of an idealised homeland, the Gothic renders this very homeland uncanny by perverting its idyllic quality. Medieval or pagan Goth music is characterised by precisely this Gothic gesture of transgressing the borders between past, present and future. Rebekah Ahrendt has interrogated the remediation of the Middle Ages by Gothic bands Helium Vola and Qntal, arguing that the sentimentalised nostalgia of its sounds does not reflect a leap back into history, but rather invokes a timeless memory space, al- lowing Goths to enact their desire for an idealized past whilst dancing away in the ‘fantastic vision’ of the medieval Gothic (Ahrendt 2007). Tanzwut even goes one step further, as it adopts the future as well as the past into this fantastic vision by blending pagan Goth, metal and trance into a musical amalgamate depicting quite literally how music moves beyond chronology. The video of ‘Tanzwut’ shows a computer-game interface with figures playing medieval instruments in the background, in which the display functions blink rhythmically. The message here is the medium: music allows for an escape from chronological and moral taxonomies and may take the listener on a trip between the medieval past and the technological future as well as ‘between God and Devil’.

The digital material of cybergothic music In digital music, technology is both an agent and a medium. Technology creates music, it mediates music, and it allows us to interact with music. I contend that in cybergothic music by bands like Apoptygma Berzerk and Tanzwut, the agency of music technology is uncannily pushed to the foreground and into the footlight. This music thus explores the Gothic dimensions of digital music culture. It en- genders Gothic dialectics through the musical interplay between biological and technological realities on the one hand, and the past, present and future on the other – an interplay which must remain without a winner: it is the motionless dialectic in between such categories that is the issue. As the transgressions in the song lyrics are increased by the fact that they are musically (as well as visually) mediated by the phantom voices of digital technology, these songs demonstrate that digital music can operationalise the Gothic ghost story principle and create a

130 digital material medial space of its own. The hypermediacy of this music evokes reflections upon the very theme it represents: the blurring of boundaries between human and non- human musical agencies. Cybergothic music has escaped the dichotomies of hu- man versus nonhuman sounds, information versus materiality: it is the musical ‘digital material’ originating from the convergence of music technology and mu- sic culture. But it is, moreover, uncanny digital material, as it dwells in the border- lands beyond those dichotomies of musical experience and self-consciously med- iates their in-betweenness. As the phantom voices of the cybergothic sing their uncanny song, the listener is confronted with the undead spectres they conjure up: the simultaneous enthusiasm and skepticism for music technology’s autono- mous creative agency. Those spectres are embodied by cybergoths, who dance their cyborg bodies to this music – but that is the subject matter of another ghost story.

Notes 1. The term ‘Goth’ is used here to distinguish present-day from the trans- historical Gothic genre evolving from the 18th-century Gothic novel. 2. ‘Pagan’ and ‘medieval’ Gothic musical genres are very much alike both in instrumenta- tion, melodic and rhythmic outline, and performance. Although they are not synon- ymous, Tanzwut could be categorised in both genres. 3. Neue Deutsche Härte is a metal/industrial genre that originated in the reunited Germany in the 1990s and that is characterised by distorted metal guitars, industrial and electronic noise, upbeat tempo, and German lyrics. The internationally most famous representa- tive of NDH is Rammstein. 4. Pierre Nora has made the important differentiation between factual history on the one hand and desired and sentimentalised memory on the other (Nora 1996: 626ff).

References Ahrendt, Rebekah. 2007. Celts, crusaders, and clerics: The ‘medieval’ in gothic music. In Nostalgia or perversion? Gothic rewriting from the eighteenth century until the present day, ed. Isabella van Elferen, 96-112, Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press. Benschop, Ruth. 2007. Memory machines or musical instruments? Soundscapes, recording technologies and reference. International Journal of Cultural Studies 10 (4): 485-502. Bolter, Jay and Richard Grusin. 2000. Remediation: Understanding new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Botting, Fred. 2005. Reading machines. In Gothic technologies: Visuality in the romantic era, ed. Robert Miles. Romantic Circles. http://www.litgothic.com/LitGothic/general.html. Botting, Fred. 2007. Gothic. London: Routledge. Deleuze, Gilles and Félix Guattari. 1986. Nomadology: The war machine. New York: Semiotext (e). Elferen, Isabella van. 2007. Introduction. In Nostalgia or perversion? Gothic rewriting from the eighteenth century until the present day, ed. Isabella van Elferen, 1-10. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Press.

‘and machine created music’ 131 Elferen, Isabella van, and Imar de Vries. Forthcoming. The musical Madeleine: Communica- tion, performance and identity in musical ringtones. In Popular Music and Society 33 (2). Eshun, Kodwo, 2000. Visions of rhythm in the kynematic pneumacosm of Hype Williams. Machine times, ed. J. Brouwer, 116-133, Rotterdam: Nai Publisher / V2. Evens, Aden. 2005. Sound ideas: Music, machines, and experience. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Hodkinson, Paul. 2002. Goth: Identity, style and subculture. Oxford/New York: Berg. Hutcheon, Linda. 2000. Irony, nostalgia, and the postmodern. Studies in Comparative Litera- ture 30: 189-207. Law, Jules David. 2006. Being there: Gothic violence and virtuality in Frankenstein, Dracu- la, and Strange Days. ELH 73 (4): 975-996. McCutcheon, Mark A. 2007. Techno, Frankenstein and copyright. Popular Music 26: 259- 280. Middleton, Richard. 2006. Last night a dj saved my life: Avians, cyborgs and siren bodies in the era of phonographic technology. Radical Musicology 1. http://www.radical-musicol- ogy.org.uk/2006/Middleton.htm. Nora, Pierre. 1996. The era of commemoration. In Realms of memory: The construction of the French past, Vol. III: Symbols, ed. Pierre Nora. New York: Columbia University Press. Punter, David and Glennis Byron. 2004. The gothic. Malden: Blackwell. Rushkoff, Douglas. 1994. Cyberia: Life in the trenches of cyberspace. London: Flamingo. Sconce, Jeffrey. 2000. Haunted media: Electronic presence from to television. Durham: Duke University Press. Schafer, R. Murray. 1977. The tuning of the world: Toward a theory of soundscape design. New York: Random House. Schäfer, Mirko Tobias and Bernhard Rieder. 2008. Beyond engineering: Software design as bridge over the culture/technology dichotomy. In Philosophy and design: From engineering to architecture, eds. Pieter E. Vermaas, Peter Kroes, Andrew Light, and Steven A. Moore, 152-164, Dordrecht: Springer. Schwartz, Hillel. 2003. The indefensible ear: A history. In The auditory culture reader, eds. Michael Bull and Les Back, 487-501, Oxford/NY: Berg. Smith, Andrew. 2007. Hauntings. In The routledge companion to gothic, eds. Catherine Spoo- ner and Emma McEvoy, 147-154, London: Routledge. Sterne, Jonathan. 2003. The audible past: Cultural origins of sound reproduction. Durham: Duke University Press. Whittaker, Jason. 2007. Gothic and new media. In The Routledge companion to gothic, eds. Catherine Spooner and Emma McEvoy, 270-279, London/New York: Routledge. Williams, Anne. 1997. Edifying narratives: The gothic novel, 1764-1997. In Gothic: Transmu- tations of horror in late twentieth century art, ed. Christoph Grunenberg, Boston: The Insti- tute of Contemporary Art & Cambridge, MA: MIT. Wolfreys, Julian. 2001. Victorian hauntings: Spectrality, gothic, the uncanny and literature. Lon- don: Palgrave Macmillan.

132 digital material Network

Moving beyond the artefact

Lessons from participatory culture

William Uricchio

I can’t seem to shake a déjà vu feeling when considering the current moment of media change as if, knowing what I do now, I was present during cinema’s first decade. How, I often wonder, did that new medium’s contemporaries fail to pre- serve films, key texts, and audience experiences? But when I consider the lax and, with a few notable exceptions, unsystematic efforts that are being made to pre- serve our latest ‘new’ media, it should come as no surprise. In the pages that follow, I will speak as a cultural historian who makes extensive use of archives and has an abiding interest in heritage and access. But I also speak as one whose personal and working life is increasingly bound up in new media and particularly . These two positions are hardly incompatible; on the contrary, they seem to me to offer not only real advantages thanks to the computerized archive, but real opportunities for historians to reflect upon the birth and development of the latest ‘new’ medium. And they bring with them the responsibility of learning from the past and preparing for the future, and urging the thoughtful and sys- tematic archiving of this latest chapter in our cultural history. What follows will therefore of necessity have a polemical edge. The stakes for our culture and our ability to understand are both immediate and profound.

Posing the problem The ‘digital turn’ has enabled the transformation of such familiar media as photo- graphy, film, recorded sound and the printed word, introducing new platforms, standards and applications. As Hollywood’s growing dependence on digital pro- duction techniques and DVD sales shows, and the press’s routine embrace of computer-based information flow attests, the media industry has quickly accom- modated these transformations. There are of course some concerns about putting low-cost professional digital production equipment in the hands of ordinary citi- zens, but the media industry is quickly learning to turn a profit on the results. The revolution provoked by seems more of a problem, and although ‘piracy’ is the term most often asserted by the industry, its own failure

135 to develop adequate digital distribution models is a far more serious liability. But these problems largely reside in the domain of business strategy, and while many in the business and political community fret about the implications of digitaliza- tion for the bottom line, few have bothered to ask whether digitalization has fun- damentally altered the nature of the media with which they are concerned. The archival world has, by contrast, shown deep concern with what might best be termed ‘media ontology’ and the implications of the differences between, for example, the grain and pixels that constitute a film image. Although digital tech- nologies have demonstrated their advantages for helping with the task of image and sound restoration and preservation, a significant cohort of archivists has ar- gued that a shift in mediality, from analog to digital, fundamentally undercuts their mission. They argue that preserving film is not the same as storing com- pressed .1 Yet while profound in its implication, even this shift leaves the basic parameters of the traditional archive largely intact. Whether digital or analog, pixel or grain, the archive remains concerned with the restoration and preservation of cultural artefacts that are still called films, books, audio record- ings and photos. True, a fundamental debate regarding media ontology remains unresolved and the indiscriminate use of nomenclature such as ‘film’ and ‘photo- graphy’ is problematic, but collections still adhere to the basic selection and cata- loguing parameters of the analog past. Of far greater concern to our culture’s memory institutes should be new cate- gories of digital culture that have been enabled particularly by networked compu- ters – categories that are growing exponentially. Consider the case of e-mail – computerized versions of the physical letter (of course with a fabric of stylistic and formal differences) that generally speaking enjoy no systematic archiving or even technical standard. Future historians of the ‘information age’ will, ironically, face a gap in key evidentiary domains when attempting to make sense of their topic since most business archives are designed to account for paper records, but not electronic. And e- are a best-case scenario…. Social media such as blogs (web logs), wikis, massively multiplayer role-playing games, and various on-line social spaces that lack any homologies to traditional archival objects face a far more difficult situation. In the case of social media, there are neither pre-existing archival categories nor memory institutes charged with collection, selection, re- storation, preservation and access. Indeed, there seems to be a very real debate about how to even think about these emerging media forms. They do not adhere to the familiar ‘mass’ distribu- tion of the traditional media (although their reach can be greater than many tradi- tional media), nor are they as atomized as telephone calls and individual corre- spondence (although they can be uniquely person to person), nor is their textual identity necessarily stable and fixed in the way that we think of photographs or films or books (although they can inhabit a range of positions from dynamic, like games, to stable, like e-books). They fall outside of the familiar limits of our

136 digital material cultural habits and expectations, and since memory institutions are largely in- volved in the business of creating and maintaining tradition, it’s easy to see why these new forms are so awkward. The challenges to those concerned with preserving cultural heritage are enor- mous. Not only must we move beyond familiar objects and homologies in our choice of what to save, we must also attend to the larger cultural shift towards participation and collaboration. Blogs and wikis are not only highly dynamic as texts; they are examples of networked and collaborative cultural production. They depart from the strictures (and legal definitions) of authorship familiar from the book or film, and are instead accretive, multiply voiced, collective, and ongoing. Although we have some historical precedents for this type of authorship (exam- ples ranging from the Old and New Testaments to quilts come to mind), they have tended either to acquire an institutionally imposed stability (the Bible) or been repositioned from media text to artistic artefact (quilts).2 Yet, this collabora- tive dynamism is a core defining aspect of today’s new social media. Without familiar criteria such as authorship or the text as an authoritative and fixed entity, or the many institutions that help us to construct hierarchies of importance, how will we know what to save? What evaluative criteria should we deploy? And even if we could answer these questions, what would be an appropriate point to ‘freeze’ and hold these dynamic artefacts in the archive? Where do we draw the line be- tween the cultural and the social, between the artefact and the means of its pro- duction? And even if we accept the social and acknowledge that patterns of inter- action are as important as the text, how do we go about documenting them in meaningful ways? The answers are not clear, but there might at least be produc- tive new ways of posing the questions. The stakes of facing such questions go beyond the need to document a signifi- cant change in how our cultures represent themselves and their experiences and how they circulate those representations. These are, of course, vital issues parti- cularly at moments of transition, where new constituencies are empowered to represent and circulate, or where people develop new technological affordances and new ways of using them. Such broad concepts as knowledge and the public are redefined and empowered at such moments. And while of great interest to cultur- al historians such as myself, these concepts also help to define the fabric of our daily lives. Consider our changing relationship to the news. Once vetted and produced by trained journalists and centralized institutions with carefully cultivated ideological profiles and professional reputations, news has slipped onto the Internet where it is often neither vetted nor contextualized and where it circulates at the speed of light. When there were well-established filters and a clear line of responsibility, one could agree or disagree, but the status of the information was known. Having ‘seen it on the Internet’ does little to pin down critical parameters or accurate sources of information. Yet, perhaps even more than rumor, such information moving beyond the artefact 137 can take on a life of its own, confusing public discourse. As we now know about so-called misinformation campaigns, digitally altered photographs, and re- worked press releases, even the highest levels of some national governments have made use of the new media to manipulate the record and with it public perception and knowledge. The policy implications both for day-to-day politics and for the historical record couldn’t be more profound. Here, too, is an area where systematic archiving of social media – dynamic texts as well as circulation patterns – could greatly assist the functioning of our political lives by allowing us to go back to the record and check instances of manipulation.3 Such an intervention, it needs to be said, can only serve the present to the extent that the public is educated in the critical assessment and use of these new media. Our cultural knowledge and assumptions are grounded in the traditional centralized media. The press and book publishers, film and music companies, broadcasting authorities, and the rest have long exercised a near paternalistic control over media production and circulation. More importantly, at least in the West, interpretive systems grounded in 2,000+ years of biblical exegesis, legal precedent working out the meanings of terms, and dictionaries and lexicons pin- ning down the precise functioning of language have all worked hand in glove with centralized media systems to circumscribe meanings and enforce responsi- bility. Audio and visual culture challenged the precision of the word, but even here rather strict protocols developed in order to minimize charges of libel and maximize impressions of consistency and professionalism. But the digital turn and the steady emergence of bottom-up and collaborative media require new ways of encountering texts and new skill sets on the part of media users. This new literacy can no longer take the news at face value, but rather must consider it as partial, as a construction, and as data that must be critically assessed and com- bined with other sources in order to yield some sense of the truth. But I digress….

Web 2.0: social media In a world where people increasingly manage, direct and redefine when and where they experience media, how they share it, and what it means to produce and consume, we need to think about cultural processes in dramatically new ways. The shifts from analog to digital, from centralized to dispersed, from mass media to social media, from information transmission to collective intelligence, from old statistical extrapolations to new data feeds, all point to media use that is social by design, not social by default. The descriptors used by Tim O’Reilly and others for Web 2.0 are revealing: ‘an architecture of participation,’‘harnessing collective intelligence,’‘exchanging,’‘pooling,’ and ‘collaboration’. Whether we look to social media communities such as Technorati (http://technorati.com) or social networking sites such as Friendster (www.friendster.com) and MySpace (www.myspace.com) or media fashion communities such as Digg (http://digg.

138 digital material com), we see new logics that have to be understood if we are to make use of them. I’d like to borrow a term from the worlds of biology, neurology, and com- puter science that speaks to these new conditions: high connectivity. High connec- tivity in these various domains refers to dynamic networks, high magnitudes of contact among many nodes, and both interactive and iterative behavior. Before looking a bit more closely at what these developments portend for cul- ture and, in consequence, our memory institutions, first a few words about the technologies that have been drawn upon. The World Wide Web was largely made possible thanks to the introduction of web browser and the Pentium chip a little over ten years ago (ca 1995). Making far more effective use of networked computers, these developments were also aided by significant increases in cable carrying capacity (), compression algorithms, and cheap memory. These developments have continued, and two parameters in particular have a bearing on the archive: memory and transmission speed. Memory capacity is growing ever vaster and cheaper, as a look at the retail sector will demonstrate. As production capacities grow, so too does our ability to hold the massive amounts of data that are being produced. Transmission speeds have also improved significantly: in 2007, Alcatel-Lucent announced that it had broken the 25.6 terabyte optical data transmission speed, or the equivalent of sending the information on 600 in one second. Together, massive increases in memory and the new transmission speeds combine with a near geometrical progression of wired households in some national contexts to suggest that the developments we have seen since the introduction of Mosaic are but the tip of the iceberg. We have a sense of what is looming in the distance, but its magnitude is not yet visible or even imaginable. Yet we also know that these changes are touching most parts of our lives, from banking and buying train tickets, to entertainment and leisure, to driving and working. But the most interesting developments – and the develop- ments that we need to think about archiving – remain submerged and out of sight. As suggested at the outset, the implications of the digital turn for media produc- tion have gotten most of the press coverage. Armed with a modestly priced com- puter and video camera, a skilled teen can produce films or music that achieve industry technical standards. And while this is a big advance on the 8mm or 16mm of two or more decades ago, the real advantage of digital culture has been in transforming ‘home’ movies into ‘world’ movies. New logics of distribution have enabled grassroots producers to sidestep the control long ex- ercised by media corporations and governments, and reach a global audience. The rapid circulation of digital texts has also stimulated the growth of cultural hunters and gatherers who cut and mix, collect and reassemble, borrow and re- purpose, and who do so as collectives. These practices are not so distant from those evident in pre-industrial and agrarian cultures (or said another way, in the era of pre-commodified culture) – again, consider the work of quilters, folk sing- moving beyond the artefact 139 ers and storytellers that might be characterized in precisely the same terms. And just as notions of ownership were blurred in folk cultures, so they are unclear with many of today’s new media practitioners. The contemporary blurring of in- tellectual property can be attributed in part to the new logics of digital culture, and in part to the increasingly draconian control over our cultural heritage as- serted by corporate copyright and trademark holders. As intellectual property pro- tection steadily expands at the behest of corporate interests, the public is increas- ingly deprived of anything other than paid access to their own popular culture. And as corporate profits invariably decline in traditional sectors such as music and film, the pressure to expand control over intellectual property only grows, even though the decline correlates to the increasing market share of cell phones, computer games, and exponentially increasing involvement with social media.4 The challenges posed to the old order by the collaborative logics of Web 2.0 can be seen in many sectors. Collaborative news networks such as Slashdot (‘News for Nerds, Stuff that Matters’, www.slashdot.org) and Kuro5hin (‘Tech- nology and Culture from the Trenches’, www.kuro5hin.org) have blurred the dis- tinctions among editors, readers and writers, with their participants fulfilling all roles. They draw on correspondents and commentaries from around the world, complicating, contradicting, and compositing various bits of information so that the reader must actively consider multiple points of view and sources before mak- ing a determination about the news. In a similar way, open source software initia- tives such as Linux draw upon a community of collaborators, and by keeping the source code open, they direct their energies towards improving functionality rather than building encryption systems. Moreover, with ample networked input and development, they have the advantage that their software mutates and im- proves more quickly than proprietary models. Add low costs into the mix, and it is little wonder that Linux is steadily winning terrain from centralized companies such as Microsoft. Decentralized, networked, collaborative, accretive, ephemeral and dynamic… these developments and others like them bear a closer resemblance to oral cul- tures than to the more stable regimes of print (writing and the printing press) and the trace (photography, film, recorded sound). Time-bound and contingent, they are at odds with the durability of the printed word and photographed image. Spread from person to person, with the always present possibility of manipula- tion and mutability, they differ in the main from the relative stability and unifor- mity of the traditional fixed media.5 And like oral cultures, they seem to evade the preservation frameworks that we have put in place in our institutions of memory, built as they are around tangible media. And yet, despite these conditions, these collaborative efforts also enjoy embodiment as digital text, image and sound, and as such differ from oral culture. They can be apprehended, but the question is, at what point? What constitutes a sufficient ‘capture’ in a dynamic and fast-evolving distributed network where any of the nodes is capable of change.

140 digital material If we take an instance of social media such as Wikipedia, we can see the bene- fits of collaboration and mutability. A reader-edited and written encyclopedia, its entries change over time to reflect new developments, complications in and re- gional inflections of meaning, and the lively debates among its contributors. Its entries evolve, and as such are responsive to the latest undulations of scholarship. Yet, for all of the Wikipedia’s value as a documentary history of changing cultural conceptions and definitions, it confronts the archivist with a problem: what point is the right point to fix and hold for posterity? Social networks such as Friendster and Flickr will offer future researchers invaluable information about the construc- tion and functioning of our society. Not only are they as textually dynamic as Wikipedia, but the fabric of thematic tags (the elements that permit associations on the basis of location, interest, or background) and the patterns of links (as users form elaborate networks) are themselves valuable data. Indeed, the textual data only acquires meaning thanks to these other parameters. Again, what is the archivist to do? It is as if we expected librarians not only to keep books but to track their circulation as well. Yet with social media, circulation is a crucial and defining measure of meaning and import. A third complicating parameter is in- troduced by on-line games, for example MMORPGs (massively multiplayer on- line role-playing games) in which the texts are extraordinarily dynamic, the social networks are crucial to the substance of the game, and the interactions of players with one another are actually constitutive of the gaming experience. Pity the ar- chivist! Yet these games occupy a significant amount of cultural space, have social implications, and provide voice to their users on a variety of topics. The game America’s Army (www.americasarmy.com) not only offers an interesting text against which to read US involvement in Iraq, but it includes remarkable debates among its users over issues that range from the political to the tactical and offer informed readings from voices that researchers rarely have access to.6 In some cultural settings, South Korea for example, the penetration of virtual worlds is enormous and growing (South Korea Telecom’s Cyworld includes nearly half of the population). Is this something that we can afford to ignore, fixating instead on the extension of traditional 19th- and 20th-century cultural forms in our digital and networked present?

Signs of success Social media differ fundamentally from the media around which our archival poli- cies have been constructed. Their rootedness in community and collaborative in- teractions and their responsiveness to an ever-shifting present give them an un- ique quality as Zeitdokumenten, finely grained embodiments of culture. Of all the differences from traditional media discussed above, perhaps the two most diffi- cult ones for memory institutes are 1) that these media are dynamic and always in progress rather than having a final, completed state; and 2) that these media are moving beyond the artefact 141 networked, and that the web of connections bears heavily on the meaning of any one site. These two parameters are not only unfamiliar, but somewhat daunting in terms of their potential storage requirements. Fortunately, as mentioned at the outset, memory is getting cheaper by the day, and transmission speeds are im- proving significantly. But just as importantly, the very distributed logic that en- ables social media and peer-to-peer (P2P) applications holds a potential solution to the storage problem. Consider music file exchanges such as Napster or Grok- ster and the like. They managed something well beyond the physical (let alone financial) capacities of the traditional music industry by digitalizing a vast amount of music, storing it, and distributing it on demand to millions of users. They did this by networking millions of personal computers in homes across the world, distributing the tasks of digitalization, storage and access in such a way that the cost was negligible and the labor involved was freely given. Millions of modestly sized memory chips and processors, when properly linked, emerge as a formid- able and robust computing force far beyond the potentials of any one centralized system. This network, the basis after all of social media, could also potentially be put to use as a decentralized memory institute, complete with the redundancies, checks, and quality controls currently evident in many existing applications. And the best part is that there are working examples of this principle! One of America’s founding fathers, Thomas Jefferson, summarized the princi- ple upon which a new distributed archive would operate:

let us save what remains: not by vaults and locks which fence them from the public eye and use in consigning them to the waste of time, but by such a multiplication of copies, as shall place them beyond the reach of accident (1791, n.p).

Jefferson was speaking of ways to assure the preservation of America’s founding documents, but a clearer and more succinct summary of the differences between the traditional and the new archive is difficult to imagine. In this spirit, LOCKSS (‘Lots of Copies Keep Stuff Safe’, www.lockss.org) offers a splendid working ex- ample. In their own words, ‘LOCKSS is open source software that provides librar- ians with an easy and inexpensive way to collect, store, preserve, and provide access to their own, local copy of authorized content they purchase. Running on standard desktop hardware and requiring almost no technical administration, LOCKSS converts a personal computer into a digital preservation appliance, creat- ing low-cost, persistent, accessible copies of e-journal content as it is published. Since pages in these appliances are never flushed, the local community’s access to that content is safeguarded. Accuracy and completeness of LOCKSS appliances is assured through a robust and secure, peer-to-peer polling and reputation system.’ Just as LOCKSS is exemplary of a solution that makes use of distributed com- puting, other examples have tackled the problem of capturing the dynamic and

142 digital material extensive character of the web. Nearly synonymously with the appearance of the World Wide Web, Brewster Kahle initiated his remarkable Internet archive known as the Wayback Machine (www.archive.org). With over 50 billion web pages ar- chived since its inception in 1996, the archive is composed of ‘snapshots’ of web- sites taken at regular intervals, allowing the interested researcher to go back in time and track changes. The previously mentioned ‘discrepancy’ in the White House Press Secretary’s rewriting of a or attempts to rewrite the CVs of Enron officials after their company’s collapse came to light thanks to this archive. But for the cultural historian, having access to the first decade of the World Wide Web’s existence and with it the ability to track the emergence of social protocols, home page formats, early games, etc. is an invaluable resource. And the best part is that Mr. Kahle managed to capture the dynamic character of the web with a modest infrastructure and limited budget. With a mirror site in Alexandria, Egypt, the archive’s discursive claim is loud, clear and, I think, not at all overstated. With a more fulsome budget, the archive could expand its opera- tions and the frequency of its ‘snapshots’, but for the moment, its beauty is that it works efficiently and outside the entanglements of national governments and funding agencies. For once in our media history, someone has managed to both think ahead and act accordingly. LOCKSS and the Wayback Machine offer two splendid examples of what is possible, one growing out of the efforts of progressive librarians and the other from an insightful and resourceful individual. Together, they have solved several of the problems unique to the digital domain. The issue of mapping links and social-networking patterns has been taken on in the aggregate (social-network mapping and analysis is a developed field, and can take on the face-to-face as easily as the digitally networked). The difficulty here turns on issues of privacy and the potentials for misuse, just as the problems potentially facing Internet archives turn on issues of intellectual property. Social problems rather than con- ceptual or technological difficulties seem to be the order of the day, which is where an organization like UNESCO can be of great help.

Conclusions Digital media have blurred relations between the once clearly demarcated realms of producers and consumers. As these digital technologies have become net- worked and entered a state of high connectivity, a process that is roughly a decade old, we have seen the fast emergence of new social media forms. Social media have enabled new forms of collaboration, and they provide what Pierre Lévy de- scribes as a collective intelligence. In so doing, they have rapidly intensified the erosion of traditional and highly centralized organizations through a process of redefinition. Collaborative news networks compete with established , in the process redefining the news from an institutional assertion of facticity to moving beyond the artefact 143 an act of critical engagement and a struggle for meaning. Music file exchanges such as KaZaa compete with the established recording industry, in the process transforming music from a commodity to be bought and sold into communities of taste built upon distributed sharing. And open source software developers compete with the Microsofts of the world, in the process redefining software from a commodity to a collaborative language and community tool. So, too, the world of the archive. The traditional archive has served as a social agent active in the reproduction of culture. By serving as a repository of what key institutions deem valuable, archives preserve cultural values and sustain hierar- chies of social and cultural power. Given the very real limits of space and re- sources, difficult decisions have been made regarding whose letters to keep, which to store, and which sort of artefactual ephemera to hold. Not surprisingly, these decisions reflect an institutional sense of importance and rele- vance, which in turn largely maps onto the vision of the dominant classes. Little wonder that researchers seeking traces of immigrant life in the US at the turn of the century, or marginal political and social movements of the present, have such difficulty in finding relevant archival sources. But new archival practices that at- tempt to account for social media forms such as blogs, wikis, chat spaces, games, etc., enabled through distributed logic, enhanced storage capacity and accelerated transmission speeds, can redefine the archive from social agent to social practice. By embracing bottom-up dynamics, they will better reflect a wide range of social values, not just the ruling elite. By addressing cultural production that takes place outside of confines of corporate media, they will assume a much wider range of social granularity. And by taking advantage of the new affordances of digitally networked culture, they will encourage widespread participation. Archives reflect the environments in which they are situated, and new environ- ments require new policies. As I have attempted to argue, networked digital tech- nologies and ‘participatory culture’ offer new challenges to both cultural produ- cers and archives, generating new producers and users, new content and collaborators. But they also offer solutions that might be used to rethink the ca- pacities and logics of the archive (storage, distribution, dynamic capture). The examples of the Wayback Machine and LOCKSS show what is possible and pro- vide provocations to more traditional archives to consider these new possibilities. Challenges, of course, remain. We need to think carefully about issues of privacy (for the archiving of network maps) and intellectual property (long overdue for an overhaul in the age of cut and paste). We must make careful distinctions in the weights of various cultural artefacts between say, diplomatic documents and bottle collections, and develop different strategies for safeguarding and making both available. But above all, we must build upon the pioneering efforts of the few visionaries who have ventured into this new world, archiving the fast development of this dynamic cultural sector, and guarding against their selective and strategic

144 digital material use/misuse by those in positions of power, and making information accessible to all in accordance with the cultural logic of the age.

This article is an updated version of ‘Moving beyond the artifact: Lessons from participa- tory culture’ in Preserving the digital heritage: Principles and policies, eds. Yola De Lusenet and Vincent Wintermans, 15-25. Amsterdam: Netherlands National Commission for Unesco, 2007.

Notes 1. For a detailed examination of this issue from the perspectives of both film theory and archival practice, see Giovanna Fossati’s From grain to pixel: The archival life of film transi- tion (PhD dissertation, Utrecht University 2009). 2. In fact, most of our cultural texts are profoundly intertextual, relying upon layer upon layer of precedent, commentary and reference. Particularly since the Romantic Era, we have tended to suppress this unruly aspect of authorship, a practice today enforced by the strictures of intellectual property. The digital turn has forced the question upon us, and as we think through the implications for new media forms, we might reconsider the questions put forward by the likes of Michel Foucault and Roland Barthes and re- flect upon what we have long forgotten about the reign of authorship. 3. But one example involves President Bush’s 2003 ‘mission accomplished’ declaration in regard to Iraq on the USS Abraham Lincoln. If we set aside for a moment the staging of the press conference (the background contained a banner reading ‘mission accom- plished’ and photographers were forbidden to take any shots that would show that the ship was in fact not at sea, but instead docked in San Diego harbor), the White House took an additional step to control information that amounted to rewriting history. The office of the Press Secretary initially issued a statement on its website on May, 1 2003, entitled ‘President Bush announces combat operations in Iraq have ended’. Later, after it was clear that combat had not ended, the headline was modified to read ‘Major Op- erations’. The press release, a matter of record, was reworked to accord with White House spin, but backdated to May 1, and attempts were made to prohibit access to the earlier and now telltale version. Thanks to regular archiving of the website, the White House was found out, and future historians will understand that the criticism generated by the first version was based on real events, not the fantasies and misinterpretations alleged by the White House after its revision of the historical record. 4. The market success of Japanese manga and anime in the US (where manga outsells do- mestic comic books by a factor of four to one) is due in large part to the work of fans who imported, translated and circulated these cultural products without copyright clearance. They effectively created a commercial market, tested it, and their translations in many cases remain superior to commercial alternatives. The industry understands the value of these ‘pirates’, and both sides have worked out a harmonious co-existence. 5. Although in truth, written texts such as Shakespeare’s plays have undergone hundreds of small (and sometimes major) transformations, and films routinely change as they pass through the hands of censors and countless projectionists. Nevertheless, they are relatively stable compared to the dynamic state of wikis, blogs, and other social media. 6. For an extensive discussion of America’s Army, see the chapter by David Nieborg in this book.

moving beyond the artefact 145 References Jefferson, Thomas. 1984 (orig.1791) Thomas Jefferson to Ebenezer Hazard, Philadelphia, February 18, 1791. In Thomas Jefferson: Writings: Autobiography, notes on the state of Virgi- nia, public and private papers, addresses, letters, ed. Merrill D. Peterson. New York: Library of America. Cited on the homepage of LOCKSS.

146 digital material Participation inside?

User activities between design and appropriation

Mirko Tobias Schäfer

In the summer of 1999, a little cat awakened the monolithic music industry that was sleeping its way into the digital age. The cat wore headphones and was the logo of a small application called Napster crawling over the Internet. Millions of people used the application to search for music files and download them on their computer. Developed by a 19-year-old university student, the Napster software did nothing more than index music files stored on a user’s computer and share this information with other users in the network. Napster changed the logic for the distribution of digitized artefacts for good as peer-to-peer (P2P) file-sharing technologies enabled the global distribution of di- gital information at negligibly low costs. But first and foremost Napster is re- markable because it represents an effective concept of global distribution of arte- facts neither developed nor controlled by those industries that have built their business models and economical power on the control of distribution. Napster and its successors tell a well-known tale of computer technology and the Internet, a story of media use as a battle between consumers and producers. Distribution through peer-to-peer systems was soon recognized as subverting the established cultural industries. It also fostered the legend of enthusiast amateurs producing artefacts of a quality that can meet or even beat industrial products. Due to these and other developments, new media have gained the imago of being enabling technologies that could turn the former consumer of corporate media content from dupe into hero, mastering the new means of production and actively participating in the creation and distribution of – mostly digital – arte- facts. And indeed, the new technologies have led to an emerging media practice where users participate significantly in the production and distribution of the cul- tural industry’s goods (Bruns 2008; Jenkins 2002, 2006a, 2006b; Jenkins et al. 2006; Jenkins and Thoburn 2003; Schäfer 2005, 2006). Recently, popular dis- course is embracing the phenomenon of producing users, labeling them Genera- tion C (c for content), 1 anticipating a revolution of pro-ams, professional amateurs (Leadbeater, Miller 2004), and describing their production logic as Wikinomics (Tapscott, Williams 2006). With reference to Pierre Lévy, the aspect of a plurality

147 of users collectively producing content and creating artefacts online has been un- derstood as ‘collective intelligence’ (Jenkins 2001). Metaphors such as the wisdom of crowds (Surowiecki 2005) or the wealth of networks (Benkler 2006) show collective interactions to be an ‘invisible hand’ in creating prosperity. To Henry Jenkins, the emerging media practice constitutes a converging of different participants and old and new media practices into a field where the distinctions between user and producer are increasingly blurred (Jenkins 2006). Axel Bruns has coined the term produsage for the newly emerging practices, and labels participants in production communities as both users and producers (Bruns 2008). The second coming of the World Wide Web – Web 2.0 – thrives on the imma- nent promise of user participation in social interactions, and the collective gen- eration and sharing of content. In 2006, Time magazine put a face to this promise when it nominated the generic computer user (‘YOU’) Person of the Year.2 By claiming that YOU, the user, has risen to become the hero of the Information Age, the perception of consumers as dupes seems to have been abandoned for good, and we seem to have finally become a participatory culture (Jenkins 2006a). However, as the examples above have indicated, this take on new media culture often leads to simplified and rather romanticized interpretations, in popular cul- ture as well as media theory. Only a critical analysis of the term and its connota- tions can help to understand the underlying mechanisms and the intertwined dy- namic of the various participants. According to Jenkins, the criteria defining participatory culture are ‘low bar- riers to artistic expression and civic engagement’, ‘strong support for creating and sharing one’s creations with others’, and ‘informal mentorship whereby what is known by the most experienced is passed along to novices’, as well as the belief ‘that their contributions matter’ and that ‘members feel some degree of social connection with one another’ (Jenkins et al. 2006; Benkler 2006). Participa- tion is here formulated as a community-based activity determined by a high de- gree of social interaction and mutual understanding among its participants. In cultural studies the term participation describes audiences engaging in culture by receiving, interpreting, and deconstructing media texts, and most recently through acts of appropriation and creation. This perception is highly influenced by ideological connotations (Jenkins et al. 2006; Benkler 2006) that identify parti- cipation as a process of explicit and conscious, often intrinsically motivated activ- ities of users claiming their cultural freedom from the culture industries.3 Along with the explicit participation described by Jenkins and others, the emergence of the so-called Web 2.0 shows an implicit participation where user activities are channeled and directed through software design. Recent research has demon- strated how media industries have implemented those activities in their business models, questioning the romanticized understanding of participation (Van Dijck and Nieborg 2008; Scholz 2008; Zimmer 2008).

148 digital material The mechanisms shaping explicit and implicit participation are far more com- plex, however, and a thorough analysis of the dynamic interaction between users, corporate companies, artefacts, and socio-technical ecosystems is lacking. An- other aspect that deserves more attention is the dynamic interplay constituting aspects of collectivism and collaboration. Bruns has recently pointed out that the community and the collective are misleading metaphors in describing the social interaction on the Internet (Bruns 2008:327). This chapter tries to design a new concept that appropriately describes and analyzes the phenomenon of massive user interactions.

Mapping user activities In general, participatory culture unfolds in three domains described hereafter as accumulation, archiving, and construction. These three domains are not mutually ex- clusive and overlap to a certain extent. The logic of electronic distribution and copying of files applies to all three of them. As will be described later, recent soft- ware design for information management systems channels these user activities and proposes interfaces and functions that stimulate and regulate them. Accumulation describes all activities evolving around texts originally produced within the established media industries. This content is collected, altered, further developed or remixed by users and dedicated fans. Examples include the large Star Wars fan community producing their own Star Wars movies on websites such as TheForce.net or the so-called slash fiction communities Jenkins has described (1991). These communities alter traditional media texts, for example by develop- ing homosexual narratives involving popular media characters like Harry Potter. Archiving refers to the organization, maintenance and distribution of digital ar- tefacts. This ranges from providing public-domain books in digital formats, such as Project Gutenberg does, to hosting the productions of specific cultural niches like demos or music files from the – a subculture developing ani- mated realtime graphics – or the production and free distribu- tion of the so-called netlabel scene. The Internet Archive (Archive.org) is probably the most well-known example for storing and preserving data online. This important resource archives material provided by common users as well as established institutions and professionals and is maintained by a foundation. Although archiving tends to be more institu- tionalized than accumulating, both areas overlap, for instance in fan archives and the often sophisticated strategies users employ to allocate and share licensed con- tent like movies, audio files, and computer games. In general, the sector of ar- chiving describes all means of indexing, storing, and structuring data for access and easy information retrieval. Construction describes forms of production that take place outside the estab- lished production and distribution channels. Prime examples are open-source participation inside? 149 software, the demo scene, and the netlabel scene. The domain of construction overlaps with accumulation insofar as users alter software-based products and build new applications for devices initially programmed by commercial vendors. It shows overlaps with archiving in all areas where infrastructures for storing, organizing, and maintaining information are built and knowledge systems are created, such as online software repositories (e.g. Sourceforge.net), and collec- tively created open-access encyclopedias such as Wikipedia. The three domains of user activities extend the established culture industries and form a new and complex set of relations between producers and consumers (see Figure 1). Instead of replacing them, these new modes complement older modes of production, distribution, and consumption, and can therefore be de- scribed as establishing an extended culture industry. The extended culture industries are characterized by the dynamic interaction of all participating parties. Produc- tion processes are not only extended into the domain of users – where the (old) culture industry’s media texts and products are appropriated – but also happen completely independent of established production and distribution channels. In conclusion, we can state that this present culture is constituted by new design and appropriation of existing content, unfolding along the lines of accumulation, con- struction, and archiving from the culture industries to its fringes and beyond.

Figure 1: User activities extend the culture industries

150 digital material Material aspects of design and appropriation The agency of technology in enabling or averting certain media practices has only recently been acknowledged in media theoretical analysis (Rieder and Schäfer 2008; Schäfer 2006; Hughes and Lang 2006). Due to their technological make- up, some digital artefacts can be reused, modified, and developed more easily than others. Hughes and Lang describe this quality as transmutability (2006). In general, all software-based artefacts are transmutable because computer compo- nents and software are open to modification. There is a relatively superficial level, like enthusiast fans who photoshop their favorite TV characters or remix their personal hit songs, but in fact every -based product or digi- tized artefact can enter a second stage of development, and rigorous transmuta- tions yield surprising results. A Microsoft Xbox becomes a Linux computer, Nin- tendo’s Gameboy is turned into a musical instrument, Sony’s robot dog Aibo learns how to dance, and the robotic vacuum cleaner Roomba attracts skilled program- mers who use the affordable device for experiments in artificial intelligence and robotics.4 The modifications of these products are rooted in the basic affordances of computer technology, software, and the Internet. Affordances are specific qua- lities of material and artefacts, and they affect design and use to a great degree (Norman 1998, 9). To be more precise, the affordance of electronic computers to copy files without loss is crucial to an application like Napster and the new logic of distribution. This logic is inherent to electronic computers; for the execution of any given task, they need to copy files from memory to a . As such, computers can be described as universal machines that can execute basi- cally every task formulated in a language the machine understands. Software con- stitutes the many different applications that can be executed by any computer (Turing 1948). Despite the fact that software is bound to a material data carrier, it shows parallels with language in its structure, while in its effect it is similar to machinery (Rieder and Schäfer 2008, 163). Software is a means of production organized and structured as (programming) language. Like language, it is also modular, and parts of one software application can be used for a completely dif- ferent activity. Such pre-programmed modules are available with a framework for software development. Programming software therefore implies the reuse of pre- viously written software. Taken together, all available software constitutes a reser- voir, a cultural resource, that programmers use and to which they contribute at the same time. Software as a cultural resource is distributed and made available through the Internet that forms a global infrastructure and connects all users. It is due to this hybrid constellation of technological qualities that the Internet has become today’s primary medium for collaboration and communication, and a universal archive for all kinds of information. An application like Napster is profoundly related to the affordances of compu- ter technology, software and the Internet, and the way users deal with these tech- participation inside? 151 nologies. While Napster is nothing more than a bricolage of a file-transport pro- tocol combined with a chat program and a graphical user interface for convenient use, it satisfied the technological requirements of the digital age: Napster’s de- sign perfectly fitted the qualities of the Internet. While the music industry was unaware of the looming digital revolution, the logic of distributing media texts electronically through computer networks developed through the appropriation of a set of existing technologies, such as the (FTP), the MPEG format for compressed audio and movie files (e.g. mp3 and DivX), music player applications as WinAmp, and programs for automated indexing, retrieval and distribution of files.

The history of Napster teaches us that the availability of technologies plus the knowledge of how to generate, use, and recombine them create potentiality. Wil- liam Gibson’s well-known line ‘the street finds its own uses for things’ (2003, 199) obviously applies to the virtual landscape of the Internet and its users. Nap- ster also demonstrates that participation and collective collaboration can take place on a very basic level and that the user-collective can improve the infrastruc- ture for retrieving files and information. It worked like this: after downloading the Napster application, the user contributed to the overall file-sharing network by allowing a part of her hard drive to function as a server for file exchange, by uploading files to the network. The Napster application indexed the files a user shared and made those data available for search requests. P2P file-sharing clients such as Napster have revealed that has much less to do with explicit participation and community-driven objectives than enthusiast commentators an- ticipated. Actually – and by technological design – participation became an auto- mated process, completely unrelated to community values, social interaction or communication in general. Although those aspects are optional in many software applications, they are far from necessary for sharing files. In an attempt to limit the damage caused by digital distribution through P2P networks, the music industry started appropriating the technology itself by setting up networks of fake users, so-called bot networks, that flooded the file-sharing systems with corrupted song files. Old business models and new media practice collided at the level of popular discourse, where fans promoted piracy as an ap- propriate activity in view of the music and movie industries’ tight control over how music is consumed, a debate also reflected by the design of P2P networks and the attempts of the industry to protect their products through copy-protection systems and Digital Rights Management (DRM). Triggering a reciprocal competi- tion, the protective move of the established industries stimulated the improve- ment of file-sharing protocols like eDonkey and BitTorrent, as each new copy-pro- tection system was countered by a more advanced cracking technology.5 This combat not only charged technology emotionally. The harsh reaction of the med- ia giants and their representative associations also revealed another aspect of

152 digital material technologies’ social use: due to its affordances, its development is very much dri- ven by users’ appropriation and its resulting formalization in new design solu- tions. The interplay of technological design and appropriation analyzed here using the example of Napster, sheds a different light on participation. Participation can- not be assigned only to users who get involved with media and ‘oppose’ a domi- nant vendor. The original producer and other commercial units – who are either actively involved in the process of modifying the original design or benefit from its outcome – are also part of participatory culture. Implementing user labor in the development of design by commercial vendors is a usually neglected aspect in enthusiasts’ descriptive texts on participatory culture (e.g. Jenkins 2006b; Benkler 2006). The most recent Microsoft game console, for example, features many as- pects developed by the so-called scene. As unlicensed users of the Micro- soft Xbox Development Kit (XDK), these hackers designed many useful applications for the Xbox. Their work was distributed within user networks and, due to its unlicensed status, not commercially exploitable. Microsoft however learned from this experience and integrated many features into the next Xbox 360, also provid- ing an Integrated Development Kit (IDK) that can be used to create software and dis- tribute it through the Xbox network. Microsoft achieved technological closure by consequently implementing user activities and appropriation into the design and legal regulation of the successive Xbox model. It is claimed that user activities revolve around explicit participation, which thrives on intrinsic motivation and often takes place in teams or ad-hoc and team-like collectives (e.g. Bruns 2008 on Wikipedia; Jenkins 2006 on fans of the television program Survivor; Raessens 2005 on game modifications; Schäfer 2005 on the modification of the Xbox). However, there is also implicit participation. Implicit participation can be part of the software design as the sharing of a part of the user’s hard drive in P2P file-sharing. It is automated and delegated to an information system, not requiring any intrinsic motivation, community feeling or collaborative effort. Implementing participation into software design entails for- malizing and channeling user activities. It is no coincidence that Tim O’Reilly has dubbed this design step an architecture of participation. In his programmatic text ‘What is Web 2.0’, he describes basic configurations of channeling user participa- tion for commercial ends (2005). User activities are thus employed for the im- provement of information systems and the generation of content, which either extends the content of the commercial provider or constitutes its main potential. The explicit participation of user communities in developing technology is im- plemented into new design decisions, but Web 2.0 applications show that next to explicit participation, implicit participation can be employed to improve existing information systems and to build new business models of cultural production.

participation inside? 153 Participation as design or the return of the audience Culture industries are witnessing a shift from creating content to providing plat- forms for user-driven activities. On these platforms the users create content or alter existing content from the proprietary resources of the cultural industries according to their regulations. The Star Wars MashUp editor, for example, aims at fans who accumulate media texts relating to their favorite subject and alter them or create new ones. The TheForce.net has become a popular platform for creating, promoting, and hosting fan movies. Featuring tutorials on how to make fan movies or create computer-generated imagery for space ships and special ef- fects, it has earned a reputation as the best Star Wars website out there. The copy- right holder Lucasfilm acknowledged the need for fans to play with the media texts but controls this play through a corporate web platform. The Star Wars Mash- Up editor offers fans the opportunity to exercise their creativity and equips them with the means to do so. It does so, however, with strict restrictions, trapping the fans on the Death Star so to speak, as they are bound to the corporation’s design and legal regulations. The MashUp editor prevents downloads of any content to users’ hard drives, and editing of content is possible only in the web-based editor Lucasfilm provides. Using other editing programs is prohibited as well, as are certain forms of representation. Nudity for instance is recognized and filtered through the Eyespot editing software, avoiding displays of naked persons in user- created remixes.6 Furthermore, fans’ creations may be published by the corporate platform only, and any distribution through YouTube or other services is forbid- den. Finally, Lucasfilm requires that users grant to Lucasfilm, ‘its licensees, suc- cessors and affiliates a perpetual and irrevocable, exclusive, royalty free, world- wide license in all rights, titles and interests of every kind and nature’ to their self-created content.7 This practice of extending the value of a proprietary re- source through fans while at the same time denying these fans any form of authorial compensation and even freedom of creativity is highly questionable (Lessig 2007). Increasingly, user creations are subject to the software design and legal admin- istration of corporate platforms that explicitly integrate user activities into their services. The so-called Web 2.0 applications O’Reilly refers to take participation to another level by implementing it into software design for the purpose of chan- neling user activities implicitly. On the photo platform Flickr users might not even notice how publishing their personal photos, adding a title to them, or even placing them on a map is extending the Flickr information system. By simply uploading a photo, users contribute data on the camera model, date and time of picture, camera settings, etc. These so-called Exchangeable Image File (EXIF) data are metadata generally attached to pictures taken by standard digital cam- eras. By adding tags, keywords, to the pictures, users compensate the information systems’ lack of semantic information retrieval. The machine cannot read a pic-

154 digital material ture, but it can read the meta-information provided either by the camera through the EFIX data or by users who add title, location, and certain keywords. By using it, users extend the overall information system and contribute to an improved information management. By providing valuable meta-information in tags of up- loaded photos, users improve the information retrieval of Yahoo’s search engine, Flickr’s owner. Thanks to Flickr’s tagging system, Yahoo is able to compensate the inability of search engines to recognize a picture’s content. User-generated meta-information teaches the machine to answer complex search requests. Contrary to earlier accounts of participation, I have shown that systems that thrive on the implementation of user activities are not dependent on or encoura- ging community activities. There are Flickr groups, which might be considered communities because they share objectives, rules, regular communication, and recurring patterns of social interaction as well as offline gatherings. But these activities are an optional function in the system’s design and not a precondition for the cultural production it generates. Despite the fact that users are participat- ing in the creation of an information system and collectively building a resource of stored data and metadata for efficient information retrieval, they do not neces- sarily share a common goal or social interaction. Adding photos to Flickr can involve different uses and gratifications and therefore is not limited to explicit participation as commonly understood. The idealizing connotations of participa- tion as a critical, communal and social activity has to be revisited in the light of software design that channels user activities as implicit participation. The affordances of networked media, which enable large groups of users to actively participate in cultural production, and the high amount of user-generated content in different domains of cultural production have led to the assumption that the promise of participation has been fulfilled. But software design employ- ing these user activities as implicit participation calls for critically revisiting the way technology is designed, used, and appropriated. Large user numbers provid- ing valuable personal data through the interfaces of platforms such as social net- work sites (e.g. Facebook, MySpace, Orkut, Hyves, and LinkedIn), giving ratings through media sites such as YouTube, and affecting search results in Yahoo through the provision of metadata to Flickr once again posits the audience as a source for market research and target for advertising. This clearly contrasts the utopian ideal of a user-controlled participatory culture. Figure 2 shows a number of applications that successfully employ user activities from the domains of accu- mulation, archiving, and construction, and implement them into corporate-con- trolled platforms.

participation inside? 155 Figure 2: Implementation of user activities into commercial applications

The interaction of large numbers of users, user activities-channeling interfaces, and intelligent information systems show participatory culture to be a hybrid, a socio-technical ecosystem. The many possible motivations for using these sys- tems, as well as the plurality of social interaction, reflects heterogeneous partici- pation that can hardly be grasped with the ideological connotations of earlier en- thusiast accounts. It will be necessary instead to critically analyze how software design affects user behavior and how power structures are re-established through implementing participation in information systems.

Notes 1. Generation C. In Trendwatching.com, March 2004. www.trendwatching.com/trends/GEN- ERATION_C.htm (accessed June 2008). 2. Time, December 25/January 1, 2007. 3. For a further analysis and critique of the utopian perception of participation, see Eggo Müller in this volume. 4. The Xbox-Linux Project is hosted at: www.xbox-linux.org (accessed June 2008). There are a number of musicians using the software Little Sound DJ, Nanoloop or Pocketnoise to produce music on the Game Boy; see Game Boy Music Club Vienna http://www. gameboymusicclub.org/ (accessed June 2008). The hacker Aibopet offers a large num- ber of programs on his website www.aibohack.com. The program DiskoAibo, which

156 digital material makes Aibo dance, is available there as well. The Roomba modders meet at Roomba Community, http://www.roombacommunity.com/ (Acessed June 2008). 5. Companies like Overpeer flooded P2P networks with corrupted files on behalf of music companies and industry associations. In order to do so, they set up fake networks of virtual file sharers distributing the corrupted files. As Thomas Mennecke (2005) argues, these efforts consequently lead to the development of safer and less corruptible file- sharing protocols such as BitTorrent and eDonkey. Due to its inefficiency, Overpeer was discontinued in 2005 after three years of anti-P2P activity. 6. Ideological and sociopolitical issues can be channeled through software design. Devel- oping hermeneutics and methods of analysis is an important task for media studies to accordingly interpret and criticize ‘back-end politics’ inscribed into design decisions. 7. Section C and E of the Lucasfilm’s Star Wars MashUps Terms of Service. http://starwars. com/welcome/about/mashup-copyright (accessed August 2007).

Acknowledgements I am indebted to Bernhard Rieder, Tanja Sihvonen and Kim de Vries for their comments and helpful remarks.

References Benkler, Yochai. 2006. The wealth of networks: How social production transforms markets and free- doms. New Haven, London: Yale University Press. Bruns, Axel. 2008. Blogs, Wikipedia, Second Life, and beyond: From production to produsage. New York: Peter Lang. Dijck, José van, and David Nieborg. 2008. De opmars van de cybernauten: Drie nieuwe studies geven hun visie op de digitale participatiecultuur. Academische Boekengids 65, No- vember 2007, 7-10. Gibson, William. [1982] 2003. Burning chrome. In Burning chrome, William Gibson, 179- 204. New York: Eos. Gillmor, Dan. 2006. We the media: Grassroots by the people, for the people. Sebastopol: O’Reilly Media. Hughes, Lang. 2006. Transmutability: Digital decontextualization, manipulation, and re- contextualization as a new source of value in the production and consumption of cul- ture products. Proceedings of the 39th Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences. http:// doi.ieeecomputersociety.org/10.1109/HICSS.2006.511. Jenkins, Henry. 2002. Interactive audiences? The collective intelligence of media fans. In The new media book, ed. Dan Harries. London: BFI. —. 2006a. Fans, bloggers, and gamers: Exploring participatory culture. New York: New York Uni- versity Press. —. 2006b. Convergence culture: Where old and new media collide. New York: New York University Press. Jenkins, Henry, Katie Clinton, Ravi Purushotma, Alice J. Robison, and Margaret Weigel. 2006. Confronting the challenges of participatory culture: Media education for the 21st century. MacArthur Foundation. http://www.digitallearning.macfound.org/atf/cf/% 7B7E45C7E0-A3E0-4B89-AC9C-E807E1B0AE4E%7D/JENKINS_WHITE_PAPER.PDF. participation inside? 157 Jenkins, Henry, and David Thoburn. 2003. Democracy and new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Lessig, Lawrence. 2007. Lucasfilm’s Phantom Menace. The Washington Post, July 12 2007. http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/07/11/ AR2007071101996_pf.html. Leadbeater, Charles, and Paul Miller. 2004. The pro-am revolution. London: Demos. Lévy, Pierre. 1999. Collective intelligence: Mankind’s emerging world in cyberspace. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Books. Mennecke, Thomas. 2005. End of the road for Overpeer. Slyck News, December 10 2005. http://www.slyck.com/story1019.html. Norman, Donald. 1998. The design of everyday things. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. O’Reilly, Tim. 2005. What is Web 2.0. http://www.oreillynet.com/pub/a/oreilly/tim/news/ 2005/09/30/what-is-web-20.html. Rieder, Bernhard, and Mirko Tobias Schäfer. 2008. Beyond engineering: Software design as bridge over the culture/technology dichotomy. In Philosophy and design: From engineer- ing to architecture, eds. Pieter E. Vermaas, Peter Kroes, Andrew Light, and Steven A. Moore, 152-164. Dordrecht: Springer. Schäfer, Mirko Tobias. 2005. Homework: The extension of the culture industry. In Data browser 01: Economising culture, eds. Geoff Cox, Joasia Krysa, and Anya Lewin, 191-199. Brooklyn: Autonomedia. Schäfer, Mirko Tobias. 2006. Partizipation als Output des Konsums softwarebasierter Pro- dukte. In Das Spiel mit dem Medium: Partizipation – Immersion – Interaktion, eds. Britta Neit- zel and Rolf Nohr, 296-310. Marburg: Schüren. Scholz, Trebor. 2008. Market ideology and the myths of Web 2.0. First Monday 13 (3). http://www.uic.edu/htbin/cgiwrap/bin/ojs/index.php/fm/article/view/2138/1945. Surowiecki, James. 2005. The wisdom of crowds: Why the many are smarter than the few and how collective wisdom shapes business, economies, societies and nations. New York: Random House. Tapscott, Don, and Anthony D. Williams. 2006. Wikinomics: How mass collaboration changes everything. New York: Portfolio. Turing, Alan M. 1948. Intelligent machinery. National Physical Laboratory Report. http://www. alanturing.net/turing_archive/archive/l/l32/L32-001.html. Uricchio, William. 2004. Cultural citizenship in the age of P2P networks. In European culture and the media, eds. Ib Bondebjerg and Peter Golding. Bristol: Intellect Books. Zimmer, Michael. 2008. The externalities of Search 2.0: The emerging privacy threats when the drive for the perfect search engine meets Web 2.0. First Monday, 13 (3) 2008. http:// www.uic.edu/htbin/cgiwrap/bin/ojs/index.php/fm/article/view/2136/1944.

158 digital material Challenging the magic circle

How online role-playing games are negotiated by everyday life

Marinka Copier

‘Darn,’ I cursed at myself as I walked up to my desk to turn on my computer. It was mid- September 2006, I looked at my watch, it was already 7:15 pm and I wanted to be logged onto the online game World of Warcraft around 7:30 pm. Considering that it was a Sun- day evening, there would probably be a queue of a few hundred players who wanted to connect to the Argent Dawn role-play server, just like me. This meant it would be impos- sible to get logged on before 8:00 pm. I tried to remember what Eiswein wrote in his post on the official server forum. The caravan of the Argent Archives would leave for Thelsamar from outside the gates of the Alliance city of Ironforge at 8:30 pm. The dwarven Archivar Eiswein, a character played by Jørgen (24, Norwegian), head of the Argent Archives role- play guild and organizer of the event, had asked player-characters to arrive early so he could hand out assignments and missions. While Windows loaded, I made a quick to-do list: 1) As we would be traveling through the virtual winter landscape of Dun Morogh I had to dress my gnome character Speckles Snapwiggle in proper clothes – gloves and furry- looking boots would be essential for a wintry feel, 2) I had to move Speckles from the Alliance capital city of Stormwind to Ironforge – the Deeprun Tram that runs between the two cities would probably be the fastest, 3) I wanted to answer some letters sent through the in-game postal system. Most of them were job offers for Speckles, who together with her twin sister Freckles formed a photographers duo called the Snap . This means they take on jobs that involve photographing characters and role-play events such as weddings, sporting events, trials, beauty pageants, markets, and, in this case, the Archives caravan. I (29, Dutch) picked up my mobile phone and rang my friend Zoe (28, Dutch), who played the role of the character Freckles. ‘Are you already in?’ I asked, ‘Is there a queue?’ It turned out that she had been playing the whole day, and yes, she heard there was quite a queue. There were 260 players in front of me in the queue – I mumbled. Zoe laughed: ‘Be happy if you make it by eight.’‘I’ll get something to eat first, then,’ I replied.

159 The ambiguity of play In massively multiplayer online role-playing games (MMORPGs) such as World of Warcraft (WoW, Blizzard Entertainment 2004), large numbers of players come to- gether in a complex online environment not only to defeat monsters and each other in return for virtual gold and armour, but also to turn their avatars into colourful characters by roleplaying them. The above is an excerpt of my auto- ethnographic account of the gnome warrior and photographer Speckles Snapwig- gle, one of the characters I played during my two-year participatory ethnographic study of role play in WoW (Copier 2007). According to the game studies concept of the ‘magic circle’, games proceed within their own boundaries of time and space, absorbing players utterly into a separate world set off from ordinary life (Salen and Zimmerman 2004). In this chapter I challenge the concept and metaphor of the magic circle. As T.L. Taylor argued in Play between worlds, an ethnographic study of the MMORPG Everquest (Sony Online Entertainment 1999), the notion that we can or should (re)constitute game boundaries ‘thereby solving the deeper social and regulatory issues that can nag us’ is very problematic (Taylor 2006, 151). Although at first glance the above thick description of logging onto WoW might seem to illustrate a process of entering into a magic circle, I argue that the magic circle, which resonates references to ‘walled off’ magic rites and places, supernatural powers, illusions and experiences, blinds us to the ambiguous qua- lities of games and game play. The thick description also shows that game play is not only shaped by experiences within the online gaming environment but – often simultaneously – by (mediated) experiences outside, both online and offline. Not only before and after logging onto the game, but also while being logged on, I find myself negotiating the spatial, temporal and social dimensions of the game play experience. It is precisely this process of negotiating rules and boundaries that shape not only role play in MMORPGs, but games and game play in general. As the emergence of Fantasy1 gaming culture from the 1970s onwards, of which WoW is merely the latest incarnation, ties in with the development of what Man- uel Castells termed the ‘network society’ (Castells 1996), I introduce the network perspective as an alternative to the magic circle. The network perspective makes it possible to understand the ambiguous qualities of online role-playing games.

Role-playing games and the network society More than 30 years ago, in January 1974, in a garage in the city of Lake Geneva near Minneapolis, Gary Gygax and Dave Anderson hand-assembled the booklets that made up (what is generally considered to be) the first Fantasy role-playing game called Dungeons and Dragons (D&D). Back then it must have been unthinkable that this blend between war-gaming, educational role play, and Fantasy would

160 digital material have such an impact on the development of computer games (King and Borland 2003). Since the release of D&D, the Fantasy gaming world has developed from what pioneer researcher Gary Alan Fine in 1983 called a ‘rather small, perhaps trivial, social world’ (Fine 1983, 1), mostly consisting of white, middle-class boys and men, to a ‘rather big, important, social world in which females now also make up a significant part’ (Fine 1983, Yee 2005). Between 1999 and 2008, the number of people playing online role-playing games increased from one to four- teen million. Approximately ten million people play World of Warcraft; which equals the population of . The current Fantasy gaming world not only includes online games, but also tabletop role-playing games, live-action roleplaying, wargaming, board games, and collectible card games. The Dutch Elf Fantasy Fair, the largest Fantasy conven- tion in Europe that attracts around 20,000 visitors each year, shows how Fantasy gaming often blends in with a love for Fantasy books, films, television series, clothing and jewelry, folk music, historical re-enactment, and (neo)pagan spiri- tuality. A three-year study that I initiated of the visitors to the Fair, in which I inquired into their interests ranging from gaming to clothing and from music to spirituality, showed the heterogeneity of the public. Not only in age (ranging from children to 70-year-olds), but also in gender (an average of 60 per cent female and 40 per cent male) and interests: participants create their own mix of Fantasy cul- ture in which games often take up a central role (Copier 2005; Copier and Ram- stedt 2006). In the last three decades, the heterogeneous Fantasy gaming world has grown exponentially; it has also changed dramatically. While it is still mostly boys and men playing war games, card games, and tabletop role-playing games, women and girls are very active in live-action roleplaying and MMORPGs.

In his trilogy The information age: Economy, society and culture (1996, 1997, and 1998), Castells used rich empirical case studies to map how, from the late 1960s on- wards, we are witnessing a shift from hierarchies to networks in all sectors of society. According to Castells, this shift is due to three interdependent processes: the information technology revolution, the economic crisis of both capitalism and statism, and the blooming of cultural social movements, such as , human rights, feminism, and environmentalism. Whereas Castells focused on an analysis of the socio-political forms of social interaction, such as business net- works in Asia and the Mexican Zapatista movement led by Subcomandante Mar- cos, online networks of play are also important global and distributed forms of sociability. Castells’s work is part of a growing body of network theory in which our society, including science itself, is understood as a complex system shaped by flows within and between actor networks that are often powered by information and communication technologies. In order to study the interactions that are going on between the human and nonhuman actors in these networks, I con- ducted an ethnographic study of role play in WoW from the perspective of the challenging the magic circle 161 actor-network theory (ANT), a theory and methodology that is part of the network discourse. ANT, was first developed in Science and Technology Studies (STS) in the mid-1980s (Callon 1986; Law 1987; Latour 1987, 2005). This method not only allows us to research collaborative play, it also uncovers how MMORPG research- ers and their work are tied in with the networks of play and design that they study. When Callon, Law, and Latour originally formulated ANT in 1980s, they argued that to understand the process of knowledge production in science and technol- ogy, we should map the networked interactions between both human and nonhu- man actors. In his latest work, Latour reformulated ANT as a new form of that consists of a ‘tracing of associations’, thus offering insight into com- plexity, instead of mapping a material domain or providing a singular social ex- planation (Latour 2005). In order to understand how actor networks are formed, stay together, or fall apart, Latour proposed ethnographic research of actual pro- cesses. In turn, these experiences should be reassociated and reassembled into a ‘thick description’. In a thick description, behavior is described in its context, in such a way that it becomes meaningful to the reader (Geertz 1973). Latour insists on calling ANT a travel guide instead of a methodology. This way, he argued, we cannot confuse ANT with a frame that is imposed on its object of research. Like a travel guide, ANT offers suggestions for tracing associations and for traveling through webs of interrelations. ‘Tracing associations’ allows us to understand the constant morphing process of the social in and around MMORPGs. Using a slogan from ANT, you have to ‘follow the actors themselves’: ‘it is no longer enough to limit actors to the role of informers offering cases of well-known types. You have to grant them back the ability to make up their own theories of what the social is made of. Your task is no longer to impose some order, to limit the range of acceptable entities, to teach actors what they are, or to add some reflexivity to their blind practice’ (Latour 2005, 12). In what follows I first introduce my ethnographic study of role play in WoW, after which I will discuss the historical and theoretical background of the concept and metaphor of the magic circle. Going back to Homo ludens (1938), the book in which the Dutch historian Johan Huizinga first introduced the term magic circle in relation to games and play, I argue that his work is often misinterpreted by modern game scholars. The network perspective allows us to work from Huizin- ga’s main premise: understanding the play element of culture.

Role play in online role-playing games In order to ‘follow the actors’ I became a WoW player, on 11 February 2005, the day that WoW was released in Europe, along with thousands of others. I had already been playing tabletop and live-action role-playing games for a few years and was an active participant in the Dutch Fantasy game culture as a designer,

162 digital material researcher, and organizer. Ethnography involves studying a natural research set- ting over a substantial period of time, thus collecting rich data in order to develop an empathic understanding of the behaviour and meaning-making of persons in that setting. In traditional ethnography, three levels are distinguished in which the researcher can integrate into the culture: observer, participant-observer, or participant. In an ethnographic study of play in MMORPGs, the researcher does not have this choice, he or she has to become a participant in order to play; thus, there is no observer position possible. The participant position makes the MMORPG researcher into an active actor, both in play and in research networks. As a player-researcher I chose to focus on the role-play (RP) game mode which is remarkably absent from MMORPG research. The name ‘Massively Multiplayer Online Role-Playing Game’ suggests that all its players role play. Paradoxically, World of Warcraft is coded for instrumental play. As the word ‘warcraft’ in the title emphasizes, playing the game is about battling monsters and other players. In order to participate in instrumental play, it is not necessary to perform your ava- tar. The result of this is that most players use their avatar as a pawn. Psychologist Nick Yee even feels that the ‘RP’ in MMORPG is ironic, as ‘most MMORPGs have had to deliberately set aside designated role-playing servers, and these have al- ways been in the minority’ (Yee 2006). In WoW, these role-play servers are tech- nically no different from PvE (Player versus Environment) or PvP (Player versus Player) servers, which means that role play is not written into the code of the game; rather, it consists of a set of meta-game rules. In order to encourage players to enact their characters, the developer, Blizzard Entertainment, added special guidelines, known as ‘role-play policies’: ‘Players who choose to play in an RP realm should abide by the Role-Playing realm policies and remain in-char- acter at all times. Role-Playing realms give players the chance to develop charac- ters with a backstory who do not go blindly from quest to quest, but instead assist or hamper the efforts of others for reasons of their own’ (Realm types, WoW website 2004). Most scholars focus on the ‘instrumental’ play that the PvE and PvP modes offer. The role-play cultures that develop on designated RP servers, complete with their own rules and etiquette, are not a representative sample of online play and culture. However, Taylor suggests, by telling ‘border stories’,in other words, looking at areas of gaming that are normally neglected, we can learn more about both the games themselves and about the broader culture in which they are embedded (Taylor 2006, 10). Let us return to the caravan of the Argent Archives, a role-play guild that Eis- wein had started as an imaginary subdivision of the Ironforge Library. The narra- tive of the game holds minimal information on this library in the city of - forge, which enabled Eiswein to make up his own story, without breaking the rules of Warcraft’s lore as represented throughout the different games that Bliz- zard Entertainment published in this setting.

challenging the magic circle 163 Upon returning with tea and a cheese sandwich, the queue was down to 145. The good thing was that the queue gave me some time to clean off the stacks of research papers and teaching materials from my desk. While eating my sandwich, I turned on MSN and started chatting with Zoe while I simultaneously went through my e-mail. As Freckles was recovering from a previous role-play adventure (in which we were stranded on a deserted island), Zoe would use one of her other characters to travel with the caravan. It was 7:50 pm when I was finally able to log on. As she should, Speckles appeared where I had logged out the last time – in a tavern in the Dwarven district of Stormwind. The top view angle of the camera made my gnomish character look unpleasantly small, as if I was a giant looking down on her. Using my mouse I quickly turned and lowered the camera and as I zoomed in, I smiled at the combination of her funny- looking three red ponytails and the determined expression on the character’s face.

After arriving in Ironforge I spotted Archivar Eiswein standing in front of a table that was positioned underneath a simple tent. In order to have a better look I scrolled the mouse wheel forward to turn the camera into first-person perspective. The older dwarf had a long white beard and was wearing a gray robe combined with a silver-gray tabard that displayed a compass, and green gloves kept his hands warm. Player-characters had lined up to talk to him, and he was using a combination of chat and emotes to hand out assignments and missions. ‘Oh, hello, Miss Snapwiggle,’ Eiswein said. ‘Yes, hullo,’ I replied. ‘Here I am.’ While I waited for my turn to talk to the Archivar, the group of player-characters wanting to join the caravan grew fast, and as a result it became almost impossible to follow all the conversations taking place in the vicinity. I pulled the camera back to third person so I could focus on the chat of the player-characters nearby, which showed up in the text bubbles above their heads. ‘Now, I will need you to take as many photographs of those that are with us here,’ Eiswein told Speckles. ‘Do not fear the price of the film you use. The Archives will pay.’

Eiswein asked Speckles to document the trip in snapshots ‘so that nothing be- comes lost or forgotten’. This not only meant that I would perform the role of photographer but also that I would take screenshots during the event. Later Eis- wein used the screenshots taken by both himself and others to make what he calls a photoreel, a report of the caravan to be posted on the role-play community website ArgentArchives.org. Here, players document their characters, guild and role-play experiences in stories, drawings, and screenshots. If we consider the above auto-ethnographic fragment in terms of the magic circle, is ArgentArc- hives.org part of World of Warcraft?

Challenging the magic circle The magic circle became a popular game studies concept due to the work of game designers and researchers Katie Salen and Eric Zimmerman. In their book on game design fundamentals, Rules of Play (2004), Salen and Zimmerman adopted

164 digital material the term ‘magic circle’ as one of the core concepts to define the game experience. In a chapter that opens with an image of a chalk circle they argue: ‘To play a game means entering into a magic circle, or perhaps creating one as a game begins. (…) The term magic circle is appropriate because there is in fact something genu- inely magical that happens when a game begins (…) Within the magic circle, special meanings accrue and cluster around objects and behaviors. In effect, a new reality is created, defined by the rules of the game and inhabited by its players’ (Salen and Zimmerman 2004, 95-96). Salen and Zimmerman borrowed the term ‘magic circle’ from Huizinga, who in Homo ludens defined play as an activity that ‘proceeds within its own proper boundaries of time and space according to fixed rules and in an orderly manner’ (Huizinga 1938, ed. 1955, 13). Huizinga did not label this bounded activity as taking place within a magic circle, however. He refers to the magic circle, or ‘toovercirkel’ in Dutch, when he compares the playground to similar arenas: ‘the card-table, the magic circle, the temple, the stage, the screen, the tennis court, the court of justice, etc., are all in form and function playgrounds, i.e., forbidden spots, isolated, hedged round, hallowed, within which special rules obtain’ (Hui- zinga 1938, ed. 1955, 10). Salen and Zimmerman seem to have picked the appeal- ing term ‘magic circle’ from Huizinga’s list and matched it with both Huizinga’s and their own definition of games. The term magic circle thus became a powerful concept and metaphor, leading to a perception of games as safe havens of imagi- nation and experimentation that are separated from ‘real’ or ‘ordinary’ life. The game space is understood as a ‘special space’,a‘fun space’, because players enter into it voluntarily and are temporarily freed of work. Even though the metaphor of the magic circle might seem to be especially fitting for research into Fantasy role- playing games, some researchers, including myself, have expressed their concern about the magic circle (Castronova 2005; Consalvo 2005; Copier 2005, 2007; Lammes 2006; Montola 2005; Nieuwdorp 2005; Roderiquez 2006; Taylor 2006; Pargman and Jakobsson 2006).²

In trying to find a way around the ‘magic’ and the ‘strong boundaries’ of the metaphor of the magic circle in order to express how they can both be open and closed, a few game researchers reformulated the magic circle. In discussing per- vasive games, Eva Nieuwdorp (2005) chose to adapt Erving Goffman’s metaphor of the screen: ‘the screen not only selects but also transforms what is passed through it’ (Goffman 1961, 33). In his economic analysis of MMORPGs, Edward Castronova opted for the term ‘porous membrane’: ‘people are crossing it all the time in both directions, carrying their behavioral assumptions and attitudes with them. As a result, the valuation of things in cyberspace becomes enmeshed in the valuation of things outside cyberspace’ (Castronova 2005, 150). In her ethnogra- phy of Everquest, Taylor defined MMORPG play as ‘play between worlds’: ‘Playing EQ is about playing between worlds – playing back, and forth, across the bound- challenging the magic circle 165 aries of the game and the game world, and the “real” or nonliteral game space’ (Taylor 2006, 17). Building on these modifications of the magic circle, Daniel Pargman and Peter Jakobsson proposed a ‘weak-boundary hypothesis’ (Pargman and Jakobsson 2006). In order to adopt a more flexible idea of the boundaries of play, they (re)introduced Erving Goffman’s concept of ‘frames’ and Fine’s idea of ‘frames-within-frames’, which suggests that inside the primary framework (which is the basis for everything we do), we establish roles and subframes that redefine the situation. Pargman and Jakobsson argued that gaming creates a spe- cific set of roles or subframes. Thus, they replaced the magic circle with the por- ous or weak boundaries of the game framework, which holds the conventions of the game. In line with the work of Goffman and Fine, they state that, ‘There is nothing magical about switching between roles. It is something we do all the time and can literally be done at the blink of an eye’ (Pargman and Jakobsson 2006). Even though these reconfigurations of the magic circle assist in uncovering the ambiguous qualities of games and game play, I still find the concept and meta- phor of the magic circle problematic in two ways. Conceptually, the magic circle refers to a pre-existing artificiality of the game space, which creates a dichotomy between the real and the imaginary that hides the fact that digital play is a materi- al practice which is deeply anchored in everyday life. The metaphor of the magic circle makes the boundary between ‘game’ and ‘non-game’ even stronger because it represents the game space as an isolated magical wonderland which seems to be almost impossible to grasp rationally. In order to discuss the relation between fantasy and reality, scholars have opted for a counter-rhetoric that includes break- ing or blurring the boundaries between the inside and outside of a game. MMORPG researchers have, for instance, argued that the magic circle of MMORPGs becomes porous when we consider the sale of virtual items and gold on eBay (Castronova 2005; Taylor 2006). In order to understand this paradox of the magic circle, in which games can be both open and closed, we have to engage more critically with Salen and Zimmerman’s Rules of play and Huizinga’s Homo ludens.

The play element of culture Huizinga wrote his definition of play in relation to his overarching argument that culture is sub specie ludi: civilization arises and unfolds in and as play. His main goal was not to analyze the play element in culture, but to understand the play element of culture; how culture itself is formed through the process of play. Therefore, Huizinga argued that even though ‘play is distinct from “ordinary” life both as to locality and duration’, at the same time, it is an important part of daily life: ‘play presents itself to us in the first instance: as an intermezzo, an interlude in our daily lives. As a regularly recurring relaxation, however, it becomes the ac-

166 digital material companiment, the complement, in fact an integral part of life in general’ (Huizin- ga 1938, ed. 1955, 9). In his analysis of Homo ludens, Hector Rodriquez argues that Huizinga underscores that the concept of play often cannot be circumscribed within precise conceptual boundaries. ‘His entire study can be seen as an effort to speak as precisely as possible about categories and distinctions that cannot be neatly demarcated’ (Roderiquez 2006). That many game scholars focus on Hui- zinga’s bounded definition of play instead of his more ambiguous cultural inter- pretation of play might also be due to the fact that against Huizinga’s will, the English subtitle of his book became ‘A study of the play element in culture’ in- stead of ‘of culture’, thus hiding the nature of his overarching argument. A closer look at Salen and Zimmerman’s work reveals that they also deal with this paradox of play. Building on Huizinga’s idea that games are ‘temporary worlds within the ordinary world’, Salen and Zimmerman argued that games can be open or closed systems depending on the perspective that we choose. They distinguished between three primary perspectives: rules (formal perspective), play (experiential perspective), and culture (cultural perspective). Salen and Zim- merman claimed that the formal systems of games are closed, whereas if we con- sider games as play, the magic circle can be either open or closed and considered as culture; games are extremely open systems. Salen and Zimmerman even ar- gued that the study of game phenomena that cross the borders of the magic circle (such as computer-mediated and analogue role-playing games, player-generated mods [modifications] and hacks, level editors and tools designed for players, games created as open-source systems, games that are played within and across multiple platforms, and self-organizing social networks) are essential for the fu- ture of innovative game development. As Huizinga’s overarching argument is for- mulated from a cultural perspective, Salen and Zimmerman – based on their cate- gorization of rules, play and culture – would probably argue that he considers games to be open systems. Also taking into account the strong metaphor, I pro- pose to withdraw from the magic circle (Copier 2005, 2007). I suggest we shift our focus from a study of games in culture to a study of game-play as one of the play elements and producers of culture. Exploring ethical choices in relation to games and players, Mia Consalvo ar- gues that we should build a theoretical framework that transcends ‘the place apart’ that games are often constructed as: ‘For many players, playing games is, in some measure, a playing with rules and their boundaries’ (Consalvo 2005, 10). Those rules and boundaries construct a specific game context. In turn, this con- text only exists in relation to other contexts, rules and boundaries. Play is thus always a negotiation of rules and boundaries both in the specific context itself but also in relation to other rules and boundaries. Defining pervasive gaming, Montola states that the genre explores the magic circle in spatial, temporal and social dimensions. He adds that the spatial, temporal and social dimensions can provide new ways of analyzing ‘traditional’ games as well, as even non-pervasive challenging the magic circle 167 games do not exist in isolation (Montola 2005, 3). Instead of looking for the boundaries of the metaphorical magic circle, we can use a network perspective to map how every game and game experience is negotiated spatially, temporally and socially. Considering the above auto-ethnographic fragment in terms of the magic circle, ArgentArchives.org would not be part of the game experience as it has a different online place and rules. However, from the network perspective, I would analyze that WoW creates a specific context and rule set which is for instance negotiated spatially (by a website outside of the game), temporally (by players who are for instance adding information to the website while at work) and so- cially (by players who stop playing WoW, but are still roleplaying through their profiles on ArgentArchives.org).

From the network perspective, role play is especially interesting as it underlines in many ways how game play can be negotiated. I consider the role-play game mode to be a highly ‘contested’ form of play, even on RP servers. Technically, role play is ‘optional’, the effect of this is that there is a constant negotiation process going on between players regarding the type of game-play and behavior that is accept- able. Besides this, role play in itself is a play mode which revolves around negotia- tion. This contested relationship between instrumental game play and role play in WoW can be traced back throughout the code and culture to previous digital and analogue Fantasy role-playing games (Copier 2007). Role play is a collaborative experience; by playing the role of their characters, players are creating a ‘shared fantasy’ (Fine 1983) or ‘shared imagined space’ (Edwards 2004). For example, a player who decides to roleplay a gnomish innkeeper needs other players who are willing to enact their characters to be his personnel or guests in his tavern. Players who theorize tabletop role play called this the ‘lumpley princi- ple’, after the nickname of the independent game designer, Vincent Baker. Baker stated that the essence of role play is negotiating which situations or events can be part of the shared fantasy (Edwards 2004). This negotiation process, and its constantly morphing outcome, is shaped by a wide range of explicit and implicit factors such as the 3D graphical design, rules of the game, Warcraft lore, charac- ter backgrounds, character performance, player motivations, and the interperso- nal relationships between both the characters and the players. Our gnomish inn- keeper has to deal with two types of negotiations: players who come in with no intention of pretending that their character is a guest in a tavern, and players who act as if they are in a tavern and, for example, may roleplay their character as a friendly customer. Through negotiation, role players create a shared fantasy in which they not only form their characters, but through which they also concep- tually blend conventions, identities, and interpersonal relationships. As there are thousands of player-characters on one RP server, there is not just one shared fantasy; instead, there are multiple fantasies that are continually negotiated as well. Using ANT we can study the functioning of these negotiation processes as

168 digital material well as the in-character and out-of-character roles, conventions, identities, and interpersonal relationships that self-proclaimed role-players negotiate in and through the systems of the commercially distributed game WoW. It is precisely the ‘contested’ and ‘negotiated’ characteristics that make role play very useful in uncovering the functioning of the systems that MMORPGs are and the cultures in which they are embedded. A shift from games to the play element of culture, in other words to game play from a cultural perspective, is also what differentiates the work of Fine from most recent scholarship on digital games. By building on the work of Goffman and Fine, Pargman and Jakobsson’s ‘weak-boundary hypothesis’ also focuses on play instead of games, which separates their alternative from, for instance, the ‘porous membrane’ (Castronova 2005). A focus on play as social interaction within a spe- cific context opens up possibilities to discuss the ambiguity and variability of game play, for instance with regard to the relation between the real and the ima- ginary, not in terms of a ‘closed’ and ‘magical’ circle but as constructs that are under constant negotiation. Rules are also one part of these constructs that can be negotiated and (re)constructed. The role-play experience is shaped by (re)con- structions and negotiations between various real and imaginary frames, between what I call the ‘code and culture’ of the game.

Conclusions To recapitulate, the concept of the magic circle refers to a pre-existing artificiality of the game space that, combined with the strong metaphor, creates a dichotomy between the real and the imaginary which hides the ambiguity, variability, and complexity of actual games and play. I propose to withdraw from the magic circle and suggest we shift our focus from a study of games in culture to a study of game-play as one of the play elements and producers of culture. A network per- spective allows us to understand how every game and game experience is nego- tiated spatially, temporally and socially. As networks of human and nonhuman actors, online role-playing games are simultaneously tied in with other networks of production, power, and experience. Together, these networks make up what Castells called the network society. From the network perspective, role play is especially interesting. Role play is a contested and negotiated style of play, which makes it useful to uncover the rules, play, and culture that are constructed through online role-playing games. Additionally, be- cause role-players consciously engage in the process of constructing and nego- tiating roles and frames, it becomes very visible how, through MMORPG play, pre-existing roles and frames are negotiated and (re)constructed, while at the same time new roles and frames are being constructed. These roles and frames can simultaneously be related to what we consider to be real and imaginary, game and non-game, online and offline. For various situations we construct different challenging the magic circle 169 roles and cognitive frames, but these identities and frames exist simultaneously, they are porous and never fixed. These roles and frames can never be fixed be- cause they are continually being negotiated and (re)constructed, as both Huizinga and Goffman suggested, often through play-like processes. Games are merely one of the settings in which these processes take place.

Notes 1. ‘Fantasy’ as a genre of imaginative fiction is capitalized in order to differentiate from fantasy in general, meaning the creation of the imaginative. 2. For a critical discussion of the issue of the magic circle in relation to pervasive games, see the chapter by Eva Nieuwdorp in this book.

References Callon, Michel, John Law, and Arie Rip. 1986. Mapping the dynamics of science and technology: Sociology of science in the real world. Houndmills: Macmillan. Castells, Manuel. 1998, 2000. End of millennium. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. —. 1997, 2000. The power of identity. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. —. 1996, 2000. The rise of the network society. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. Castronova, Edward. 2005. Synthetic worlds: The business and culture of online games. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Consalvo, Mia. 2005. Rule sets, cheating, and magic circles: Studying games and ethics. International review of information ethics 4. http://www.i-r-i-.net/inhalt/004/Consalvo.pdf. Copier, Marinka. 2005. Connecting worlds: Fantasy role-playing games, ritual acts and the magic circle. Paper presented at Changing Views: Worlds in Play – Digital Games Research Conference. Vancouver, Canada. —. 2007. Beyond the magic circle: A network perspective on role-play in online games. PhD thesis, Utrecht University. Copier, Marinka, and Martin Ramstedt. 2006. Converging plays of identity. Paper pre- sented at Strange convergences: Performance and performativity in Fantasy game cultures, the Gothic milieu, and pagan spirituality. Amsterdam, the Netherlands. Edwards, Ron. 2004. The provisional glossary. The Forge. http://www.indie-rpgs.com/_arti- cles/glossary.html. Fine, Gary Alan. 1983. Shared fantasy: Role-playing games as social worlds. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Geertz, C. 1973. Thick description: Toward an interpretive theory of culture. The Interpreta- tion of Cultures, 3-30. Goffman, Erving. 1961. Encounters: Two studies in the sociology of interaction. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill. Huizinga, Johan. 1938. Homo ludens: Proeve eener bepaling van het spel-element der cultuur. Haar- lem: Tjeenk Willink. —. 1955. Homo ludens: A study of the play-element in culture. Boston: Beacon Press. King, Brad, and John Borland. 2003. Dungeons and dreamers: The rise of computer game culture from geek to chic. New York: McGraw-Hill.

170 digital material Lammes, Sybille. 2006. Spatial regimes of the digital payground: Cultural functions of spa- tial identification in post-colonial computergames. In Conference proceedings Mediaterr@ – Gaming realities: A challenge for digital culture, ed. Manthos Santorineos, 236-43. Athens, Greece: Fournos Centre for Digital Culture. Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. —. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford: Oxford Univer- sity Press. Law, John. 1987. Technology and heterogeneous engineering: The case of Portuguese ex- pansion. In The social construction of technological systems: New directions in the sociology and , eds. W. E. Bijker, T. P. Hughes and T. J. Pinch. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Montola, Markus. 2005. Exploring the edge of the magic circle: Defining pervasive games. Paper presented at Digital experience: Design, aestethics, practice conference. Copenhagen, Den- mark. Nieuwdorp, Eva. 2005. The pervasive interface: Tracing the magic circle. Paper presented at Changing views: Worlds in play – Digital Games Research conference, Vancouver, Canada. Pargman, Daniel, and Peter Jakobsson. 2006. The magic is gone: A critical examination of the gaming situation. In Conference proceedings Mediaterr@ – Gaming realities: A challenge for digital culture, ed. Manthos Santorineos, 15-22. Athens, Greece: Fournos Centre for Digi- tal Culture. Roderiquez, Hector. 2006. The playful and the serious: An approximation to Huizinga’s Homo Ludens. Gamestudies 6 (1). http://gamestudies.org/0601/articles/rodriges. Salen, Katie, and Eric Zimmerman. 2004. Rules of play: Game design fundamentals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Taylor, T. L. 2006. Play between worlds: Exploring online game culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Yee, Nick. 2005. The real life demographics of World of Warcraft. The Daedalus Project. http://www.nickyee.com/daedalus/archives/001364.php. —. 2006. The role-playing series. The Daedalus Project. http://www.nickyee.com/daedalus/ archives/001524.php.

challenging the magic circle 171

Renaissance now!

The gamers’ perspective

Douglas Rushkoff

The frightening news is that we are living in a story. The reassuring part is that it is a story we are writing ourselves. Alas, though, most of us do not even know it – or are afraid to accept it. Never before did we have so much access to the tools of storytelling – yet few of us are willing to participate in their creation.¹ Gamers might be today’s most likely candidates to helm what I hope will be a renaissance in our relationship to stories as well as the reality they mean to describe and influence. We are living in a world of stories. We cannot help but use narratives to under- stand the events that occur around us. The unpredictability of nature, emotions, social interactions and power relationships led human beings, from prehistoric times, to develop narratives that described the patterns underlying the movements of these forces. Although we like to believe that primitive people actually believed the myths they created about everything from the weather to the afterlife, a grow- ing camp of religious historians are coming to the conclusion that early religions were understood much more metaphorically than we understand religion today. They did not believe that the wind or rain were gods; they invented characters whose personalities reflected the properties of these elements. The characters and their stories served more as ways of remembering that it would be cold for four months before spring returns than genuinely accepted explanations. The people were quite self-consciously and actively anthropomorphizing the forces of nature. As different people and groups competed for authority, they used their narra- tives quite differently. They used their stories to gain advantage. Stories were no longer being used simply to predict the patterns of nature but to describe and influence the course of politics, economics, and power. In such a world, stories compete solely on the basis of their ability to win believers, to be understood as real. When the Pharaoh or King is treated as if he were a god, it means his sub- jects are still actively participating in the sham. He still needs to prove his po- tency, in real ways, at regular intervals. But if the ruler can somehow get his

173 followers to accept the story of his divine authority as historical fact, then he need prove nothing. The story itself serves as a substitute for reality. Since biblical times, we have been living in a world where the stories we use to describe and predict our reality have been presented as truth and mistaken for fact. These narratives, and their tellers, compete for believers in two ways: through the content of the stories, and through the medium or tools through which the stories are told. The content of a story might be considered the ‘what’, while the technology through which the story is transmitted can be considered the ‘how’. A story can vie for believers in both ways – through the narrative itself, or by changing the level of the playing field on which it is competing. Exclusive access to the ‘how’ of storytelling lets a storyteller monopolize the ‘what’ . In ancient times, people were captivated by the epic storyteller as much for his ability to remember thousands of lines of text as for the actual content of the Iliad or Odyssey. Likewise, a television program or commercial holds us in its spell as much through the magic of broadcasting technology as its teleplay. Who- ever has power to get inside that magic box has the power to write the story we end up believing. After all, we do not call the stuff on television ‘programming’ for nothing. The people making television are not programming our TV sets or their evening sche- dules; they are programming us. We use the dial to select which program we are going to receive, and then we submit to it. This is not so dangerous in itself, but the less control we have over exactly what is fed to us through the tube, the more vulnerable we are to the whims of our programmers. For most of us, what goes on in the television set is magic. Before the age of video recorders and camcorders, it was even more so. A television program is a magic act. Whoever has gotten his image in that box must be special. Back in the 1960s, Walter Cronkite used to end his newscast with the assertion, ‘and that’s the way it is.’ It was his ability to appear in the magic box that gave him the tremendous authority necessary to lay claim to the absolute truth. I have always recoiled when this rhetorical advantage is exploited by those who have the power to monopolize a medium. Back in college, I remember being incensed by a scene in the third Star Wars movie, Return of the Jedi. Luke and Han Solo have landed on an alien moon and are taken prisoner by a tribe of little furry creatures called Ewoks. In an effort to win their liberation, Luke’s two robots tell the Ewoks the story of their heroes’ struggle against the dark forces of the Em- pire. C3PO, the golden android, relates the tale, while little R2D2 projects holo- graphic images of battling spaceships. The Ewoks are dazzled by R2’s special effects and engrossed in C3PO’s tale. The ‘how’ and the ‘what’. They are so moved by the story that they not only release their prisoners but fight a violent war on their behalf! I kept wondering, what if Darth Vader had gotten down to the alien moon first and told his side of the story complete with his own special effects?

174 digital material Similarly, television programming, like the many one-way media before it, communicates through stories, and it influences us through its seemingly magi- cal capabilities. The programmer creates a character we like – with whom we can identify. As a series of plot developments bring that character into some kind of danger, we follow him, and a sense of tension rises within us. This is what Aristotle, in his role as one of the first theater analysts, called the rising arc of dramatic action. The storyteller brings the character and the audi- ence into as much danger as we can tolerate before inventing his solution – the rescue – allowing us all to let out a big sigh of relief. Back in Aristotle’s day, this solution was called Deus ex machina (God from the machine), and one of the Greek gods would descend on a mechanism from the rafters and save the day. In an Arnold Schwarzenegger movie, that miraculous solution might take the form of a new, super-powered laser gun. In a commercial, well, it is the product being ad- vertised. In any case, if he has got a captive audience, the storyteller can pick whichever solution he wants, and if we have been following the story into increas- ing anxiety, we will take it. Television commercials honed this storytelling technique into the perfect 30- second package. A man is at work. His wife calls to tell him she has crashed the car. The boss comes in to tell him he just lost a big account. His bank statement shows he is in the red. His secretary quits. Now his head hurts. We have followed the poor guy all this way, and we feel his pain. What can he do? He opens the top desk drawer and finds his bottle of Brand A Pain Reliever! He swallows the pills as an awe-inspiring high-tech animation demonstrates to us the way the pill passes through his body, relieving his pain. In a passive and mysterious medium, when we are brought into a state of vicar- ious tension, the storyteller can make us swallow any pill he chooses. Only by accepting his solution can we be freed from our despair. Interactive media changed this equation. Imagine if your grandfather were watching that aspirin commercial back in 1955 on his old console television. Even if he suspected that he was watching a commercial designed to put him into a state of anxiety, in order to change the channel and remove himself from the externally imposed tension, he would have to move the popcorn off his lap, pull up the lever on his recliner, walk up to the television set, and manually turn the dial. That is a somewhat rebellious action for a bleary-eyed television viewer. To sit through the rest of the commercial, however harrowing, might cost him only a tiny quantity of human energy until the pills come out of the drawer. The brain, being lazy, chooses the path of least resistance, and grandpa sits through the whole commercial. Flash forward to 1990. A kid with a remote control in his hand makes the same mental calculation: an ounce of stress, or an infinitesimally small quantity of hu- man effort to move his finger an eighth of an inch and he is free! The remote control gives viewers the power to remove themselves from the storyteller’s spell, renaissance now! 175 with almost no effort. Watch a kid – or yourself – the next time he channel surfs from program to program. He is not changing the channel because he’s bored. He surfs away when he senses that he is being put into an imposed state of ten- sion. The remote control breaks down the ‘what’. It allows a viewer to deconstruct the content of television media and avoid falling under the programmer’s spell. If he does get back around the dial to watch the end of a program, he no longer has the same captivated orientation. Kids with remotes are not watching television – they are watching the television, playing television. Putting it through its paces. Just as the remote control allowed a generation to deconstruct the content of television, the videogame joystick demystified its technology. Remember back to the first time you ever saw a videogame. It was probably Pong, that primitive black and white depiction of a ping pong table, with a square on either side of the screen representing the paddle, and a tiny white dot representing the ball. Now, remember the exhilaration you felt at playing that game for the very first time. Was it because you had always wanted an effective simulation of ping pong? Did you celebrate because you would be able to practise without purchasing an entire table and installing it in the basement? Of course not. You were celebrating the simple ability to be able to move the pixels on the screen for the first time. It was a moment of revolution! The screen was no longer the exclusive turf of the televi- sion broadcasters. Thanks to the joystick, as well as the subsequent introduction of the VCR and camcorder, we were empowered to move the pixels ourselves. The TV was no longer magical. Its functioning had become transparent. Finally, the computer mouse and keyboard transformed a receive-only monitor into a portal. Packaged programming was no longer any more valuable – or valid – than the words we could type ourselves. The addition of a modem turned the computer into a broadcast facility. We were no longer dependent on the content of Rupert Murdoch or CBS but could create and disseminate our own. The Inter- net revolution was a ‘do-it-yourself’ or DIY revolution. The people were now the content. New forms of community were being formed. Of course this represented a tremendous threat to business as usual. Studies in the mid-1990s showed that families with Internet-capable computers were watch- ing an average of nine hours less television per week. What is worse, Internet enthusiasts were sharing information, ideas, and even whole computer programs, for free! Software known as ‘’ and ‘’ gave rise to a gift economy based on community and mutual self-interest. People were turning to alternative news and entertainment sources for which they did not have to pay – and, worse, they were watching fewer commercials. Something had to be done. And it was. Through a series of both deliberate and utterly systemic responses to the threat of interactivity, the mainstream media sought to reverse the effects of the remote, the joystick, and the mouse. Borrowing a term from 1970s social science, media business advocates declared that we were now living in an ‘attention economy’.

176 digital material True enough, the media space might be infinite, but there are only so many hours in a day during which potential audience members might be viewing a program. These units of human time became known as ‘eyeball-hours’, and pains were taken to create TV shows and web sites ‘sticky’ enough to engage those eyeballs long enough to show them an advertisement. Perhaps coincidentally, the growth of the attention economy was accompanied by an increase of concern over the ‘attention spans’ of young people. Channel surfing and similar behavior became equated with a very real but differently diagnosed childhood illness called Atten- tion Deficit Disorder. Children who refused to pay attention were much too quickly drugged, before the real reasons for their adaptation to the onslaught of commercial messages were even considered. The demystification of media enabled by the joystick and other tools was quickly reversed through the development of increasingly opaque computer inter- faces. Whereas an early DOS computer user tended to understand a lot about how his computer stored information and launched programs, later operating systems such as Windows 95 put more barriers in place. Although these operating sys- tems make computers easier to use in certain ways, they prevent users from gain- ing access or command over its more intricate processes. Now, to install a new program, users must consult ‘the wizard’. What better metaphor do we need for the remystification of the computer? As a result, ‘computer literacy’ no longer means being able to program a computer, but merely knowing how to use Micro- soft Office. Finally, the DIY ethic of the Internet community was replaced by the new value of commerce. The communications age was rebranded as an ‘information age’ even though the Internet had never really been about downloading files or data but, instead, about communicating with other people. The difference was that information, or ‘content’, could be bought and sold, unlike real human interac- tion. It is a commodity. When selling information online did not work, business people turned to selling real products online. Thus, the e-commerce boom was ignited. Soon the Internet became the World Wide Web, whose opaque and im- age-heavy interfaces made it increasingly one-way and read-only – more condu- cive to commerce than communication. Although very few e-commerce companies actually made any money selling goods, the idea that they could was all that mattered. News stories about online communities were soon overshadowed by those about daring young entrepre- neurs launching multi-million-dollar IPOs (initial public offering of shares). In- ternet journalism moved from the culture section to the business pages as the dot. com pyramid scheme became the dominant new media story. And so a medium born out of the ability to break through packaged stories was now being used to promote a new, equally dangerous one: the great pyramid. A smart kid writes a business plan. He finds a few ‘angel investors’ to back him up long enough for him to land some first-level investors. Below them on the pyra- renaissance now! 177 mid are several more rounds of investors until the investment bank gets involved. Another few levels of investors buy in until the decision is made to ‘go public’. This means that poor suckers like you and I can invest, too, by purchasing a new- ly issued stock on the NASDAQ exchange. Of course, by this point, the angels and other early investors are executing what is known as their ‘exit strategy’. It used to be known as a carpet bag. In any case, they are gone, and we are left holding the soon-to-be-worthless shares. Tragically, but perhaps luckily, the dot.com bubble burst, along with the story being used to keep it inflated. The entire cycle – the birth of a new medium, the battle to control it, and the downfall of the first victorious camp – taught us a lot about the relationship of stories to the technologies through which they are dis- seminated. And the whole ordeal may have given us another opportunity for re- naissance.

Renaissance now? Many considered the birth of the Internet era a revolution. My best friends – par- ticularly those in the counterculture – saw in the Internet an opportunity to topple the storytellers who had dominated our politics, economics, society, and religion, in short, our very reality, and to replace their stories with ones of our own. It was a beautiful and exciting sentiment, but one as based in a particular narrative as any other. simply replace one story with another. The capitalist nar- rative is replaced by the communist; the religious fundamentalist’s by the gnos- tic’s. The means may be different, but the rewards are the same, as is the exclu- sivity of their distribution. That is why they are called revolutions; we are just going in a circle. I prefer to think of the proliferation of interactive media as an opportunity for renaissance: a moment when we have the opportunity to step entirely out of the story. Renaissances are historical instances of widespread recontextualization. People in a variety of different arts, philosophies, and sciences have the ability to reframe their reality.² Quite literally, renaissance means ‘rebirth’. It is the rebirth of old ideas in a new context. A renaissance is a dimensional leap, when our perspective shifts so dramatically that our understanding of the oldest, most fun- damental elements of existence changes. The stories we have been using no long- er work. Take a look back at what we think of as the original Renaissance – the one we were taught in school. What were the main leaps in perspective? Well, most ob- viously, perspective painting itself. Artists developed the technique of the ‘vanish- ing point’ and with it the ability to paint three-dimensional representations on two-dimensional surfaces. The character of this innovation is subtle, but distinct. It is not a technique for working in three dimensions; it is not that artists moved

178 digital material from working on canvas to working with clay. Rather, perspective painting allows an artist to relate between dimensions. Likewise, calculus – another key Renaissance invention – is a mathematical system that allows us to derive one dimension from another. It is a way of de- scribing curves with the language of lines, and spheres with the language of curves. The leap from arithmetic to calculus was not just a leap in our ability to work with higher-dimensional objects, but a leap in our ability to relate the ob- jects of one dimension to the objects of another. It was a shift in perspective that allowed us to orient ourselves to mathematical objects from beyond the context of their own dimensionality. The other main features of the Renaissance permitted similar shifts in perspec- tive. Circumnavigation of the globe changed our relationship to the planet we live on and the maps we used to describe it.³ The maps still worked, of course – only they described a globe instead of a plane. Anyone hoping to navigate a course had to be able to relate a two-dimensional map to the new reality of a three-dimen- sional planet. Similarly, the invention of moveable type and the printing press changed the relationship of author and audience to text. The creation of a manu- script was no longer a one-pointed affair. Well, the creation of the first manu- script still was – but now it could be replicated and distributed to everyone. It was still one story, but now it was subject to a multiplicity of individual perspectives. This lattermost innovation alone changed the landscape of religion in the Wes- tern world. Individual interpretation of the Bible led to the collapse of church authority and the unilateral nature of its decrees. Everyone demanded his or her own relationship to the story. In all these cases, people experienced a very particular shift in their relationship to and understanding of dimensions. Understood this way, a renaissance is a mo- ment of reframing. We step out of the frame as it is currently defined, and see the whole picture in a new context. We can then play by new rules. It is akin to the experience of a gamer. At first, a gamer will play a video or computer game by the rules. He will read the manual, if necessary, then move through the various levels of the game. Mastery of the game, at this stage, means getting to the end – making it to the last level, surviving, becoming the most powerful character or, in the case of a simulation game, designing and maintain- ing a thriving family, city, or civilization. And, for many gamers, this is as far as it goes. Some gamers, though – usually after they have mastered this level of play – will venture out onto the Internet in search of other fans or user groups. There, they will gather the ‘cheat codes’ that can be used to acquire special abilities within the game, such as invisibility or an infinite supply of ammunition. When the gamer returns to the game with his new secret codes, is he still playing the game, or is he cheating? From a renaissance perspective, he is still playing the game – albeit, a different one. His playing field has grown from the CD on which the game was renaissance now! 179 shipped, to the entire universe of computers where these secret codes and abil- ities can be discussed and shared.4 He is no longer playing the game, but a meta- game; the inner game world is still fun, but it is distanced by the gamer’s new perspective – much in the way we are distanced from the play-within-a-play in one of Shakespeare’s comedies or dramas. And the meta-theatrical convention gives us a new perspective on the greater story as well. It is as if we are looking at a series of proscenium arches and being invited, as an audience, to consider whether we are within a proscenium arch ourselves. Gaming – as a metaphor but also as a lived experience – invites a renaissance perspective on the world in which we live. Perhaps gamers and game culture have been as responsible as anyone for the rise in expressly self-similar forms of televi- sion, such as Beavis and Butthead, The Simpsons, and South Park. The joy of such programs is not the relief of reaching the climax of the linear narrative, but rather the momentary thrill of making connections. The satisfaction is recognizing which bits of media are being satirized at any given moment. It is an entirely new perspective on television – where programs exist more in the form of Talmudic commentary – perspectives on perspectives on perspectives. We watch screens within screens – constantly reminded, almost as in a Brecht play – of the artifice of storytelling. The great Renaissance was a simple leap in perspective. Instead of seeing everything in one dimension, we came to realize there was more than one dimen- sion in which things were occurring. Even the Elizabethan world picture, with its concentric rings of authority – God, king, man, animals – reflects this newfound way of contending with the simultaneity of action in many dimensions at once. A gamer stepping out onto the Internet to find a cheat code certainly reaches this renaissance level of awareness and skill. But what of the gamer who then learns to program new games for himself? He, I would argue, has stepped out of yet another frame into our current renaissance. He has deconstructed the content of the game, demystified the technology of its interface, and now feels ready to open the codes and turn the game into a do-it- yourself activity. This is precisely the character and quality of the dimensional leap associated with today’s renaissance, as well. The evidence of today’s renaissance is at least as profound as that of the one that went before. The 16th century saw the successful circumnavigation of the globe via the seas. The 20th century saw the successful circumnavigation of the globe from space. The first pictures of earth from space changed our perspective on this sphere, forever. In the same century, our dominance over the planet was confirmed not just through our ability to travel around it, but to destroy it. The atomic bomb (itself the result of a rude dimensional interchange between submo- lecular particles) gave us the ability to destroy the globe. Now, instead of merely being able to circumnavigate ‘God’s’ creation, we could actively destroy it. This is a new perspective.

180 digital material We also have our equivalent of perspective painting, in the invention of the holograph. The holograph allows us to represent not just three, but four dimen- sions on a two-dimensional plate. When the viewer walks past a holograph, she can observe the three-dimensional object over the course of time. A bird can flap its wings in a single picture. But, more importantly for our renaissance’s pur- poses, the holographic plate itself embodies a new renaissance principle. When the plate is smashed into hundreds of pieces, we do not find that one piece con- tains the bird’s wing, and another piece the bird’s beak. No, each piece of the plate contains a faint image of the entire subject, albeit a faint one. When the pieces are put together, the image achieves greater resolution. But each piece contains a representation of the totality – a leap in dimensional understanding that is now informing disciplines as diverse as brain anatomy and computer pro- gramming. Our analogue to calculus is the development of systems theory, chaos math, and the much-celebrated fractal. Confronting nonlinear equations on their own terms for the first time, mathematicians armed with computers are coming to new understandings of the way numbers can represent the complex relationships between dimensions. Accepting that the surfaces in our world, from coastlines to clouds, exhibit the properties of both two- and three-dimensional objects (just what is the surface area of a cloud?), they came up with ways of working with and representing objects with fractional dimensionality. Using fractals and their equa- tions, we can now represent and work with objects from the natural world that defied Cartesian analysis. We have also become able to develop mathematical models that reflect many more properties of nature’s own systems – such as self- similarity and remote high leverage points. Again, we find this renaissance char- acterized by the ability of an individual to reflect, or even affect, the grand narra- tive. To write the game. Finally, our renaissance’s answer to the printing press is the computer and its ability to network. Just as the printing press gave everyone access to readership, the computer and Internet give everyone access to authorship. The first Renais- sance took us from the position of passive recipient to active interpreter. Our current renaissance brings us from a position of active interpretation to one of authorship. We are the creators. As game programmers instead of game players, we begin to become aware of just how much of our reality is, indeed, open source – up for discussion. So much of what seemed like impenetrable hardware is actually software, and ripe for re- programming. The stories we use to understand the world seem less like explana- tions and more like collaborations. They are rule sets – and only as good as their ability to explain the patterns of history or predict those of the future. Consider the experience of a cartographer attempting to hold a conversation with a surfer. They both can claim intimate knowledge of the ocean, but from vastly different perspectives. While the mapmaker understands the sea as a series renaissance now! 181 of longitude and latitude lines, the surfer sees only a motion of waves that are not even depicted on the cartographer’s map. If the cartographer were to call out from the beach to the surfer and ask him whether he is above or below the forty- third parallel, the surfer would be unable to respond. The mapmaker would have no choice but to conclude that the surfer was hopelessly lost. If any of us were asked to choose which one we would rather rely on to get us back to shore, most of us would pick the surfer. He experiences the water as a system of moving waves and stands a much better chance of navigating a safe course through them. Each surfer at each location and each moment of the day experiences an entirely different ocean. The cartographer experiences the same map, no matter what. He has a more permanent model, but his liability is his propensity to mis- take his map for the actual territory. The difference between the cartographer and the surfer’s experience of the ocean is akin to pre- and post-renaissance relationships to story. The first relies on the most linear and static interpretations of the story in order to create a static and authoritative template through which to glean its meaning. The latter relies on the living, moment-to-moment perceptions of its many active interpreters to develop a way of relating to its many changing patterns. Ultimately, in a cognitive process not unlike that employed by a chaos mathematician, the surfer learns to recognize the order underlying what at first appears to be random turbulence. Likewise, the surfer understands each moment and event in his world – like a toss of the I-Ching coins were once understood – as a possible reflection on any other in the entire system. The renaissance experience of moving from game to meta-game allows every- thing old to look new again. We are liberated from the maps we have been using to navigate our world, and free to create new ones based on our own observa- tions. This invariably leads to a whole new era of competition. Renaissance may be a rebirth of old ideas in a new context, but which ideas get to be reborn? The first to recognize the new renaissance will compete to have their ideologies be the ones that are ‘rebirthed’ in this new context. This is why, with the emer- gence of the Internet, we saw the attempted rebirth (and occasional stillbirth) of everything from paganism to libertarianism, and communism to psychedelia. Pre- dictably, the financial markets and consumer capitalism – the dominant narra- tives of our era – were the first to successfully commandeer the renaissance. But they squandered their story on a pyramid scheme – indeed, the accelerating force of computers and networks tends to force any story to its logical conclusion – and now the interactive renaissance is once again up for grabs. Were I in the futurism business, I’d predict that gamers will be the next to steer the direction of our renaissance, and that they may have entirely better results. For, unlike businessmen or even politicians, gamers know that the reality they are engineering is not real. This is why cheating is not really cheating – but merely playing from a new perspective. It is all play. Where gamers may have

182 digital material formerly been competing from within the game, now they meet and compete on an entirely new level – and, in comparison, they fight as gods. This is a powerful perspective from which to operate, and one that may grow in popularity as games become an even more central entertainment in mass culture. Without even a convincing business-to-business strategy on which to hang their market hopes, increasing numbers of hi-tech speculators are coming to the irrefutable conclusion that they just spent billions of their own and other people’s money on a communications infrastructure that amounts, more than anything else, to a network gaming platform. No, the Internet is not a content delivery system. It is not a way to download movies or even songs. It is a way of connecting gaming consoles. The only ques- tions left are whether processing will be done on centralized servers or within the consoles, and how to cope with latency problems in transmission. The rest is a done deal. The gamers (remember who started this Internet craze, after all…) managed to convince the world to build them the most expensive toy in the his- tory of civilization. To some, this might seem like a sad turn of events. I do not think it is. Renaissances afford us the ability to rethink and redesign our world using en- tirely new rule sets. The shift in perspective, itself, however, is probably more valuable than where it takes us. It is an open window – a moment when the very control panel of our world is up for grabs. For as surely as it opened up, this window will close again once a sufficient consensus has been reached. We will then go on, accepting some new, albeit more dimensionalized, picture of reality as the truth, and mistake yet another map as the territory. Our present, mid-renaissance moment, however, is a window of opportunity. It is like the peak of a mystical experience or psychedelic trip – that moment when the journeyer thinks to himself, ‘how will I remember this when I am back to reality?’ More often than not, the psychic traveler will scribble down some words (‘I am one! It is one!’) that appear nonsensical in the light of day – even though the insight they mean to communicate is quite penetrating. So, assuming that we can even do it, what is it we want to embed in the civiliza- tion of the future? What would we want to remind ourselves of, once this little window has closed? I think, more than any ideology or narrative, the most impor- tant idea to associate with our renaissance is the notion that we are, as individuals and a collective, the writers of our own stories. And who or what might best accomplish this grand, trans-dimensional communication of autonomous, com- munitarian values? I would place my renaissance bet on the gamers’ perspective: the very notion that our world is open source, and that reality itself is up for grabs. For, more than anyone else, a real gamer knows that we are the ones creating the rules.

renaissance now! 183 This chapter was first published in Handbook of computer game studies, eds. Joost Raessens and Jeffrey Goldstein, 415-421. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Notes 1. For a critical discussion of the ideal of participatory culture, see the chapter by Mirko Tobias Schäfer in this book. 2. For a discussion of the importance of framing and reframing, see the chapter of Joost Raessens in this book. 3. For an in-depth discussion of the use of cartography in games, see the chapter by Sy- bille Lammes in this book. 4. For a discussion of how games like World of Warcraft are anchored in daily life, see the chapter of Marinka Copier in this book.

184 digital material Screen

What you get is what you see

Digital images and the claim on the real

Frank Kessler

In 1898 Boleslas Matuszewski, a photographer and former court cinematographer of Tsar Nikolas II, published a booklet in France entitled Une nouvelle source de l’histoire in which he pleads for the creation of a repository for actuality films so that they can serve as historical documents for future generations. Animated photography, he argues, is unrivalled in its capacity to faithfully record historical events and thus should be collected and stored in an official archive. Matuszewski claims that cinematographic images in particular can resist attempts to manipu- late them and thus are the most valuable witnesses of the past:

Perhaps the cinematograph does not give history in its entirety, but at least what it does deliver is incontestable and of an absolute truth. Ordinary photo- graphy admits of retouching, to the point of transformation. But try to retouch, in an identical way for each figure, these thousand or twelve hundred, almost microscopic negatives...! One could say that animated photography has a char- acter of authenticity, accuracy and precision that belongs to it alone. It is the ocular evidence that is truthful and infallible par excellence (Matuszewski 1995, 323).

Matuszewski thus offers a quite early formulation of a claim on the real, or in fact even a truth claim, that has haunted documentary film but also, for instance, news photography throughout the 20th century. Often challenged, time and again criticized and critiqued by practitioners and scholars alike, it has a tendency of popping up like a Jack-in-the-box whenever our trust in such images appears to have been abused. However, about a century after Matuszewski’s optimistic as- sessment of the cinematograph’s powers, media historian Brian Winston pro- claimed the definitive end of such naïve hopes:

Digitalization destroys the photographic image as evidence of anything except the process of digitalization. The physicality of the plastic material represented in any photographic image can no longer be guaranteed. For documentary to

187 survive the widespread diffusion of such technology depends on removing its claim on the real. There is no alternative (Winston 1995, 259).

According to Winston, the emergence of digital technology opens up almost un- limited possibilities to manipulate, reshape, fake and forge photographic and ci- nematic images which puts an end to a long tradition of endowing documentary photography and film with what has often been seen, in reference to a famous essay by film critic André Bazin, as an ontological claim on the real.1 This claim, the privileged relationship of the photographic image to the real, is actually based upon the fact that photography can be regarded as a result of a trace of light reflected from an object that has caused a chemical reaction in the photosensitive emulsion of a filmstrip. Following a remark by Charles Sanders Peirce on the complex semiotic nature of photographs, being both icon, as they are ‘in certain aspects exactly like the objects they represent’, and index, as a result of their hav- ing a ‘physical connection’ to the referent, Peter Wollen (1998, 86) points towards the similarity between Bazin’s thoughts on the ontology of the photographic im- age and Peirce’s concept of the indexical sign.2 In this way, indexicality has come to be considered an essential quality of conventional photo and film, and by the same token the guarantee of the ‘authenticity, accuracy and precision’, and thus truthfulness, which Matuszewski celebrated in 1898.3 Interestingly, looking at that question from the point of view of new media, for Lev Manovich, cinema as such is ‘an art of the index’ (2001, 293), and he argues that ‘as a media technol- ogy, its role was to capture and store visible reality’ (307). This, however, is al- tered radically by the advent of digital media, and so Manovich arrives at a conclu- sion that is quite similar to Brian Winston’s account quoted above: ‘The mutability of digital data impairs the value of cinema recordings as documents of reality’ (307). Thus, the question arises of whether digital technology indeed weakens, im- pairs, or maybe even destroys the privileged (ontological, indexical) link between analogical photographic or cinematic images and the real. This is a vexed ques- tion, indeed, most of all because several aspects appear to be inextricably inter- twined here. So in order to assess the scope of the problem, it may be useful to try and provisionally separate the different issues that are tied together in this argu- mentative knot, by designating them with a somewhat global character by using the following three tags: technology, indexicality and practices.

Technology: what you get Looking at the claims put forward with regard to the specific powers of the new image technologies concerning their relationship to the real, it is interesting to note that Matuszewski as well as Winston and Manovich rely on quantitative rather than qualitative arguments. While Matuszewski emphasises the quasi-im-

188 digital material possibility to retouch the sheer number of individual photographs contained on a filmstrip, Winston and Manovich insist on how extraordinarily easy it is to modify digital images or, as Philip Rosen phrases it, their ‘practically infinite manipul- ability’ (2001, 319). However, inverting these characterisations of the new tech- nologies, one could riposte to Matuszewski that this relative difficulty of retouch- ing a view taken by a cinematograph by no means guarantees truthfulness. With historical hindsight, it becomes clear such manipulations are not even that excep- tional (tricks, special effects, but also the sometimes rather blunt attempts in So- viet films to conceal certain individuals who had fallen into disgrace). One could counter Winston and Manovich with the argument that manipulability is nothing new in this domain, and that the traditional claim on the real, in that respect, could only be accepted by wilfully disregarding such potentials for manipulation. The change brought about by the new image technologies, in other words, could be seen as rather less radical than the above-quoted statements suggest. On the other hand, the possibilities to digitally manipulate images have, some- what paradoxically, caused news photographers to scrutinize the various techni- ques they habitually used, in order to find out to what extent these are prone to objectionable alterations. As Dona Schwartz (2003) shows, interventions of one kind or the other are unavoidable: the photographer does have to make choices with regard to lenses, filters, the position from which the photo is to be taken, the , the shutter speed, etc. Furthermore, also in the darkroom, even the most standard methods are in fact acts of interference (see also Gunning 2004, 40). So what are the limits? What can a photographer justifiably eliminate from a picture? A reflection from a flash? The red-eye effect? Reducing a colour photo to black and white? Is a motion blur inappropriate? From the discussions repro- duced by Schwartz (2003, 40-45), it is obvious that professional photojournalists are afraid of getting on a ‘slippery slope’ here and thus tend to ban even minor manipulations. On the other hand, however, there is no way to fix a standard that could guarantee the absolute objectivity that functions here tacitly as an ideal. Schwartz distinguishes three strategies to establish such a norm: depicting the subject ‘as the camera sees it’, depicting it ‘as someone present at the scene would have seen it’,orto‘authorize the photographers to make decisions regard- ing image production consistent with the prevailing norms governing journalistic representations across communicative modes’ (2003, 45-46). The first two strate- gies seem to be oriented towards a conception of objectivity in accordance with the scientific criterion of repeatability, namely that, given identical circumstances, a certain procedure will always have the same result, when a normative frame- work exists that photographers can refer back to in case of doubt. However, as Schwartz rightly states, taking ‘camera vision’ as a rationale would presuppose the use of standardised equipment, whereas the alignment with a human obser- ver’s visual experience raises numerous questions, in particular regarding the en- what you get is what you see 189 ormous differences between human perception and ‘camera vision’. According to which parameters can a photograph be said to correspond to the way an onlooker would have perceived a situation? In a way, the third strategy admits the impossi- bility of unambiguous guidelines, relying instead on a set of more or less unwrit- ten rules that can at any moment be modified or revised. Nevertheless, these discussions show that the problem of manipulability did not arise with the advent of digital technologies, but has been an issue in photo- graphy all along. Rather, the debates generated by new media about the possibi- lities of intervention have led to a self-critical questioning of traditional media practices. In this respect, one may conclude that photography’s claim on the real has always been rather fragile. Digitalization, in other words, not so much caused an obliteration of the privileged link between the photographic image and the real, but rather provoked a return of the repressed, namely a renewed awareness of the numerous forms of manipulation and intervention that constitute the very activity of producing and presenting (moving) pictures. This, I would argue, is actually the point Winston is trying to make as well. Given his detailed critique of documentary’s claim on the real, preceding the remark quoted above, digitaliza- tion may in fact be nothing but the straw that breaks the camel’s back.4

Indexicality: what you see But even if, with regard to both traditional and digital photo and film, there are numerous factors that influence the way a picture is taken and how it appears on screen or as print, the question remains of whether the indexicality of the photo- graphic image is somehow reduced or even abolished through the advent of digi- tal technologies. In an article in which he interrogates the status of the concept of the index in recent debates on the subject, Tom Gunning (2004, 40) states that the difference, again, is certainly not absolute:

Clearly a records through its numerical data the same intensi- ties of light that a non-digital camera records: hence the similarity of their images. The difference between the digital and the film based camera has to do with the way information is captured – which does have strong implications for the way the images can be stored, transferred and indeed manipulated. But storage in terms of numerical data does not eliminate indexicality (which is why digital images can serve as passport photographs and the other sorts of legal evidence or documents which ordinary photographs supply).

Engaging in a discussion with Tom Gunning, David Rodowick insists on what he describes as an ‘ontological distinctiveness of analogical and digital processes’ (2007, 113). Rodowick refers here to the two fundamentally different ways in which they relate to the object that is represented:

190 digital material If analog media record traces of events and digital media produce tokens of numbers, the following may also be asserted: digital acquisition quantifies the world as manipulable series of numbers. This is the primary automatism and the source of the creative powers of digital computing. Alternatively, photographic automatisms yield spatial segments of duration in a uniform substance. Both kinds of photography produce convincing representations as a result of their quality of counterfactual dependence, wherein any change in the referent is reflected as a corresponding change in the image, and in both cases this qual- ity relies on the logic of indexicality. But they may also be qualitatively distin- guished according to the types of causation involved in the acquisition of images and by ascertaining whether the causal relations between inputs and outputs are continuous or discontinuous. Here (analogical) transcription should be distinguished from (digital) conversion or calculation (Rodowick 2007, 116; author’s emphasis).

So on the one hand, both Gunning and Rodowick agree that the ‘logic of indexi- cality’ is at work in both digital and analogue photography and film. They differ, however, in their assessment of the impact that results from the qualitative differ- ence between the two processes. Here, for Rodowick, the ontological distinctive- ness of the digital ultimately leads to an ‘unbecoming of photography’ (2007, 124). Using the terminology coined by Sol Worth (1981, 52-53) in the 1960s, one could say that both Gunning and Rodowick conceive the videme, the image-event, in similar terms, while they differ in their views on the status of the specificity that distinguishes the digital cademe (that which is recorded during one uninterrupted take) from its analogue counterpart. As my concern is rather with the ‘claim on the real’ that is habitually based on the indexical quality of photography and film, I shall not discuss the issue of the ontological difference postulated by Rodowick further, even though I am sceptical about some of the conclusions he draws from this premise (more on this below). What needs further interrogation here is the scope of the ‘claim on the real’ that indexicality can actually support. What exactly is it that is truthfully rendered by a photograph or a cinematic take? Strictly speaking, of course, the indexical link between a filmic take or a photo and the real cannot go beyond the spatio-tem- poral segment that was recorded. And this in fact only concerns what Worth calls the cademe, as what is to be seen is in fact already the result of various forms of intervention. Yet, as Roland Barthes (1964, 47; 1980, 120) puts it, a photo is al- ways the trace of something that has been in front of the camera. While this corresponds exactly to the idea of photographic and cinematic indexicality, one should be careful not to glide from stating the object’s ‘having been there’ to the more global assertion that the image depicts ‘how it was’. This in fact is what Barthes himself does in the earlier text, when he declares that a photograph ap- pears as the evidence of how things happened (‘cela c’est passé ainsi’, 1964, 47). what you get is what you see 191 Such a view indeed overstates the case that an indexical image can reasonably make5, and, as a matter of fact, in his 1980 book La chambre claire Barthes limits photography’s evidential power once more to its confirming of the object’s ‘hav- ing been’: ‘ça a été’ or, in Latin: interfuit (1980, 120-121).

As I have argued elsewhere (Kessler 1998), the concepts of the profilmic and of the afilmic that were coined by the French École de filmologie in the early 1950s can help to clarify the complex relationship between indexical images and ‘the real’. Eti- enne Souriau (1953, 8) defines the profilmic as everything that has been in front of the camera and was recorded by it, whereas the afilmic refers to what exists in our world ‘independent of the art of film or without any specific and original destiny in relation with this art’ (1953, 7; author’s translation). This distinction can be read as follows: while the profilmic is either photochemically transcribed or digitally coded, the afilmic remains irreducible to such a recording.6 The in- dexical ‘claim on the real’, in other words, can never go beyond the profilmic. The afilmic, on the other hand, should not be seen as simply the spatial and temporal continuation of the profilmic but rather as a construction against, and in refer- ence to, how the represented is understood, evaluated, judged, accepted or re- jected, etc. by the viewer. The indexical image can hardly state anything else than that the profilmic ‘has been’; even for it to say ‘it has been there and then’ re- quires, in most cases, additional information of some kind (think of the many infamous examples of abducted persons holding a in their hands in order to identify the date the picture was taken). Thus, I would argue that the problem in most of the debates about non-fictional photography or film lies in their conceiving them as documentations of the afilmic real rather than approaching them as discourses on it. Through such a shift in perspective, the ‘claim on the real’ no longer depends on the indexical image but on the status a viewer ascribes to that discourse. Tak- ing up John Searle’s reflections on the logical status of fictional discourse (Searle 1979, 58-75) and using them in a pragmatic perspective, one can say that, in the first instance, what makes a photo or a film function as a non-fictional or ‘se- rious’ utterance is the fact that the viewer can interrogate it in terms of trueness. This makes it possible to deflate the idea of documentary’s ‘truth claim’, as this does not mean that the utterance has to be true – it just is possible to ask the question of whether it is, or whether it could be a lie (whereas such questions would not make any sense with regard to a fictional utterance). The viewer, in other words, constructs an ‘enunciator supposed to be real’ (Odin 1984), an in- stance, thus, that is committed to the truth of the expressed proposition accord- ing to the rules underlying such a speech act (Searle 1979, 62). As this commit- ment concerns the discourse as a whole and not necessarily all of its elements, the indexical image need not carry the claim on the real all by itself. Quite to the contrary, as Roger Odin (2000, 127-150) shows, the functioning of a ‘documen-

192 digital material tarisational’ mode (mode documentarisant) will be upheld in spite of a vast hetero- geneity of image material (animation, simulation, CGI, staged scenes, poetic images, etc.), as long as the spectator does construct an enunciator that is sup- posed to be real. And indeed, there are countless examples of documentaries as well as educational, scientific, or even news films that incorporate diverse forms of non-photographic imagery without their ‘claim on the real’ being impaired in any way.7 Even recreations such as the actualités reconstituées in early cinema, but also more recent examples such as United 93 (Paul Greengrass, USA 2006) can be read as serious utterances that do not present indexical recordings of the ‘there and then’ that their discourse refers to. In the context of such a discourse on the afilmic real, indexical and other types of images can be used in many different ways. Being contextualised, arranged, oriented, discursively framed, no picture ‘speaks for itself’. Viewers have to judge for themselves whether to go along with the discourse proposed by the images or read it differently: they can either trust or reject it, and the meanings that are explicitly or implicitly presented can be assessed, negotiated, evaluated and inter- preted. The indexical has to be taken into account here, certainly, but it does not guarantee anything. Or, as a text title in Jean-Luc Godard’s Vent d’Est (1969) pro- claims: ‘Ce n’est pas une image juste, mais juste une image.’

Practices: what you get to see Paradoxically, one might assert that new media have brought forth a proliferation of practices that foreground the indexical properties of digitally recorded images. From JenniCam to pet portraits on personal websites, from image-sharing sites such as Flickr or YouTube (not to mention their pornographic versions), from celeb- rity pictures to rather infamous examples like the execution of Saddam Hussein or the Abu Ghraib photos, from the most scandalous revelations to the most mun- dane documents of people’s everyday lives, the uses of and video in innumerable cases rely on the indexical qualities they undoubtedly have.8 And indeed, one would rather hope that the x-ray photos taken by one’s dentist, even though they are produced and viewed as digital images, do have a justified ‘claim on the real’–even though, as many may have found out in a painful way, there is no guarantee that the dentist reads them properly. Furthermore, digital media – CD-ROM, DVD, the Internet – provide new chan- nels of distribution, either for historical non-fiction films or for new productions, but also enable filmmakers (the term seems a bit out of place here) to experiment with new documentary forms, making use of hypertext structures, non-linear pre- sentation, interactive elements, etc. Online archives and platforms make a large amount of documentary images accessible, and nothing indicates that people treat them any differently than conventional photochemical images.

what you get is what you see 193 For David Rodowick, however, these new forms of distribution and circulation are not so much a continuation of earlier practices but rather part of the ‘ontolo- gical distinctiveness’ of the digital image:

In worrying about the capacity of computers to transform images, we nearly forget their more powerful and prosaic will to copy and transmit. Digital-cap- ture documents and digital documentation express new powers – not only deep and superior copies, but also an increasing ease and velocity of dissemi- nation. (…) One key difference, though, is that digital images may no longer be capable of producing the existential or ontological perplexity of which both Barthes and Cavell were so keenly and philosophically aware. Digital photo- graphs have become more social than personal, and more attuned to the pre- sent itself than to the present’s relation to the past and future. Symbolic and notational at their core, they provoke discussion of images as information.In this they solicit often-healthy debates (would that all images did) about prove- nance, reliability, accuracy, and context (Rodowick 2007, 148-149; author’s emphasis).

But here, I would argue, Rodowick’s focus actually shifts from the ontology of photographic images to the level of uses and practices. Observing a move from the personal to the social, from the photograph as ‘remembrance of things past’ celebrated by Barthes and Cavell (1979) to their informational function, Rodowick takes this as a consequence of the ‘ontological distinctiveness’ of digital photo- graphy. But then again, there always have been an enormous variety of ways in which the photographic image has been used, and not for all of them a phenom- enological functioning as a trace of the past saying that ça a été is equally relevant.9 Here Rodowick does not quite escape the problem of identifying a medium with but one specific type of practice. This does not mean, however, that the emergence of digital technology has hardly affected photography as a medium. The argument I am making here is a different one: by looking first and foremost at alone, dis- cussions tend to either overrate or underrate its impact. Similarities and continu- ities are overlooked or, conversely, overemphasised. The new is seen as either radically disruptive or as just a variant of what exists. Media change, I would argue, manifests itself rather in the way new media dispositifs emerge. Considering media as the interrelation between the different affordances of a material technol- ogy, the positions it provides for the viewer or the user, and the textual forms it produces may help to understand media change differently, to be precise as re- configurations of such dispositifs, keeping intact some of its aspects and modify- ing or even completely reshaping others (Kessler 2002, 2006). It is quite evident that an initially photochemical image that is remediated in a digital medium func- tions within a dispositif that is different from its traditional manifestation as a

194 digital material printed picture. So we need to analyse the dispositif in order to understand the functioning of the image. As for the potential threat that digital manipulability poses to the documentary value of photography and film, the problem is addressed in a too one-sided way by just looking at the technology instead of taking into account the practices it is embedded in. As Dai Vaughan so convincingly put it, there is indeed a chance that digitally manipulated imagery will eventually have become so omnipresent that our trust in the photographic image gets lost in something like a ‘catastrophe model, where a seemingly innocuous curve takes a sudden nosedive, an irreversi- ble switch into another state’ (1999, 189). But this would then be the result of the discursive practices in which these images are used, not of the technology as such. In the end, what is needed, and will become increasingly important, is a general level of media literacy that enables viewers and users to interrogate and critically assess in what way a digital image may have a claim on the real.

Notes 1. The reference here is of course to André Bazin’s ‘Ontologie de l’image photographique’ (Bazin 1958, 11-19). 2. For a discussion about the relation between Peirce’s and Bazin’s ideas, see Rosen (2001, 18-23 et passim) and Gunning (2007, 29-33). 3. Furthermore, from very early on photography has been considered a potential scientific instrument as well. Already in his 1839 report on the daguerreotype the French scientist Dominique-François Arago (1995) stresses its usefulness for that domain. See also Win- ston (1993). 4. Elsewhere Winston’s critique concerns in particular observational documentary films and their ‘inflated claim on the real’, and he quite favourably discusses classic docu- mentaries and their strategy of ‘honest, straightforward re-enactment’, as Joris Ivens called it (Winston 1999). 5. This became painfully clear when the Rodney King videotape was presented as evidence in court. Bill Nichols (1994, 17-42) gives a brilliant analysis of this event. 6. Souriau’s definitions are not without ambiguities. They also allow a different reading according to which everything that is destined to be filmed belongs to the realm of the profilmic, in particular studio sets, costumes, etc., while everything that has an exis- tence outside the institution of cinema is considered afilmic. In this perspective the profilmic is sometimes even exclusively linked to fiction film, whereas documentary is associated with the afilmic. Jean-Luc Liout (2004, 41-51) calls everything in its actual existence afilmic, regardless of whether it is being filmed (such as the silhouette of a mountain, for instance), and everything profilmic that is intentionally linked to the act of filming (not only the abovementioned studio elements such as sets and costumes, but also, for example, the staging of an interview for a non-fiction film). While Sour- iau’s formulations do authorise such readings, I would argue that on the basis of what one sees in the image, it is not always possible to determine whether or not it has been arranged intentionally to be filmed, and thus the difference between both concepts becomes relative and also artificial, as all the aspects of the profilmic that Liout lists do obviously exist in the afilmic world as well.

what you get is what you see 195 7. A case in point might be the documentary mode that Bill Nichols (1994, 92-106) de- scribes as ‘performative’. See also Plantinga (2005) who defines documentary as ‘as- serted veridical representation’, referring also to its overall discursive status in an at- tempt to account for the complex interaction of different types of representational strategies, imagery, sound, and speech. 8. Rubinstein and Sluis (2008) describe the current developments in what they call ‘the networked image’ even in terms of ‘a life more photographic’. 9. Including some in which the indexical quality is of lesser importance, such as in certain artistic practices, but also, at the other end of the spectrum, in stock photography used for illustration and advertisement. For the latter, see Frosh (2003).

References Arago, Dominique-François. 1995 (orig. 1839). Rapport sur le Daguerréotype. Reprint, La Ro- chelle: Rumeur des Ages. Barthes, Roland. 1964. Rhétorique de l’image. Communications 4: 40-51. —. 1980. La chambre claire. Paris: Gallimard/Cahiers du Cinéma. Bazin, André. 1958. Qu’est-ce que le cinéma? I. Ontologie et langage. Paris: Cerf. Cavell, Stanley. 1979. The world viewed: Reflections on the ontology of film. Enlarged edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Frosh, Paul. 2003. Digital technology and stock photography: And God created photoshop. In Image ethics in the digital age, eds. Larry Gross, John Stuart Katz, and Jay Ruby, 183-216. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Gunning, Tom. 2004. What’s the point of an index? or, faking photographs. Nordicom Re- view 1-2: 39-49. —. 2007. Moving away from the index: Cinema and the impression of reality. Differences: A Journal of feminist cultural studies 18 (1): 29-52. Kessler, Frank. 1998. Fakt oder Fiktion? Zum pragmatischen Status dokumentarischer Bilder. Montage/AV 7(2): 63-78. —. 2002. Het idee van vooruitgang in de mediageschiedschrijving. Utrecht: Universiteit Utrecht. —. 2006. The cinema of attractions as dispositif.InThe cinema of attractions reloaded, ed. Wan- da Strauven, 57-69. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Liout, Jean-Luc. 2004. Àl’enseigne du réel: Penser le documentaire. Aix-en-Provence: Publications de l’Université de Provence. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Matuszewski, Boleslas. 1995. A new source of history [1898]. Film History 7 (3): 322-324. Nichols, Bill. 1994. Blurred boundaries: Questions of meaning in contemporary culture. Blooming- ton, Indianapolis: University of Indiana Press. Odin, Roger. 1984. Film documentaire, lecture documentarisante. In Cinémas et réalités, eds. Jean-Charles Lyant and Roger Odin, 263-278. Saint-Etienne: CIEREC. —. 2000. De la fiction. : De Boeck. Plantinga, Carl. 2005. What a documentary is, after all. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criti- cism 63 (2): 105-117. Rodowick, David. 2007. The virtual life of film. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rosen, Philip. 2001. Change mummified: Cinema, historicity, theory. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

196 digital material Rubinstein, Daniel and Katrina Sluis. 2008. A life more photographic: Mapping the net- worked image. Photographies 1 (1): 9-28. Schwartz, Dona. 2003. Professional oversight: Policing the credibility of . In Image Ethics in the Digital Age, eds. Larry Gross, John Stuart Katz and Jay Ruby, 27-51. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Searle, John R. 1979. Expression and meaning: Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Souriau, Etienne. 1953. Préface. In L’Univers filmique, ed. Etienne Souriau, 5-10. Paris: Flam- marion. Vaughan, Dai. 1999. For documentary. Berkeley: University of California Press. Winston, Brian. 1993. The documentary film as scientific inscription. In Theorizing documen- tary, ed. Michael Renov, 37-57. New York: Routledge. —. 1995. Claiming the real: The documentary film revisited. London: British Film Institute. —. 1999. ‘Honest, straightforward re-enactment’: The staging of reality. In Joris Ivens and the documentary context, ed. Kees Bakker, 160-170. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Wollen, Peter. 1998. Signs and meaning in the cinema. Expanded edition, London: British Film Institute. Worth, Sol. 1981. Studying visual communication. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

what you get is what you see 197

The pervasive interface

Tracing the magic circle

Eva Nieuwdorp

Imagine you and your colleagues are invited to participate in a game to enhance team-building. You are divided into teams, each of which receives a lunchbox containing a city map, a digital camera and a web-enabled mobile phone. You are then sent out into the street, to wait for instructions. The mobile phone signals that you have received a message. On the screen it reads: ‘Sometime today you will be approached by the Speaker. The Speaker could be anyone, anywhere… all we know is that the Speaker will say something to you. It could be anything, and you’ll only know it’s the Speaker if you form a circle around him or her and dance wildly...’ (McGonigal 2003). Following this ambiguous clue, you have to complete a mission that consists of locating an unspecified person. He or she could be anywhere and anyone around you. It is your task to look for hints, forcing you to shift your perception of the surrounding environment. You are now playing The Go Game (www.thegogame.com), a pervasive game. Pervasive games are steadily emerging as a new genre of digital games. Exam- ples such as I Love Bees (2004, www.ilovebees.com) and Botfighters (2001, www. botfighters.com) broaden the game world to include elements of everyday life, subsequently also bringing rules of play into the public sphere of, for example, the street and the workplace. Unlike other games, the mobile nature of pervasive games is unique by allowing an ambiguous wavering between fantasy and reality when played. In this chapter, I will argue that it is exactly this ambiguity that is at the core of the player’s experience and indeed at the construction of the game world itself. Set against the backdrop of the physical reality of everyday life, the thin line between the evident ‘real’ world and the institutionalised fantasy of the game becomes the crux to which the pervasive game owes its existence. The per- vasive game interweaves the concept of reality and fantasy, thus transforming our everyday environment into a world in play. This complicates the notions of reality and fantasy (fantasy referring to the game). Furthermore, within the game world, Roger Caillois’s terms ludus and paidia (2001) are set off against one another. As will be discussed later on, the concept of childlike ‘play’ or paidia positions itself in a similar way in relation to its more formal counterpart, ludus or ‘game’.

199 Hence, not only does the world of the game reiterate its own status as a fantasti- cal artefact through the continuing juxtaposition with the ‘real’ physical world of everyday life, the nature of play is also of a freer and more open character that resembles child’s play. But what happens at the crossroads of these intermingling phenomena? What are the instances that incite the merging of fantasy and reality, and how can we best define this fusion? In this chapter, I will investigate these questions by look- ing at the applicability of the term ‘interface’ to the co-existence of supposed antagonistic forces in pervasive games. I argue that the status of the interface as an intermediary between the user and the (technological) system makes it the most important focus to determine which border is being crossed from reality to game. By asking the questions of where and how the interface comes into being in pervasive games, I offer a first insight into what the limbo between reality and the game is, as well as specifying the relationship between ludus and paidia that is so characteristic of pervasive games. The role of the player forms an important part of this chapter, as I state that players form the most crucial kind of interface in this type of play. Pervasive games exist by the mercy of players, and without them the streets will inevitably return to their everyday status. I will therefore argue that the interface I am trying to define can be partly located in the thoughts and imagination of the player, thus acquiring a more cultural and symbolic meaning. Two important notions in this equation are the ‘real’ and the ‘virtual’. They should be conceived as the opposi- tion between cultural conventions that are normally present in everyday life (such as going to work or walking on the street) and the fictional game world that is generated by means of computer technology. Further on in this chapter, this dis- tinction between ‘real’ everyday life and the game world will be addressed in more detail, and will be respectively denoted by the terms ‘telic’ and ‘paratelic’ (Apter and Kerr 1999).

Pervasive gaming For a term as up-and-coming as pervasive gaming, it may seem surprising that the definitions remain vague. A common approach is lacking, and it remains un- clear how pervasive gaming differs from neighbouring phenomena such as ubi- quitous gaming, augmented reality gaming and mobile gaming (Nieuwdorp 2007). Pervasive games are in general described as inducing a mixture of the real and the virtual, in particular creating virtual worlds of play in everyday environ- ments through the use of different ubiquitous applications of technologies (me- dia) (Davidsson, Peitz and Bjork 2004; McGonigal 2003). In a temporal, spatial and social sense, the game world encompasses everyday physical environments, which the player can interact with in real time through multiple media platforms (Sotamaa 2002).

200 digital material When investigating the nature of pervasive play, the borders between the differ- ent elements of fantasy and reality must irrevocably be sought out, which leads us to the interface. Applied to digital games, the interface is invariably made equiva- lent to either the hardware (controllers and the like) or the software (visual ele- ments of the game world) that generate human-computer interaction (HCI). The screen captures both aspects, as it is both part of the hardware while at the same time visually representing the 3D game world through software. It functions as a veritable Alberti’s window through which the user can step from physical reality into the virtual universe of the game. The screen can be viewed as a translucent membrane, an intermediary, which translates digital signs into actual player ex- perience and parallels the player’s physical actions to manipulation in the digital realm. In the field of HCI, the concept is taken to mean the human-computer interface with its desktop metaphor or hardware connotations. When applied to digital games, the interface is determined as a fixed screen and gaming device (Manovich 2001) and is increasingly seen as a potential obstacle to immersive qualities of the gaming experience (Cheok et al. 2002). But is this notion of the interface in digital games satisfactory for understanding pervasive games? In per- vasive games, visual representations are no longer dominated by the screen. This challenges current concepts of the interface. Both from the perspective of the game, which is ambivalent in its player-game interaction and reality/game status, and from the perspective of the interface, which is no longer limited to the hard- ware and software, it is interesting to see how these two terms can be defined in relation to one another. In the area of HCI as well as in digital games theory, the screen is conceived of as the ultimate interface (Johnson 1997; Laurel 1991; Man- ovich 2001). Especially in HCI, the interface is seen as the tip of the iceberg of the programming language that is needed to make an application work (Meyer 1988). This makes the interface primarily a graphical and tangible concept. Both hard- ware and software interfaces are tailored to make the interaction as easy as possi- ble. The focus is thus put on designing and testing, and keeping the concept consistent. Yet when we hark back to our definition of pervasive games as stated above, we see that the virtual (the synthetic artefact as generated by a computer) also inter- twines on a social and cultural level with everyday life. This necessitates a differ- ent approach to the concept of the interface, as the social and geographical sur- roundings of the technology used are now open to change due to the mobility of the player, who interacts with more than just a PDA or mobile phone. Although in interface theory the emphasis has been primarily placed on the graphical and the tangible, several attempts have been made to extend the con- cept to social and cultural realms. As computer scientist Grudin already foresaw (1989; 1990; 1993), we need to customize the concept of the interface to apply the social and spatial environments of interaction. Recently, the interest in defining the practice of computing in relation to users and their environment has in- the pervasive interface 201 creased. Users bring a personal history and setting along, which is comprised of prior knowledge and experience. This is what Paul Dourish (2001) calls ‘embod- ied interaction’. When players participate in a pervasive game, they are actively creating meaning, and as we will see later on, they often need to reinterpret com- mon conventions about meaning. After all, as the spatial qualities of the environ- ment are shared with the existing setting of an already familiar environment (such as the streets), the player must bring along a concept not unlike the willing sus- pension of disbelief in film to engage meaningfully in the game. The game world must be accepted as somehow different from everyday life, and thus conventions in everyday life are challenged. Therefore, the facilitating factors for playing a pervasive game lie not solely within hardware and software, but also in the player.

Semiotic domains Before examining the membrane that separates the game world from everyday life, the specifics of both terms need to be ascertained. Only after the two differ- ent domains are fenced off can we see what the fence is made of. What makes a pervasive game? What makes it come into being? To answer these questions, a closer look at the practice of signs and semiotics is needed. As a pervasive game takes place partly in an already existing environment with its own laws and conventions, it is important to look at the elements that actually change when the game world comes into being. Knowing the conventions of the real world makes it easier to observe what changes in the arena of play. These cultural conventions, which are agreed upon socially but are implemented on a personal scale, are the focus of the interface in pervasive game-play. I would like to illustrate this with an example. Imagine you are a participant in The Go Game, a pervasive game that is played with a mobile phone in an urban environment. You are walking on the street when you receive a text message: ‘Sometime today you will find the Mystery Key. It won’t look like a key, but it will work some kind of magic when you encounter a locked door later in the game. So make sure you take with you any unusual objects you find along the way…’ (McGonigal 2003). In a ‘normal’ situation, one would know a key when seeing one, whilst now the only thing you do know is that the key in question could be anything but a conven- tional key. Instead of going to a locksmith, you will need to consider all objects that do not fit the conventional context of everyday surroundings as potential keys. In other words, you need to view familiar environments with different eyes. This is only one example, and perhaps an exaggerated one, but it does point to a characteristic of all pervasive games. Whether brought about by vague missions or the situation that the street has changed into a battlefield, the fact remains that, no matter the degree of intensity, the player always needs to shift focus from the everyday world to the conventions and rules of the entered game. The

202 digital material example above demonstrates how different the approach to environments then needs to be. What changes is the correlation between an entity and its meaning. This is very apparent in the form that the key takes in the example: instead of the word ‘key’ pertaining to a specific object, it now relates to anything but that object. What is put under strain is the semiotic relationship between the Saussurian ‘signifier’ and ‘signified’, where the former refers to the linguistic sound image of a thing, and the latter to the mental concept of a thing (Hawkes 2003). The relationship between an object and its accepted conventional meaning alters in pervasive games. Surely, in everyday life it is always possible to approach an object or situa- tion in different ways according to context and personal goals, but in pervasive games this relationship is more purposefully challenged. One could argue that we transgress into another mental state that makes us accept new rules and conventions when shifting from practices of everyday life to the ludic space of the pervasive game world. But how does this happen? Semiotics can help us to answer this question. According to James Paul Gee (2003) video- games can be perceived as distinct semiotic domains. In pervasive games, we can then approach the game world as a semiotic domain with its own constructed meanings. This world can be seen as separate from the semiotic domain of every- day life, which Gee calls the ‘lifeworld’ domain. When deciding to play a perva- sive game, one crosses from one semiotic (‘lifeworld’) domain into another do- main, thus adopting and adapting to a distinctive set of conventions and meanings. But where does this border reside? To answer this question I will take a closer look at the concept of the magic circle and the metaphor of the cell mem- brane.

The magic circle and the metaphorical membrane A concept that is often employed to describe the soap bubble of the game world is that of the magical circle, as introduced by Dutch historian Johan Huizinga (1955).1 Relating this term to the interface in pervasive gaming, the thin line be- tween this ludic circle and the practice of everyday life becomes the main focus. It is this border, this threshold, which needs to be crossed in order to enter the game world. And thus, tracing the contours of the magic circle is indeed closely related to tracking down the several levels of the pervasive interface. As pervasive games force us to reinterpret meanings ascribed to everyday settings and objects, this border becomes more apparent than in any other type of game. The magic circle must not be viewed as a rigid sphere that can be superim- posed on everyday reality. Instead, it should be seen as a nearly organic entity that changes, develops and interacts with its surroundings as the pervasive game comes into being through play. In this sense the magic circle becomes a perme- able membrane where conventional meanings, psychological artefacts and envir- the pervasive interface 203 onments, and players alike can slip through. This reasoning is supported by Er- ving Goffman (1961), who argues that a permeable screen-like boundary demar- cates games from the world at large. Yet the relationship between reality and game is more intricate than a crude juxtaposition of terms. The very notion of a cell membrane points to the two-way direction of exchange between the game world and everyday life. But how can we delineate the border between everyday life and the domain of the pervasive game? According to Goffman specific boundary-maintaining me- chanisms can be distinguished that govern the shape of the magic circle or ludic cell membrane of a game. Goffman asserts that these mechanisms can be cate- gorised as follows: 1. rules of irrelevance: players renounce material, emotional or aesthetic values when playing a game; 2. transformation rules: these rules denote the amount of influence on the sta- tus of the game a non-game element has that for some reason enters the magic circle; 3. realised resources: all possible moves that can be made in the game that are open to all players.

All of these factors play an important role in pervasive games. Transformation rules tell us what effect external aspects can have in the game world. Thinking back to the example of The Go Game, it is clear that the transformation rules are very loosely defined in that game, making it difficult for the player to discern what is part of the game world and what is not. This means that the realised resources in the game world seem almost infinite to players, since they cannot be sure what objects are intended for the game world. Both the transformation rules and the realised resources can then be seen to depend on the acceptance of the game world as an omnipresent and persistent realm of which everything could possibly be part. This is what Goffman calls rules of irrelevance: a selective disregard of certain values that have a meaningful place in the life world domain, but which do not agree with the cultural conventions of the game world. These rules facilitate the state of mind that is needed to accept the game world as an arena of play. How this state can be described and takes shape will be discussed in the next section of this chapter.

Now it has become clear that the pervasive game world is in fact a semiotic do- main with its own rules and conventions and that the coming-into-being of this game world requires an active mental shift from players in relation to their envir- onment, we can direct our attention to a description of the shift that the player has to make to acquire a state of playing. So far, little research has been conducted in the field of players’ attitudes from a formal perspective. Some attempts have been made, notably by Bernard Suits

204 digital material (1990) and Satu Heliö (2004) who speak of ‘lusory attitude’ and the ‘gaming mindset’, respectively, but both of these terms are related to the way a player views the game world ‘in play’. They do not refer to the instance when this change in mental state actually occurs, which, so to speak, ‘announces’ the com- ing-into-being of the game world. This is where the notion of the interface comes in.

The liminal interface: paratelic and paraludic I have already shown that interfaces, which facilitate the game world to take form, are not merely located in hardware and software, but also in the mind of the player. I have called this the liminal interface, liminal referring to the status of the interface as threshold or transitional stage. As a term coined by anthropologist Victor Turner, the liminal has been used to describe the phase of transition to play (Ericsson 2004; Brian Sutton-Smith 1997). The liminal interface, then, is the aforementioned interface that is located in the mind of the player and refers to the semiotic switch that has to be made between the sphere of everyday life and the semiotic domain of the pervasive game. This interface consists of two sub-cate- gories: the paratelic and the paraludic interface. The following theory is based on a combination of views in psychology about adult play (Apter et al, 1991), and classifications of playing and gaming as devised by Bo Kampmann Walther (2003). Walther discerns two different transitions: first between the initially serious state of mind (non-play) into play, and secondly the subsequent transition to accepting the rigid rules of a game (from play to game). The terms ‘play’ and ‘game’ correspond to Caillois’s (2001, 13) terms pai- dia and ludus, respectively. He described paidia as ‘an almost indivisible princi- ple, common to diversion, turbulence, free improvisation, and carefree gaiety’ and ludus as ‘a tendency to bind [paidia] with arbitrary, imperative, and purposely tedious conventions.’ Paidia then refers to free play such as that of children, while ludus indicates the institutionalized game with its rules and regulations.

Let’s first focus on the transgression from non-play into play. This first initiation into the pervasive game, and indeed into all games, can be called the paratelic state. Coined by psychologists Apter and Kerr (1991), it refers to a playful state of mind as opposed to one in which the ‘seriousness’ of everyday life takes pride of place. In the paratelic state, a person becomes playful and lets go of the restraints and cultural conventions that apply to work and other activities in which the end justifies the means. The paratelic state of ‘play’ must be conceived in Caillois’s sense of the word, and corresponds to paidia. The decision to play, and thus entering a game world, implies the necessary rejection of particular conventions and practices that are prevalent in the domain of everyday life (Apter and Kerr

the pervasive interface 205 1991). This is what Goffman referred to as rules of irrelevance: letting go of the practices of everyday life to prepare one’s mind for play. When we look at pervasive gaming, the paratelic interface becomes relevant at the moment that a person rejects the practices and conventions within the semio- tic domain of everyday life in order to enter a more playful realm. In my view this has everything to do with a temporary and reversible attention shift, in which the conventions of the semiotic domain of play prevail over those in daily life. It is important to keep in mind here that the term ‘para’ refers to the two-way direc- tion between reality and play and that the player can oscillate between these posi- tions. The fact that the conventions of the ‘lifeworld’ domain are left behind through rules of irrelevance does not mean that reality is pushed out of the pic- ture. In fact, quite the contrary is happening, as play actively needs reality to re- iterate its own status (Walther 2003). However, to complete the transition of moving into a game world with its own set of rules, more is needed than the rejection of conventions that are predomi- nant in everyday life. Additionally, game rules need to be accepted as the laws of the new semiotic domain that is entered. Put in Gee’s vocabulary, the player would otherwise not be able to understand the signs that govern the realm that is entered (Gee 2003). This is why a second transition is needed (the paraludic inter- face). Once players have crossed the threshold to enter the paraludic state, the rules of the game need to be learned. Gaining knowledge of its semiotic conventions enables players to develop a literacy that is needed to become part of the game world. Again, however, we must take into account the two-directional relation of the two states of play and game (Walther 2003). As the player enters the game, play is never far away. Thinking back to The Go Game, it is clear that a playful attitude can very much be a part of the game, for example when assignments are open to interpretation. These shifts from non-play to play into game require a very active stance of the player, who needs to realise on a meta-level the qualities of play, game and reality at once: something is play because it is not reality, something is a game because it is not play and consequently not reality. This constant threefold reiteration of the status of a game means that the player of a pervasive game will always in some form be reminded of the game being a construct. At the same time, accepting the game world as a separate semiotic domain implies shifting one’s focus and ac- cepting the conventions within that domain as dominant and thus as ‘real’.

Conclusions Pervasive games are a special type of game in which the relation between reality and game is emphasized. Due to the fact that the pervasive game is set both spa- tially and temporally in the ‘lifeworld’ domain, it is important to scrutinize how

206 digital material the game world can be distinguished from daily life. In this chapter I have inves- tigated this by looking at the status of the interface. In general, I can conclude that the term interface is mostly exclusively con- signed to the screen, since it is often apparent in hardware or software applica- tions. However, I have argued that the pervasive game challenges this notion of the interface by its ubiquitous and mobile nature. Literally taking the game world to the streets, it mixes the semiotic conventions that exist in the ‘lifeworld’ do- main and the pervasive game world. I have introduced the notion of the liminal interface to account for the fact that through a mental shift the player stays aware of this mixture and is able to distinguish between these two realms. The liminal interface can be seen as the edge of the magic circle or the metaphorical mem- brane that is entered when accepting the rules of irrelevance. The liminal interface consists of two levels: the paratelic interface, which refers to the player’s shifting focus when leaving the conventions of the ‘lifeworld’ do- main behind, and the paraludic interface, which makes the player accept the new conventions of the game world. In pervasive games these shifts are foregrounded by the unrelenting presence of the everyday world: the player needs to accept the game world as an omnipresent, persistent and consistent universe of which every- thing can be part, otherwise the interface, the edge of the magic circle, will be- come damaged – obliterating the very existence of the pervasive game.

Note 1. For an in-depth discussion of the term magic circle, see the chapter by Marinka Copier in this book.

References Apter, Michael, and John Kerr, eds. 1991. Adult play: A reversal theory approach. Amsterdam: Swets and Zeitlinger. Caillois, Roger. 2001 (orig. 1958). Man, play, and games. Champaign: University of Illinois Press. Cheok, Adrian, D., Xubo Yang, Zhou Zhi Ying, Mark Billinghurst, and Hirokazu Kato. 2002. Touch-Space: Mixed reality game space based on ubiquitous, tangible and social computing. Personal and ubiquitous computing (6): 430-442. Davidsson, Ola, Johan Peitz, and Staffan Björk. 2004. Game design patterns for mobile games. Project report to Nokia Research Center, . http://www.gamedesignpatterns.org. Dourish, Paul. 2001. Where the action is: The foundations of embodied interaction. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. Ericsson, Martin. 2004. Play to love: Reading Turner’s ‘Liminal to limonoid, in play, flow, and ritual: An essay in comparative symbology’.InBeyond role and play: Tools, toys and theory for harnessing the imagination, eds. Montola, M. and J. Stenros, 15-31. Ropecon ry, Helsinki.

the pervasive interface 207 Gee, James P. 2003. What video games have to teach us about learning and literacy. New York: Macmillan. Goffman, Erving. 1961. Encounters: Two studies in the sociology of interaction. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merril. Grudin, Jonathan. 1989. The case against user consistency. Communications of the ACM 32 (10): 1164-1173. —. 1990. The computer reaches out: The historical continuity of interface design. CHI ’90 Proceedings, 261-268. —. 1993. Interface. Communications of the ACM 36 (4): 112-119. Hawkes, Terence. 2003 (orig. 1977). Structuralism and semiotics. New York: Routledge. Heliö, Satu. 2004. Role-playing: A narrative experience and a mindset. In Beyond role and play: Tools, toys and theory for harnessing the imagination, eds. Montola, M. and J. Stenros. Ropecon ry, Helsinki. Huizinga, Johan. 1955 (orig. 1938). Homo Ludens: A study of the play element in culture. Boston: Beacon Press. Johnson, Steven. 1997. Interface culture: How new technology transforms the way we create and communicate. San Francisco: Harper. Laurel, Brenda. 1991. Computers as theatre. Boston: Addison-Wesley Publications. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. McGonigal, Jane. 2003. A real little game: The Pinocchio effect in pervasive play. In Level up: Digital games research conference, eds. Marinka Copier and Joost Raessens. Utrecht: Utrecht University. Meyer, Bertrand. 1988. Object-oriented software construction. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Nieuwdorp, Eva. 2007. The pervasive discourse: An analysis. ACM Computers in Entertainment (CIE) 5 (2): n.p. Salen, Katie, and Eric Zimmerman. 2004. Rules of play: Game design fundamentals. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sotamaa, Olli. 2002. All the world’s a Botfighter stage: Notes on location-based multi-user gaming. CGDC Conference Proceedings. Tampere University Press, 35-44. Suits, Bernard. 1990. Grasshopper: Games, life and utopia. Boston: David R. Godine. Sutton-Smith, Brian. 1997. The ambiguity of play. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Walther, Bo Kampmann. 2003. Playing and gaming: Reflections and classifications. Game Studies: The International Journal of Computer Game Research 3 (1). http://www.gamestudies. org/0301/walther.

208 digital material Grasping the screen

Towards a conceptualization of touch, mobility and multiplicity

Nanna Verhoeff

In 2004 Nintendo released the DS. With this new handheld console Nintendo updated and expanded the commercially successful Gameboy (1989) and its suc- cessors, the Game Boy Color (1998) and the Game Boy Advance (2001). The DS is marketed as a revolutionary console, because it allegedly offers radically new pos- sibilities for game play. The new ‘specs’ or technological features of the DS are, indeed, various: voice-control options, WiFi connectivity, touch-screen technol- ogy, and last but not least, multiple screens.

Figure 2: The Nintendo DS Lite with screenshots of the game Wario: Master of Disguise. (Courtesy of Nintendo, Benelux)

209 I chose this handheld game console as the object for my inquiry into the status of the mobile screen to answer historical as well as theoretical questions. In the midst of a continuous push for innovation and development, accompanied by ubiquitous marketing, it is the historical status of the gadget that is my first point of interest. With its specifications the DS console offers a distinctive interface and enables quite diverse possibilities for engaging and interacting with its screens and their on-screen content. This makes the DS an appealing case for my pur- pose: to explore the complex issues that emerge from a ‘theoretical object’ ap- proach to the Nintendo DS as a time-bound piece of material screen technology. Specifically, I am interested in the way innovations of technological objects – such as this gadget – inspire, and make necessary, applications that explore the possi- bilities and limitations offered by the interface for the use of the object as ‘screen practice’. A theoretical reason for my choice of the DS as object is that it is a screen-based console – a term I consider significant, literally as well as metaphorically. As a con- sole, the DS is a platform or interface for the games that can be played on it. Like any screen-based apparatus, its technology and the ensuing possibilities for its users both prescribe and need content. It requires an on-screen image or applica- tion, on the one hand, and the actual viewing or handling of the screen on the other. This dual need makes it necessary to consider the DS as more than an object; it must be seen as a practice. Screening as practice involves technology, content or application, and use. When we take the gadget not simply as a material object but as a time-bound object-in-practice, it becomes productive to consider a handheld console like the DS a theoretical object – or, as I argue below, a theore- tical console.1 The DS can be taken as an instance of issues that emerge from the integrated examination of screen, application, and use. The DS is a mobile dispositif: a screening arrangement that encompasses both the positioning of the screen’s user and the physical set-up for interactive interfacing by the screen’s use. Its mobility is multiple – a mobility of screen, user, and image – and raises questions about the mobile screen as related to movement, touch, and the process of spatial transformation. To demonstrate the usefulness of this take on a somewhat banal object such as the Nintendo DS, I will zoom in on three of its features that make up its particular mobility – the mobility of the screen, the touch control of the screen, and the doubling or multiplicity of the screen – to explore the range of historical and theoretical questions that emanate from that mobility.

A new gadget Even though the screen features of the DS (Dual Screens) are central in the con- sole’s marketing campaign, the use of a multiscreen format is not new for Nin-

210 digital material tendo gaming devices. A clamshell case was already used in the Game & Watch series (1980-1991). There are, however, some important differences between ear- lier portable games and the DS console. Firstly, the Game & Watch series offered single games – of which Donkey Kong is perhaps the best known – rather than operating as a platform for multiple games on interchangeable game cartridges, as does the DS. A second difference is that the screens of these older games were partly pre- printed with both a foreground and background setting. These preprints situated the versatile on-screen game characters within a fixed spatial environment. More- over, the double screens offered only one possibility: the player was able to move the game characters from one screen to the other, creating a linear spatial conti- nuity between the two screens. On the DS the two screen spaces can be related to each other in a variety of ways in each game. Thirdly, the user controls the lower screen by touch. The touch screen is oper- ated by a fundamentally different kind of ‘handling’ than the traditional button controls for the upper screen. Rather than a singular object, as a console, the DS is a platform of a whole array of games that each provides different applications of the dual screens and the touch screen capabilities.2 This dual-screen element gives the company’s advertisers an argument to en- hance newness. On the Nintendo DS consumer service website, the producers stress that the letters DS, in addition to being an abbreviation for Dual Screens, have another meaning: ‘[t]o our developers, it stands for “Developers” System’, since we believe it gives game creators brand new tools which will lead to more innovative games for the world’s players.’3 In spite of the obvious rhetoric of hyperbole deployed to accentuate innovation and global scale, the producers do have a point. The two-screen features that distinguish this console from other portable, hybrid or convergent game systems such as Sony’s PSP (PlayStation Por- table) or Nokia’s N-Gage invite newly designed games or modifications of older games. Conversely, these games explore the particular possibilities of the DS screens. Moreover, with the double screens, different screen functions converge. Read the combination of the following statements from the Nintendo website, for ex- ample:

With Nintendo DS, dual screens and touch-screen technology allow you to interact with games like never before. Wireless communication allows you to experience real-time multiplayer game play, while built-in PictoChat software gives you the power to draw, write and send messages wirelessly.

Two LCD screens offer one of the most groundbreaking gameplay advances ever developed. (…) In a racing game, you might see your own vehicle’s per- spective on one screen and an overall track view on the other. Soon, games grasping the screen 211 could be created allowing you to play games on one screen while sending text messages on the other.

The lower screen offers something never before provided by any dedicated game device: touch-screen capabilities. You no longer have to rely on just but- tons to move your character or shift perspectives. Navigate menus or access inventory items simply by touching the screen with a stylus or fingertip.4

These statements each foreground precisely the different aspects I intend to focus on: a vision of what the screen is, what we can do with screens, and what makes a particular screen-based device stand out as new. They address the temporality, the real-time aspect of communication through wireless connectivity and touch- screen interaction; the spatial multiplication when they speak of multiple perspec- tives enabled and visualized by the double screens; and practice, with the sugges- tion of more intuitive interaction with the screen by direct touch. In addition to that analysis of newness, the quoted passages bring us closer to a triple theoretical point the DS makes concerning the status of the gadget as object. The gadget as object is material. Moreover, a screen-based gadget is tem- poral as well as temporary, or ephemeral. Therefore, the status of the gadget in the history of media is at issue. This status is both comparative and historical, concerning synchronic differentiations and confluence, as well as transformation over time. Herein lies its historical status. Lastly, the gadget’s functionality is deter- mined by the way any screen-based object embodies possibilities of multiple in- terfaces. This is why such multifaceted objects should be considered theoretical consoles rather than theoretical objects (singular). The issues the gadget raises offer a constellation of concepts for use in media history and theory together. The first issue raised is one of method: how can we study it from a media- archeological perspective? Within media history, a gadget is a commercial and vernacular technological object that is designed as an interface and platform for multimedia applications. Its market value is primarily determined by its innova- tive character, its newness. Paradoxically, however, its innovation is recognizable through its similarity to other, previously marketed gadgets. The fact that we speak of generations of mobile phones, mobile game consoles, or media players indicates this assumption of a family resemblance and a lineage among gadgets. More specifically, a gadget is a small, pocket-sized, handheld object designed for individual, daily use. Its status lies somewhere between practical tool, fun object, and shiny piece of technology. As Lev Manovich stresses, it is also an aesthetic object in which such different functions and meanings converge as ‘friendly, play- ful, pleasurable, aesthetically pleasing, expressive, and fashionable; signifying cultural identity, and designed for emotional satisfaction’ (2006, 1). As a technological moment the gadget provides a historical anchoring of tech- nology. In this in-between-ness of the gadget – between apparatus, device and

212 digital material appliance – a convergence becomes visible. Convergence is a useful notion to account for the other side of history, namely the momentary synthesis of a parti- cular moment, a synchronic slice of time where different issues, possibilities and desires come together. Here, the convergence is the synthesis of media technolo- gies and therefore of media uses. However, in the case at hand the issue is not that different technologies come together in one appliance, but that a singular constellation of technologies emerges in one console. This mixture offers a plat- form – console – for a whole array of possibilities for the gadget’s applications. It is not a singular medium; it is, rather, a composite, a convergence of screen para- digms within a single dispositif. Therefore, the features of the screen that both converge and transform in this apparatus bind synchrony to diachrony and thus em- body its status as theoretical console. This warrants a closer look at the many- sided screen of the DS: the touch screen, the mobile screen, and the double screen.

Touch screen The first element in this convergence of screen paradigms is touch. The haptic element of touch screens primarily meant for viewing inflects the notion – and action – of viewing itself. This haptic form of ‘viewing’ bears consequences for the way the screen enables the viewer/user to virtually travel through the screen. This feature is, again, both new and old. This traversing has a long-standing sta- tus as metaphor for screen-based viewing. The idea, or conceptual metaphor, of moving through has been dominant in our way of perceiving how visual screen media work. Seeing has a longstanding cultural meaning metaphorically expressed in the window. Not coincidentally, the Nintendo DS promotes itself in the terms of ‘thing theorist’ Bill Brown – as a dirty window: A boy approaches the dirty rear windows of a van and writes ‘GO’ with his fingers, upon which the van drives away. This short evocative clip speaks of the main feature of the touch screen technology: like on a dirty window, on the touch screen we can write commands. The analogy between a dirty window and touch screen, here deployed as a visual comparison, suggests two directions in which to consider the two elements. From window to touch screen, it says both simplicity and general availability. From touch screen to window, the clip suggests a sense of magic conferred upon the everyday; things will happen when we touch the opaque glass shield. Far from being transparent, the screen becomes, emphati- cally, a thing. The comparison between the screen and the window, so utterly commonplace, demonstrates what is at stake here. When a window is dirty, is it the window we actually see: it is the impossibility of seeing through the window, its opacity, that marks its presence as a thing. This is how Bill Brown explains what he calls grasping the screen 213 thingness. He refers to a novel by A.S. Byatt: ‘the interruption of the habit of looking through windows as transparencies enables [Byatt’s] protagonist to look at a window in itself in its opacity’ (Brown 2004, 4).

When the screen functions as a transparent window, it is invisible as an object. When it is opaque, its materiality or thingness, surfaces. This paradox of non- functionality that correlates to visibility and thingness is particularly intriguing in the case of the screen. Unlike the window, the operation of this screen necessi- tates opaqueness for virtual transparency: it needs the surface to reflect the images on the screen. Heidi Rae Cooley also invokes the difference between the screen as transparent window and the screen as opaque surface. Cooley defines what she calls tactile vision, a vision ‘activated by the hand’ and ‘a material and dynamic seeing involv- ing eyes as well as hands and a MSD [mobile screenic device]’ (2004, 137). With this term she does not refer to touch-screen technology in a strict sense, but to the more general manual ‘handling’ of mobile screens – the ‘touched-screen’ as we may call this broader category. Tactile vision, according to Cooley, is based on the principle of the fit: ‘the particular relationship between a hand and a MSD, which opens onto a relation of interface through which vision becomes and re- mains tactile’ (ibid., 137). While Cooley rightly argues for a tactile notion of interfacing, I would derive a stronger point from this tactility. The haptic nature of the touch screen technol- ogy transforms the practice of screening; it foregrounds the temporal collapse be- tween making and viewing images. Using the screen of the DS is a physical and performative activity. Viewing is no longer a matter of perceptually receiving images. It entails movements with the hand that holds the stylus. There are no images prior to the moment the user conjures them up by touch. This simultane- ity of touching, making, and viewing connects the viewing experience to the live- ness of television, and to the physical and creative experience of drawing. This temporal aspect is clear in the ad, where looking and doing occur at the same moment – are, in fact, one act. The activity, or performance, of making shifts the focus from receptivity to production. As part of a body that can move around, the hand that touches the screen of the DS gadget can also take the gadget to different places. I turn now to the mobility that results from this aspect as a second, fundamentally new, yet also continuous aspect of the gadget. As I argue below, multiple takes on mobility – of device, screen, and user – can be brought to bear on the particular touch screen interface.

Mobile screen As a handheld device the DS can be taken anywhere. The portability of the device makes it a mobile medium but because of its pocket size also a very individual

214 digital material one. Yet, as stressed in the marketing of the DS, sharing is part of the fun – of its social ecology. Sharing concerns the way the mobile screen as a handheld object can be passed around, a mobility not of space only, but also a mobility of use and even property. Although mobile gadgets are often also called ‘personal electronic devices’, the DS ad campaign explicitly targets connectivity, communal play, and media use. Consider the following commercial for the DS, called Gravy. Five young people in a restaurant play with their food. Shots of them seem to be unrelated, until we understand that they are, in fact, connected, communicating with each other. ‘Game?’ is the question a boy writes in a pool of gravy on his plate. ‘I’min,’ a girl writes on her frosted glass. This commercial plays with a magical idea, especially appealing to children who hate to be forced to finish their dinner. The medium, enabling the bored child to break his solitude, allows what can be called space- binding – the particular characteristic of televisual connections between spaces that fundamentally alters the experience of time within a place, as Anna McCarthy has pointed out (2001, 74). This telewriting invokes the association with the mys- tic writing pad, which was also alluded to in the dirty-windows ad. There, the potential opaqueness visually was offered to the use of performative writing – the command that took immediate effect. Here, the magic of the mystic writing pad appears in the writable gravy.5 This is a form of ghost writing: someone else, invisible to you as if on the other side of the screen, makes things visible on your screen. The fact that someone else, who is elsewhere, manages your screen turns that screen into a shared space. The screen gains liveness, as the process of writing is simultaneous with viewing, like in live animation. This ad suggests that different perspectives and agencies run into one another on one single screen. Connectivity not only multi- plies screen space, it also turns multiple screens into one. The gadget is thus positioned as tool and as site for private, yet collective, mediation. In addition to the possibility of passing around the whole gadget, hence, the whole screen, the feature of connectivity enables another way of sharing. Through wireless connection the user/player can share screen space, simulta- neously in multiple-player games or alternately by sending messages. Screen space is something else than, literally, the space of the hand that holds the screen. Instead, the experience of space can be considered in terms of a spatial continuity of eyes, hand, screen, and screened space. In response to earlier screen technolo- gies, the mobility of the gadget is therefore perhaps best understood as the spatial extension not beyond the screen (into the screened space) but in front of the screen (between eye and screen). More intimate than a distant screen, more indi- vidual than a large screen, more intuitive than a separated screen, the handheld aspect of the mobile screen emphasizes the continuity between spaces. This brings me to another aspect of spatial continuity, namely the impact of time on space. Continuity is spatial but inevitably also temporal. Simultaneity and grasping the screen 215 the sharing of screen space is a way of temporalizing space. The gravy ad takes time and represents time: the time of boredom, and the time in which boredom is interrupted by the initiative to play. This is why media of mobility are so attractive: they play with and naturalize the time-space continuum. Continuity, and in its wake sharing, are not only clarifying but also mystifying terms. They suggest a social advantage, an overcoming of individualism and lone- liness. When speaking of the ‘bi-located psyche’ of the player, Parikka and Suo- minen (2006) point out how this discourse of connectivity does not disrupt the traditional separation between public and private domains. Instead, this discourse expands on another trope, namely that of virtual mobility. Sharing and connectiv- ity concern transport. Space itself is transported: the expansion of space through the media device, whether or not with clean windows, allows the player to do something else, somewhere else. Thus, the mobility of the device comes to stand for the mobility of the medium. It follows that mobility operates on different levels: the mobility of the device, the mobility of the player/user, and the mobility between places and users. What is most significant for the mobile game console, then, is the way the mobility of the screen relates to the virtual mobility that the screen ‘images’. Drawing atten- tion to that double-edged mobility turns the console as gadget once more into a theoretical console. There is, however, a paradox at the heart of this mobility: that of the immobile spectator. Anne Friedberg has pointed out this paradox of the cinematic viewing arrangement in her thought-provoking analysis of screen media and their virtual mobility (2006). The virtual mobility of the medium is made possible precisely in the space between the immobile (cinema) viewer, the static screen or frame, and the mobility of the images on screen. In the case of the DS, the spectator is a player, a user, and is physically engaged when using the console. The touch screen is screen and controller in one and requires physical action, and such action entails movement. But movement is not mobility; moving one’s hand is not the same as moving around. This brings me, once more, to the ‘old’ aspect of this gadget. The immobility of the spectator is required for the classical screen, of which the film screen is the paradigmatic example. The newness resides in the fact that mobile screens not only allow, po- tentially, for mobility of both body and screen, they also position the mobility of the body within a number of relationships. The DS embodies an aspect of new- ness it shares with many other contemporary gadgets. This further develops its status as a theoretical console. As Ingrid Richardson argues, they set up a distinc- tive relationship between body, screen/technology, and environment/space:

The idea that embodiment is possible relies largely on the supposition that our engagement with screen media requires a stationary body, such that one’s awareness of the corporeal recedes. Yet, as I have suggested mobile media

216 digital material complicate this relation, and facilitate a physical mobility of the body, whether pedestrian or vehicular, partially returning one’s attention to physical location and the navigation within and around the material environment (2005, np).

This mobility is most emphatically demonstrated in the case of navigation screens. There, our literal being in the world, our physical occupation of space and the inherent coordinates, make on-screen navigation possible. Therefore, we are becoming familiar with the principle that not only the body can become mo- bile, but that it has to move in order for the screen to function.6 This mobility is similar to the movement of the avatar as a representation of the player on the screen of racing games. In those cases the cars even represent the vehicle, which virtually transports the player through the virtual space of the ra- cing track. There is a difference here. The navigation of the screen itself – in the hands of the user or in the car/vehicle that transports both user/viewer and device/ screen –‘pulls’ the avatar through the represented space on the screen of the navigation device. In contrast, the movement of buttons, finger or stylus ‘pushes’ the avatar across the screen space in the case of racing games. All these aspects of mobility over-determine the simple but significant fact that the gadget itself, as a thing, can be transported wherever the user wishes to go. It is pocketsize, handheld, and lightweight. This mobility could not even be imag- ined in the days of old media. But clearly, this mobility of the thing qua thing is only the outer shell of something of which the mobility is multiple and constantly shifting. The fascination, in the end, is with mobility as such, old and new. As it provides us a freedom within space-time that no longer holds us but that we, as owner of this gadget, can hold, it is new in relation to the old. Rather than a screen-window through which we can look outside, the gadget is like a remote control for the subject itself. Like a pocket teleporter, it transports us while being on the move.

Double screen In combination with the tactile and the mobile screen, the DS raises the stakes of screen technology through the doubling of the screen. It doubles the screen not only literally, by offering two related screens that split up screen space, but also conceptually, thus thickening its potential as a theoretical console even more. As a material site for interfacing, the screen can be multiplied. This can be done in order to combine different interfaces. This is how the screen has become a con- vergent medium. Looking at the DS, the clamshell case not only makes closing the screens possible, but also divides them: splitting up single-screen space into two separate screens. Again, theoretical implications cross historical ones, as the newness meets its past.

grasping the screen 217 Figure 2: Simultaneous screens of Mario Kart DS, a racing game for the DS (Courtesy of Nintendo Benelux)

218 digital material Obviously, screens within screens, or perhaps more appropriately, frames within frames have a longer history than Nintendo’s invention. Split screens, inserts, mise-en-abymes: we have seen it all in cinema – and before that in painting. Yet the primary difference here is the aspect of navigation. In her section on multiple frames and screens, Anne Friedberg has pointed out how the digital, multiple screen allows for multitasking. This implies a temporal simultaneity of different activities in parallel spaces (2006, 233). Following the historical metamorphoses of the screen, which Friedberg helps us to investigate, a temporal and spatial doubling of multiple screens is perhaps the most significant newness of the digi- tal screen. In this vein, I focus here on the fractured, yet connected, spatial ar- rangement of screen-based activity; the exploring of or navigating within one screen space, for example, which results in a representation of that process in another space. Through its multiple screens – material screens, in the case of the DS, not just multiple frames within the larger frame of a single screen – the DS makes con- nections between multiple (virtual) spaces but also to multiple interfaces possible; and it makes that possibility visible. The games developed for the DS explore these possibilities for double vision. One of the clearest cases of related interfaces is that of racing games. Since the early days of racing games we have known the screen insert with a little map of the racing track in the upper or lower corner of the frame. These maps show little arrows, or avatars that resemble the cars that are driven in the game. On the larger screen we see a first-person perspective from a car on the racetrack. These representations are excellent examples of what Michel De Certeau (1984) calls map and tour paradigms. While tours are visual narratives, maps are visual abstractions of space. These two forms of space-making announce what double screens make possible. De Certeau was talking about traditional cartography, but in the case of interactive digital maps, shifting perspectives and navigation on screen are at issue. The virtual movements of the avatar on screenic maps allow for a haptic navigation – navigation based on the transfer of physical movement to another spatial realm. When the navigator moves, the avatar moves along. The continuity between spaces makes navigation between the converged mapping paradigms possible. This is what the DS demonstrates, proposing for our reflec- tion the implications of mapping according to De Certeau, the way these implica- tions respond to the old cartographies, and to what extent the newness, with all its rhetoric of sharing, truly innovates the ecology of screen technology.7

Console As a theoretical console, the Nintendo DS offers us insight into the mobile screen as gadget where history and theory cross. As an instance of commercial gadgetry, the object represents the state of the art of applied technology available for the grasping the screen 219 average consumer. Its commercial value lies in the discourse of an ever-moving or changing horizon of technological development. As Baudrillard put it in his criti- cal analysis of the system of fashionable objects, this discourse is even embedded in the technological make-up of the object itself (1996, esp. 115-138). In the ‘per- manent state of revolution’ of technology, it is the object that ‘speaks’ its ‘time’ (ibid., 9; emphasis in text). With its historical status it suggests the interrogation of the gadget as ‘speaking its time’ through its combination of recognizable ‘old’ and exciting ‘new’ features. Theoretically, it encourages the exploration of its possibilities as a console, a polymorphous ‘screenic’ platform for a variety of ap- plications and practices. When we separate the thing – the DS in its material form – from the object – the thing that asks us what it is – we create what in science is denoted by the term ‘theoretical object’: a temporary construction. The object – here a particular screenic device – is imagined, constructed, in order to interro- gate the meaning of the object that is theorized ‘about’. In addition to the many faces of the console, the specific characteristic of the portable system as a piece of technology, as hardware, the very materiality, its thingness, raises questions about the gadget status of the apparatus. As such, the gadget is more than an object: it is a tool for the user/player to do things with it. In this respect, the gadget as console is best understood as a thing, place, instru- ment and portal at the same time. Moreover, unlike other (portable) media players, a console is, in part, an empty interface. The software application deter- mines part of the interface, in dialogue with the hardware elements. The complex of characteristics of the portable console as a versatile object, a thing/medium, demands a theoretical grasp of the phenomenon. As a console it is, first, a material object (the device we hold in our hands). It is also a screen we look at as well as through, and a screen we touch. And thirdly, it is an interface utility, at once an invisible and visible platform – a machine for visual (and audio) output of the applications one can play on it. This interfacing function of screens is fundamentally, not coincidentally, imagined as a spatiotem- poral traversal. And traversal, to become concretely imaginable, takes the form of travel. Travel as a practice, then, becomes a theoretical trope. As trope, travel is a concrete and visualizable idea that harbors theoretical thoughts that a critic can engage in when analyzing objects. By the same token, things that are contem- plated as objects that embody such visual forms of travel can in turn be under- stood as theoretical objects. I have proposed that the DS can thus be considered as a theoretical object, but more specifically in this case, as a theoretical console. The difference between what is called a theoretical object and what I term a theoretical console is that between a thing, used and reflected upon as object, and a variety of practices performed through that thing – its ‘consoleness’.Asanobject, the DS Nintendo already raises questions and suggests ideas about the status, the limits and the possibilities of the screen. This turns the object as artefact into a theoretical ob-

220 digital material ject. As a console, it works as a dispositif that compels particular practices, and thus it complicates these questions.

Notes 1. For a more developed version of this argument, see my article in Journal of Visual Culture 8, 2 (forthcoming, August 2009). 2. Digitally animated and interactive games are not the only applications for the DS. An Internet browser, movie and music players and e-book readers have been developed, both by Nintendo, third-party commercial producers, as well as by consumers who produce so-called homebrew applications. 3. http://www.nintendo.com/consumer/systems/ds/faq.jsp. 4. http://www.nintendo.com/overviewds. 5. About Freud’s essay on the mystic writing pad as metaphor for memory and the rela- tionship with screen time, see Mary Ann Doane (1996; 2002). In a slightly different vein, Maureen Turim considers the children’s toy Etch-a-Sketch as a pre-digital Wunder- block (1999, 49). Thanks to Ann-Sophie Lehmann for bringing this essay to my atten- tion. 6. Elsewhere (2008), I have argued about separate, yet connected spaces of navigation devices, that the on-screen representation of navigation is, in fact, the means for navi- gating off-screen space. This simultaneous onscreen and offscreen navigation can be conceptualized as the construction of screen space: a hybrid space between onscreen and offscreen space. 7. On De Certeau’s notion of space and maps, see also the essay by Sybille Lammes in this volume.

References Baudrillard, Jean. 1996. The system of objects. Translated by James Benedict. London, New York: Verso. Brown, Bill. 2004. Thing theory. In Thing, ed. Bill Brown, Chicago: The University of Chi- cago Press. Cooley, Heidi Rae. 2004. It’s all about the fit: The hand, the mobile screenic device and tactile vision. Journal of Visual Culture 3 (2): 133-155. Certeau, Michel de. 1984. The practice of everyday life. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Doane, Mary Anne. 2002. The emergence of cinematic time: Modernity, contingency, the archive. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Doane, Mary Ann. 1996. Temporality, storage, legibility: Freud, Marey, and the cinema. Critical Inquiry 22 (2), Winter: 313-343. Friedberg, Anne. 2006. The virtual window: From Alberti to Microsoft. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Manovich, Lev. 2006. Interaction as an aesthetic event. Receiver (17). http://www.vodafone. com/flash/receiver/17/articles/index09.html. McCarthy, Anna. 2001. Ambient television: Visual culture and public space. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

grasping the screen 221 Parikka, Jussi and Jaakko Suominen. 2006. Victorian snakes? Towards a cultural history of mobile games and the experience of movement. Game Studies 6 (1). http://gamestudies. org/0601/articles/parikka_suominen. Richardson, Ingrid. 2005. Mobile technosoma: Some phenomenological reflections on itinerant media devices. Fibreculture (6). http://journal.fibreculture.org/issue6/issue6_ri- chardson.html. Turim, Maureen. 1999. Artisanal prefigurations of the digital: Animating realities, collage effects, and theories of image manipulation. Wide Angle 21 (1): 49-62. Verhoeff, Nanna. 2008. Screens of navigation: From taking a ride to making the ride. Re- fractory: A Journal of Entertainment Media 11. http://blogs.arts.unimelb.edu.au/refractory/ 2008/03/06/screens-of-navigation-from-taking-a-ride-to-making-the-ride.

222 digital material Terra incognita

Computer games, cartography and spatial stories

Sybille Lammes

In this chapter I will examine computer games in which both mapping and spatial progress are important organizing principles. Games such as Age of Empires (1997- 2005), Rise of Nations (2003), and Civilization (1991-2005) invite the player to go on an imaginary expedition, where traveling through landscapes creates a story. Dur- ing this process maps and landscapes are mutable instead of fixed, changing ap- pearances according to where the player travels and what is being altered in en- vironments (e.g. mining, founding trading posts or towns, expanding borders). Right through this explorative journey, the player develops a spatial story with herself or himself as the main character as well as being an imaginary cartogra- pher who interacts with maps and changes them according to the spatial ad- vancements that are made. As I will show in this chapter, cartographical practices in such games augment the spatial awareness and reflection of players by inviting them to play with maps and change them according to their spatial advance- ments. Players themselves create spatial formations, thus generating a particular sense of place and space. To specify how the relationship between transformative cartography and spatial progress can be understood, I will approach them as spatial stories, a term that has been theorized by De Certeau (1984). Although I am aware of the fact that De Certeau is a nonconformist in how he uses terms such as space and place, his theories are pertinent to my argument because of the emphasis that he puts on the relation and oscillation between the map and tour when we create spatial stories.1 Clearly, in the games that are central to this chapter, mapping is combined with touring when moving through the game space. De Certeau’s theories, if used critically, can thus facilitate an understanding of how spatial stories are being developed in such games, and how maps function in this process. In this context it is particularly interesting to see how spatial stories in compu- ter games differ from conventional spatial stories, due to the use of digital instead of analogue mapping techniques. It has been often maintained that analogue maps – and space in general – have been ideologically constructed as fixed and

223 objective, while they are actually socially produced (Lefèbvre 1991; Massey 1994), ideologically coded (Harley 1988; Harley 1989; Wood 1992; Crampton 2001; Wood 2002) and one of the main institutions for national states to ‘imagine’ their power (Anderson 1991). De Certeau’s argument – written in the pre-digital era – also hinges on the fact that analogue maps are frozen representations. Hence, he maintains, a friction occurs between the personal and dynamic way in which peo- ple experience traveling through space in daily life and how maps (and other techno-scientific representations of space) represent environments as unchange- able and abstract. Since the digital maps under scrutiny in this chapter have lost such preset qualities, this argument needs critical reconsideration. The mutability of the digital maps that the player can manipulate prompts questions about how and to what extent spatio-cultural meanings shift when maps become more alter- able. Another reason why De Certeau offers an appealing perspective to study these games is because he speaks of spatial stories as practices (Thrift 2004). Although his writings are very much indebted to a semiotic tradition, he no longer defines stories as conventional narrative structures with a predetermined outcome and determinable positions of reader and narrator. Instead he speaks of spatial stories as performative acts in which the traveler becomes the story-maker. This is a highly important notion when trying to understand mapping and spatial progress in these games, or in fact any digital game. As has been amply discussed before, the player of a game cannot simply be theorized as a reader of or listener to a story as text, but is rather engaged in playful spatial practices through which per- sonal stories are being developed (Juul 2001; Ryan 2002; Kücklich 2003; Jenkins 2004; Murray 2005; Frasca 2005; Jenkins 2005). De Certeau’s approach offers the means to deal with games as stories, yet at the same time acknowledging their simulative and interactive qualities and the agency of the player.

Stories as playgrounds Surely the fact that De Certeau’s theories open up possibilities to look at stories in interactive terms is one of the reasons that the notion of spatial stories has so often been applied to computer games. It was especially an article by cultural theorist Henry Jenkins and literary historian Mary Fuller, Nintendo® and new world travel writing: A dialogue, that set this trend. Jenkins asserts in this article that Nin- tendo games, and even new media as a whole, may be perceived as spatial stories. He observes that games and other digital expressions can be best described in such terms because players primarily construct a narrative by traveling through space (Fuller and Jenkins 1995). Friedman took this idea on board in his writing about the game Civilization, presenting it as a suitable concept for understanding simulation games in which the player re-enacts and gives shape to history through the mastery of landscape (Friedman 1999).

224 digital material Jenkins’s and Friedman’s views have since been the touchstone for many sub- sequent academic writings on games (Douglas 2002; Poblocki 2002; Lammes 2003; Newman 2004; Magnet 2006). Following the authors’ example, they mostly refer to the difference that De Certeau made between space and place, and be- tween the map and the tour, and apply these dichotomies to games. Places and maps are then perceived as abstract, timeless and stable. Space and tours, on the other hand, are seen as concrete, known and changeable and part of a more per- sonal spatial experience. In the following section I will first briefly re-visit De Certeau’s writings on these four concepts, since they are often referred to in a rather condensed or even eroded way. I will move on to discuss how his vocabulary has been used in rela- tion to games so far, and how it could be relevant to comprehend the cartogra- phical practices figuring in the games central to this chapter. Additionally, I will argue that De Certeau’s understanding of boundaries should be more explicitly added to this quartet to come to a better understanding of how these games treat spatial borders.

De Certeau re-visited In The practice of everyday life (1984), De Certeau dedicates a chapter to the working of spatial stories. Unlike some ludologist game researchers, who would claim that games are in essence non-narrative (Frasca 2003, 2005; Juul 2004, Aarseth 2004), spatial stories are everywhere according to De Certeau. Not only do we need them to make sense of everyday life; stories are the central organizing principle for all human activity and are especially important when trying to come to grips with spatial change: ‘[E]very day, they traverse and organize places. (...) They are spa- tial trajectories’ (De Certeau 1984, 115). To understand how such spatial stories take shape, he makes the aforemen- tioned distinction between space and place and map and tour, two concepts I will explain here in more detail.

The most important difference between place (‘lieu’) and space (‘espace’) is that the first term is about stability and an ordered configuration of elements, whilst the latter rather implies mobility and has a ‘polyvalent’ character. Place refers to the ‘proper’ order, to the way spatial positions are related in an objective account, whilst space is about how we deal with spatiality as ‘a practiced place’. To explain the difference, De Certeau gives the example of walking the streets of a city. The geometrical configuration of the streets he equates with place, while the act of traversing these streets changes them into space. Thus, place is set and univocal, while the notion of space has as many meanings as there are walkers (De Certeau 1984, 117).

terra incognita 225 De Certeau speaks of both terms as constantly influencing each other. He iden- tifies place as having the purpose to create static and lifeless objects. Space, on the other hand, presupposes a subjective purpose. It implies movement and change. In stories, these two determinations should be understood as in constant fluctuation in which a lifeless, objective, abstract place can become an animated and changeable, concrete space. Conversely, space can also be consolidated into place (De Certeau 1984, 117-21). De Certeau introduces the difference between the map and the tour as a means to distinguish the different modes of the interplay of space and place in one of the most basic travel stories, namely spatial descriptions. From a study of how resi- dents experience their apartments, he learned that the majority of people describe their dwellings in terms of moving about, and that only a small minority uses terms of seeing to explain how their apartments look. De Certeau links the latter to the notion of the map. A map can be described as a static representation of the world we live in. It objectifies spatial relations. The moving mode he relates to the notion of the tour. Touring is a dynamic principle that is subjective, since the point of view of the traveler is central. According to De Certeau these two concep- tions of spatiality are both incongruous dimensions of contemporary culture. While being confronted with a static representation of the world we live in, we sense our space in a dynamic and more personal way. Just like place and space, maps and tours necessitate one another and come into being through a reciprocal movement. Even more so as a map always presupposes a tour; one first needs to go somewhere to give an objective spatial account of it (De Certeau 1984, 117-21).

Map/Space Tour/Place

Objective Subjective ‘Scientific’ Personal Abstract Concrete Fixed Dynamic

Table 1: De Certeau’s spatial distinctions

Although these concepts are in essence intertwined, maps have become more and more separated from the experience of tours in Western cultures. On medieval maps, where the itineraries themselves are basic and the emphasis lies on how long it would take to travel and where to stop, their interaction is still clearly discernable. But gradually the traces of the tours, which permitted the making of maps, were erased, and maps became more formal and abstract. Today, De Cer- teau states, we have to deal with this ‘isolated (...) system of geographical places’ (ibid., 121) while simultaneously experiencing space as an ongoing and mobile practice. Everyday stories help to make sense of such frictions: ‘they are treat- ments of space’ (ibid.).

226 digital material New world dialogues In the aforementioned dialogue between Jenkins and Fuller, Jenkins uses the writ- ings of De Certeau to situate Nintendo games in the realm of popular entertain- ment. Additionally, his dialogue with Fuller is aimed at comparing the treatment of space and place in Nintendo games with earlier Anglo-Saxon writings on the ‘discovery’ of new lands. Consequently, an interesting picture emerges of the ima- gination of space as a popular discourse, one that is closely related to the Amer- ican myth of the Wild West and new frontiers. Jenkins finds that De Certeau’s ideas on spatial stories are very apt for explain- ing imaginary spatial quests as stories. According to Jenkins Nintendo games are spatial stories because they cannot be easily defined in terms of an intricate plot or character. The story mainly develops by moving through landscapes, while the plot remains relatively simple (Fuller and Jenkins 1995; Jenkins 2004). When applying De Certeau’s distinction between place and space to Nintendo games, Jenkins relates place to the code that presupposes the game, while space ‘happens’ at the moment that the code is in the hands of the player who creates an imaginary landscape that is both personal and mobile. He then compares the paper maps that are supplied with the game to De Certeau’s medieval maps, in which descriptions are less isolated from the tour that they facilitate because they supply descriptions of how to move through the game. The assessment that Jenkins makes about the use of paper maps is of course pertinent and intriguing. Yet I would argue that maps can also be found within the games themselves, and that these maps are even less isolated than the quasi- medieval maps of which Jenkins speaks. Ted Friedman believes that the use of maps in simulation games like Civilization III (1996) differs from Jenkins’s analysis (1999). According to Friedman, such games are more about inviting the player to become a mapmaker. Interestingly, Friedman maintains that the landscape through which the player travels has car- tographical qualities: when playing the game one identifies with the environment (a spatial practice) in a more abstract sense, because one constantly sees the land- scape from above. Through this bird’s-eye view, the player is fixed in a deperso- nalized frame of mind. So a story can be developed without ever bringing it to the level of individual experience. The map therefore is not merely the environment for the story; it’s the hero of the story. Thus, Friedman concludes that the player has a less subjective identification with the visited landscape, and that space is experienced as mapping. Although the observation about the cartographical disposition of landscapes in simulation games is highly relevant, it needs some reconsideration. When Fried- man states that the map becomes the protagonist of the story, with whom the player identifies, he overlooks a pivotal quality of any game: in the end, it is al- ways the player who is the hero (or the loser). Games are not pre-set texts with terra incognita 227 pre-set heroes, but interactive forms of expression. Because the player’s actions are vital to the outcome of a game, a different identification process emerges in which a map cannot be a protagonist. It is rather the player who dynamically fluctuates between being a cartographer and being a traveler. Therefore, simula- tion games offer more than a frozen ideological representation of space, they allow us to spatially transform environments.

Figure 1: Screenshot from Sid Meier’s Civilization IV (Firaxis Games 2005)

As such, identification in simulation games takes place on an even more spatial level than in the Nintendo games. Instead of touring with an avatar on foot (vir- tual), the player is constantly involved in mapping the space that he creates by touring with a bird’s-eye view. This literal overview informs a strong interplay between mapping and touring, and the gamer is constantly and explicitly involved in making his own space, translating that into places and vice versa. The stories thus created, liberate maps from the isolated, unchangeable and static form they have gained since the Renaissance. They bring maps back (in)to life. Friedman’s argument also needs to be adjusted to the rapidly changing game- play. Nowadays games like Civilization heavily depend on the use of so-called mini-maps. Although the environment that the player watches and masters from above has certainly cartographical qualities, the use of mini-maps in recent strat- egy games adds a new layer. While environments of touring obtain cartographical

228 digital material features and become somewhat de-personalized, mini-maps develop into more subjective playgrounds. I would like to explain this by looking at the use of mini-maps in the game Age of Empires III (AOE). Here, the player is in a constant flux of moving through terri- tory, which is translated into an expansion (filling in) of the mini-map (left corner of fig. 3). Conversely, one can click on the mini-map to move to an area on the big screen. It is even possible to click on the figure of the explorer on the main screen, go back to the mini-map, click on the area he is to be sent to and subse- quently move him to that spot on the main screen. Through these actions, map- ping and touring entertain a highly dynamic relationship, which somewhat com- plicates Friedman’s claim that the player simply becomes a cartographer as opposed to a tour-maker. The player indeed becomes a mapmaker, but this can- not be described as a depersonalized endeavour. It would be more precise to call the player a cartographer on tour.

Figure 2: Screenshot from Age of Empires III (Ensemble Studios 2005)

Certainly, strategy games are the pinnacle of what De Certeau defines as spatial stories, precisely because spatial exploration is so central to them and is not hin- dered by plot or avatar. But it no longer suffices to maintain that they give the player the opportunity of understanding space as a map. Contemporary strategy games make such interesting spatial stories because they elicit a constant inter- play between the static and the mobile, the subjective and the objective. terra incognita 229 Rendering spatial categories fluid, these games actually seem to undermine De Certeau’s argument that maps and tours have become separated realms in Wes- tern cultures. Even the activities of looking and walking De Certeau assigns to mapping and touring, respectively, become less distinct. In the example I just mentioned, looking and exploring have become inseparable processes and the oscillation between them is actually a crucial part of the game play: maps are not only transformable, but become places one can go to, while landscapes that are toured acquire cartographical qualities and become observable.

Stories and boundaries Contemporary strategy games are not only unusual spatial stories because they entail a breakdown of the map as a means of seeing and tour as a way of going. They also accentuate two other objects important to De Certeau’s definition of spatial story, namely the frontier and the bridge. De Certeau argues that stories perform an important function in everyday life by setting limitations. By describing space, they arrange and order cultural do- mains. As such they not only set limits but also alter boundaries: ‘one can see that the primary function is to authorize the establishment, displacement or transcendence of limits’ (De Certeau 1984, 123). To describe this paradoxical quality of boundaries, he distinguishes two narrative figures in every story that have the power to fix boundaries and to revise them, namely the frontier and the bridge, respectively. In explaining the figure of the frontier, De Certeau takes his reader on an ety- mological tour to prove that stories are ways of creating borders. If more scat- tered now than before, the ‘primary role of stories’ has always been to function as a playground for actions after their formation as a delineated domain. Such actions can nevertheless also transgress the limits that are first set by the story (e. g. feudal conflicts in which set borders are contested). As such, boundaries are the prerequisite for any social practice. In this process the figure of the frontier and the bridge entertain a paradoxical relationship (De Certeau 1984, 118). In De Certeau’s vocabulary the frontier should be equated with ‘legitimate’ do- mains, since it creates spatial formations such as nations and empires. The bridge, on the other hand, points to what is not part of that area, in other words to ‘its (alien) exteriority’, such as other nations, unconquered territories or no- man’s lands. The frontier has a mediating or ‘bridging’ quality because it is the point of contact between the two entities it separates. In itself it does not belong to either entity (De Certeau 1984, 126-28). Frontiers are in that sense twilight zones. Strategy games explicitly ask the player to mark off land and to create borders and transgress them in an interactive way. A player has to deal with at least two different kinds of borders at once: the border between filled-in territory and the

230 digital material undiscovered black space on screen, and the borders between his own territory and that of others. Interestingly, games like AOE foreground the bridging quali- ties of borders. Since continuous spatial transgression is so central to such games, borders have gained a semi-permeable quality. They are always crossings to ‘otherlands’ and never presented as hard and definite lines. In Civilization IV (Figure 3) for example, the player’s territory spreads like liquid over a surface.

Figure 3: Screenshot from Sid Meier’s Civilization IV (Firaxis Games 2005)

Certainly, the map that has to be filled in has preset limits on what Jenkins calls the level of code (1995). Yet the demarcations of the player’s own territory appears rather fuzzy on screen. In AOE it is presented by different colours for different nations, and in Civilization IV by an opaque line that is drawn around the ‘zone of influence’. While the player is involved in a constant process of defining and ex- panding his territory, others will try to diminish the playroom or push back the borders. This element of bridging should be seen in the light of the interactive quality of games. Because the player is able to draw and transcend boundaries and can be interactively involved in creating a spatial story, the emphasis lies on the passing of borders. Players become enactors instead of tellers of spatial stor- ies, trying to develop a story by pushing spatial limits.

terra incognita 231 Digital mapping Although it has been suggested that games offer us digital playgrounds to express our daily spatial experience of living in an overcrowded world with fewer and few- er places to play outside (Fuller and Jenkins 1995; Friedman 1999), sticking to such a basic explanation of the socio-spatial function of cartographies would not do justice to the games discussed here. Jenkins places Nintendo games in the same league with early , pulp fiction and imaginary quests like Alice in Wonderland where stories also devel- op through the exploration of unknown territory while plot and character are less important. He also draws a parallel with playground attractions such as the roll- ercoaster. Like such attractions, Nintendo games offer the recreational sensation of sightseeing. But in contrast to these attractions, they offer the participant the opportunity to interact and transform landscapes during touring. As Jenkins points out, such games are also part and parcel of a more wide- spread Western fascination with new world exploration. Although a nostalgia for being an explorer and cartographer who marks out ‘new’ territory has been pre- sent in, for example, travelogues and certain board games, the actual possibilities of making environments and maps have been limited (Fuller and Jenkins 1995). The discussed games are unique in that they offer players the potential of being an active explorer and mapmaker at once. Still, I would like to add, they involve not so much a spatial reproduction of being a new world explorer, but rather en- tail a transformation of past endeavours to map and conquer new lands. Being a new world traveler is not so much re-constructed, but rather transformed into a playful activity in which mastering space becomes more of a personal power struggle than an accurate historical reiteration of how spatial relationships have been shaped by external hegemonic forces (Lammes 2003). Games translate spa- tial hegemonies into play, thus necessarily changing them into something more personal and subjective. As players are given the ludic power to mark territories and empires, they can create their own (post)colonial tales by translating world histories into personal stories. Furthermore, strategy games should also be seen within a wider contemporary development that assigns new meanings and functions to cartography. With the emergence of new media, maps in general have changed drastically. Not only do they look rather different, also the way we use them has altered significantly. Old- er maps may have offered some possibilities of modification (e.g. adding notes), but today users have the opportunity to interrelate with maps whilst navigating. Be it an automated navigation system that alters its itinerary when the driver chooses to drive elsewhere, or a map in a computer game that is partly created by the player(s) during the game – maps have become less fixed and are co-produced by their users.

232 digital material The games discussed here are particular performances within this wider tech- noscientific network of digital cartographies. The Lithuanian writer Gailitis stated that with GPS technologies, ‘the subject becomes the object, and we are nothing more than our own remote control’ (Gailitis 2005, 479). Yet, as the above analysis has shown, computer games differ from GPS devices in that they do not simply present us with an objectification of our personal whereabouts but actually over- come the one-directional transformation Gailitis stresses. They are for that matter more closely related to applications like Google Earth that also allows users to mix observant roles with subjective and personal experiences of space (e.g. The 21 Steps, Panoramio). As playful domains, they inspire gamers to appropriate spatial practices and make sense of them in their own way, hybridizing notions of objec- tive place and subjective space. It has been argued that new media have deprived us of a sense of spatial be- longing. Through their global and ubiquitous use and representations, they are believed to have created ‘geographies of nowhere’ instead (Eberle 1994; Kunstler 1994; Augé 1995). Yet this rather dystopian contention becomes problematic when one thinks of the increasing quantity of digital maps that we have to deal with. However diverse the purposes of individual technologies may be, they all point to an increasing involvement of users with their environments. As cartogra- phers on tour, players are engaged in a process that is targeted towards a perso- nal rather than a global or homogenous concept of spatiality. Such games do more than just ask a certain degree of spatial attentiveness from players to win the game. They invite them to create and transform maps and landscapes accord- ing to their individual choices. Gamers are thus actively exploring and transform- ing territories and maps in a highly personal, precise and even reflexive way. As such these games demonstrate that the global use of new media (and globaliza- tion in general) may have transformed our sense of belonging, but has not neces- sarily led to spatial homogenizations (Appadurai 2002). Our sense of place and space may indeed have changed but has not disappeared.

Note 1. For a related discussion of De Certeau’s concept in the context of portable gaming devices, see the chapter by Nanna Verhoeff. For an inverted use of the terms space and place, informed by a sociological approach, see the chapter by Ann-Sophie Lehmann.

terra incognita 233 References The 21 Steps. http://www.wetellstories.co.uk/stories/week1. Aarseth, Espen. 2004. Genre trouble: Narrativism and the art of simulation. In First person: New media as story, performance and game, eds. Noah Wardrip-Fruin and Pat Harrigan, 45- 47. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Age of empires series. Ensemble Studios, Microsoft Game Studios 1997-2005. Anderson, Benedict R. 1991. Census, map, museum. In Imagined communities: Reflections on the origin and spread of nationalism, 163-85. Rev. ed. London: Verso. Appadurai, Arjun. 2002. Disjuncture and difference in the global cultural economy. Theory, Culture & Society 7: 295-310. Augé, Marc. 1995. Non-places: Introduction to an anthropology of supermodernity. London: Verso. Certeau, Michel de. 1984. The practice of everyday life. Berkeley, London: University of Califor- nia Press. Civilization series. MicroProse, Koei, Firaxis Games, 2K Games & Aspyr 1991-2005. Crampton, Jeremy W. 2001. Maps as social constructions: Power, communication and vi- sualization. Progress in Human Geography 25 (2): 235-52. Douglas, Christopher. 2002. ‘You have unleashed a horde of barbarians!’ Fighting indians, playing games, forming disciplines. Postmodern Culture 13 (1). http://www3.iath.virginia. edu/pmc/issue.902/13.1douglas.html. Eberle, Gary. 1994. The geography of nowhere: Finding one’s self in the postmodern world. Kansas City: Sheed and Ward. Frasca, Gonzalo. 2005. Ludology meets narratology: Similitude and differences between (video) games and narrative. Ludology. http://www.ludology.org/articles/ludology.htm. —. Simulation versus narrative: Introduction to ludology. In The video game theory reader, eds. Mark J. P. Wolf and Bernard Perron, 221- 236. New York, London: Routledge. Friedman, Ted. 1999. Civilization and its discontents: Simulation, subjectivity, and space. In Discovering discs: Transforming space and genre on CD-ROM, ed. Greg Smith. New York: New York University Press. http://www.duke.edu/~tlove/civ.htm. Fuller, Mary, and Henry Jenkins. 1995. Nintendo® and new world travel writing: A dialo- gue. In Cybersociety: Computer-mediated communication and community, ed. Steven G. Jones, 57-72. Thousand Oaks: Sage. Gailitis, Viestarts. 2005. Milky way. In Making things public: Atmospheres of democracy, eds. Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel, 497-98. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Harley, J. Brian. 1989. Deconstructing the map. Cartographica 26 (2): 1-20. —. 1988. Maps, knowledge, and power. In The iconography of landscape: Essays on the symbolic representation, design and use of past environments, eds. Denis Cosgrove and Stephen Da- niels, 277-312. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jenkins, Henry. 2005. Computer and narrative. In Routledge encyclopedia of narrative theory, eds. David Herman, Manfred Jahn and Marie-Laure Ryan, 80-82. London: Routledge. —. 2004. Game design as narrative architecture. In First person: New media as story, perfor- mance, and game, eds. Noah Wardrip-Fruin and Pat Harrigan. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Juul, Jesper. 2001. Games telling stories. Game Studies, 1 (1) http://gamestudies.org/0101/ juul-gts.

234 digital material —. 2004. The Definitive history of games and stories, ludology and narratology. The ludolo- gist. http://www. jesperjuul.dk/ludologist/index.php. Kücklich, Julian. 2003. Perspectives of computer game philology. Game Studies 3 (1). http:// www.gamestudies.org/0301/kucklich. Kunstler, James Howard. 1994. The geography of nowhere: The rise and decline of America’s man- made landscape. New York: Simon and Schuster. Lammes, Sybille. 2003. On the border: Pleasures of exploration and colonial mastery in Civilization III Play the World.InLevel up: Digital games research conference, eds. Marinka Cop- ier and Joost Raessens, 120-29. Utrecht: Utrecht University. Lefèbvre, Henri. 1991. The production of space. Oxford: Blackwell. Magnet, Shoshana. 2006. Playing at colonization: Interpreting imaginary landscapes in the video game Tropico. Journal of Communication Inquiry 30 (2): 142-62. Massey, Doreen. 1994. Space, place, and gender. Cambridge: Polity Press. Murray, Janet H. 2005. The last word on ludology vs. narratology in game studies. Paper presented at the DiGRA 2005 Conference: Changing views of worlds in play. Newman, James. 2004. Videogames, space and cyberspace: Exploration, navigation and mastery. In Videogames, 107-26. London: Routledge. Panoramio. http://www.panoramio.com. Poblocki, Kacper. 2002. Becoming-state: The bio-cultural imperialism of Sid Meier’s Civili- zation. European Journal of Anthropology 39: 163-77. Rise of nations. Big huge games, Microsoft Game Studios 2003. Ryan, Marie-Laure. 2002. Beyond myth and metaphor: Narrative in digital media. Poetics Today 23 (4): 581-609. Thrift, Nigel J. 2004. Driving in the city. Theory, Culture & Society 21 (4/5): 41-59. Victoria: An empire under the sun. Paradox Interactive 2003. Wood, Dennis. 2002. The map as a kind of talk: Brian Harley and the confabulation of the inner and outer voice. Visual Communication 1 (2): 139-61. —. 1992. The power of maps. New York: Guilford Publications.

terra incognita 235

Keyboard

Conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere

Thomas Poell

On the morning of 2 November 2004, immediately after the assassination of the controversial Dutch film director Theo van Gogh by the young Dutch Moroccan Mohammed B., large numbers of people rushed to the Internet to share their grief, anger, insights, and opinions. On FOK!forum!, one of the largest web forums in the Netherlands, every minute several posts appeared. Most of them said little more than: ‘Goddammit!!!’, ‘jesus!!!!!!!!!!!!!’, ‘No! Fucking hell!’, and ‘let’s hope he’s still alive’. Later during the day, when the news spread that the assassin was Moroccan, the posts became more reflexive, but also more aggressive. For exam- ple, at a quarter past six in the evening, one message on FOK!forum! read: ‘however you look at it, it remains a POLITICAL MISTAKE. Repeatedly, it has been indi- cated that there are a lot of problems in this MULTICULTURAL society. But has anything ever been done? NO!!’. A few minutes later, someone responded by claiming: ‘Bull-shit, this involves one moron, who decided to kill someone be- cause of his ideas. There will always be such types.’1 How should this kind of online interaction be understood? Can it be inter- preted as fruitful public debate? Particularly two concepts, which are both norma- tive and descriptive, play an important role in the discussion on the influence of online communication on public debate. Firstly, inspired by Jürgen Habermas’s Structural transformation of the public sphere (1989; org. 1962), various new media scholars argue that the Internet can revive or extend the public sphere, as it is, con- trary to the traditional mass media, in essence an interactive medium. Following Habermas, most of these authors refer to the concept of the public sphere as a realm separate from political, religious, or economic interests, in which citizens articulate shared opinions through public debate (Benkler 2006, 176-178; Dahl- berg 2001; 2005; Knapp 1997; McNair 2006, 152-154; Rheingold 1993, 274-280). Secondly, in critical dialogue with the original Habermasian concept of the public sphere, other theorists maintain that the Internet is especially important because it facilitates the construction of multiple alternative or counter-public spheres. With this concept they allude to online communicative spaces in which social groups, which have no access to the mass media platform, can construct shared identities

239 and interests and coordinate public actions (Bennett 2004; Dahlgren 2001, 52-53; Downey and Fenton 2003, 198-199; Hacker and Van Dijk 2000; Poster 1995). So far, these concepts have primarily been used for general reflections on the relationship between online communication and public debate. This raises the question of whether they can also help us to understand the influence of particu- lar forms of online communication, that is, as medium-specific materializations. This chapter tries to answer this question by examining the role of Internet for- ums and blogs in the intense public discussions following the assassination of Theo van Gogh. It focuses on an actual social conflict because the medium-speci- fic characteristics of forums and blogs can be most clearly observed when the public and the various media are in a state of alert, and all focused on the same issue. The assassination of Theo van Gogh is particularly interesting from an analyti- cal point of view as it received an enormous amount of media attention and put the Netherlands, at least for a few days, in a state of . As the assassin was a young Dutch Moroccan, who claimed to have murdered Van Gogh for religious reasons, the discussions inevitably revolved around central democratic issues such as citizenship, , and the place of religion in a liberal de- mocratic society (see also Boomgaarden and De Vreese 2007; Hajer and Uiter- mark 2008; Pantti and Van Zoonen 2006). In previous years, Van Gogh himself had become an important figure in the debate over these issues, as he had fiercely criticized Muslim practices and beliefs as well as the multicultural politics of the central government, which promoted cultural diversity (Hajer and Uitermark 2008). For the evaluation of the two concepts, 51 blogs were investigated in the first three days after the assassination. A blog (short for web log) is a website, usually maintained by an individual, which has separately locatable entries, displayed in reverse chronological order. Most blogs offer the reader the opportunity to leave comments, which may be moderated or deleted by the blog owner. The 51 inves- tigated blogs effectively constitute all of the retrievable Dutch language blogs commenting on the assassination. Of these 51 blogs, 46 were found through Google Blog Search, which allows one to search specifically for blog posts written on a particular date. Yet, Google Blog Search is by no means perfect; a manual search revealed that a significant part of the most well-known Dutch blogs com- menting on the assassination was not available through Google Blog Search. Consequently, five extra blogs, among others the right-wing shocklog GeenStijl, were added to the selection. In addition, four Internet forums, covering the same time span, were exam- ined. An Internet forum is a dedicated web application facilitating asynchronous discussions, usually organized by user-created topics, and threads. All four inves- tigated forums were monitored by forum administrators, who have the authority to moderate and delete any thread and post on the forum. The four forums, Pim

240 digital material Fortuyn Forum, Indymedia, FOK!forum!, and Marokko Community, were chosen be- cause they each cover a specific region of the political and cultural landscape. The Pim Fortuyn Forum is one of the main populist right-wing forums. Indymedia is an international left-wing network of participatory journalists and activists, which offers activist news but also functions as a discussion platform. FOK!forum! is part of FOK!, which was originally focused on youngsters, but can now be considered as a general forum for everyone. Finally, the Marokko Community, which is part of the community site Marokko.nl, is the largest discussion platform for young Dutch Moroccans. The parent company, Marokko Media, maintains on its website that Marokko.nl has 45,000 unique visitors per day, which together post 50,000 mes- sages a day. It has been claimed that Marokko Community was frequented by Mo- hammed B. in the months before the assassination (Benschop 2005). In the days after the assassination, an unusual number of autochthon Dutch members were active on this forum. To assess how the relationship between the forums, blogs, and the traditional mass media can be interpreted, research was also done on the reporting of five major Dutch newspapers: De Telegraaf, Trouw, de Volkskrant, NRC Handelsblad, and Het Parool. These newspapers cover the entire spectrum of the mass press in terms of elitist versus populist, and right wing versus left wing. A selection of articles was made using a LexisNexis search for ‘Theo van Gogh’ for the first three days after the assassination. This search generated a total of 251 articles. Although this is by no means an exhaustive study of the mediated public dis- cussions following the assassination, it is sufficient for our meta-theoretical ob- jectives. It allows us to reflect on the way in which the concepts of public sphere and multiple public spheres can be used to understand the medium-specific con- tribution of forums and blogs to public debate. The first two sections of this chapter evaluate the notion of the public sphere, while the third part examines the concept of multiple public spheres.

Public sphere as critical rational debate Can the notion of the public sphere, as originally conceptualized by Habermas, be used to understand the specific contribution of Internet forums and blogs to pub- lic communication? Let us start with the forums. In principle, forums seem to be particularly equipped to facilitate inclusive, critical rational public debate, which, according to Habermas, forms the basis of a real public sphere (Habermas 1989). Forums enable everyone with an Internet connection to initiate and participate in public debate on a national or even international level. Moreover, as most forums allow the participants to make contributions under a nickname, they obscure many of the social markers which in offline discussions may unjustly benefit or discredit the opinions of speakers.

conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 241 Yet, if we examine the forum discussions in the aftermath of the assassination, most of them appear to be neither inclusive nor critical rational. The messages on FOK!forum! discussed in the introduction section are in this sense typical. The ma- jority of the posts simply expressed anger or sadness without much further reflec- tion. Politicians as well as other participants in the online debates were frequently called ‘idiots’, ‘suckers’, and ‘hypocrites’, while Muslims, or more specifically Muslim fundamentalists, were labeled ‘fascists’, ‘losers’, ‘murderers’, and ‘crim- inals’. It is important to note that most forum threads were dominated by small groups of five to ten participants. These observations are largely confirmed by various empirical studies on forum discussions, which consistently find that only a small proportion of forum partici- pants engage in public debate. It has been argued that most people use forums for entertainment or personal expression, rather than debate. Furthermore, re- search points out that when public discussion does evolve, it is far from rational and should rather be characterized as emotional and irreverent (Barber 1998; Da- vis 1999; Delli Carpini and Keeter 2003; Hurwitz 2004; Margolis and Resnick 2000). Particularly problematic from a Habermasian public-sphere perspective is that the public on the forums investigated here can be characterized as rather homo- geneous regarding ideology. The discussions on the FOK!forum!, and especially on the Pim Fortuyn Forum, were predominantly marked by the opinion that the assas- sination demonstrated that the multicultural politics of the government had failed, and that radical Muslims entail a grave danger to Dutch society. Most con- tributors on Indymedia, by contrast, asserted that the assassination was a symbol of the polarisation of societal relations to which Van Gogh had contributed heav- ily. Finally, on the Marokko Community relatively many participants argued that the assassination was the work of an individual madman and had little to do with religion. Hence, the respective forums were far from inclusive. This becomes par- ticularly evident when considering the reporting in the five national newspapers, which each provided a platform for a larger variety of opinions than could be heard on any of the forums. Taken together, the forum discussions clearly fall short of the criteria of the public sphere, as originally conceptualized by Habermas. There were, however, a few signs which showed that some of the forums were more favourable to critical rational public debate than others. In particular, Indymedia turned out to be a plat- form for more critical rational arguments. One of the participants on this forum, for example, extensively analyzed the role of the media in the aftermath of the assassination, which, according to her, should have been more critical of the role played by Van Gogh in the negative publicity on Islam and Dutch Moroccans in the previous years.2 Although these kinds of arguments subsequently evoked sev- eral emotional and aggressive reactions, even on Indymedia, they do indicate that at least some forums incidentally meet the norm of critical rationality.

242 digital material Also noteworthy were the discussions on Marokko Community, which were more inclusive than the ones on the other fora, as both critics and supporters of the multicultural society expressed their opinions here. For example, in a typical dis- cussion on Marokko Community, one member with the nickname aliyaah claimed: ‘When Theo van Gogh started to criticize the Jews, all doors were closed to him??? He was not allowed to practice anti-Semitism? And now that Muslims are put in the wrong by him, now there is … freedom of speech??’ Quickly someone else with the handle Peej responded by arguing: ‘Theo has criticized and ridiculed all religions (especially their orthodox parts). This happens to be allowed in the Netherlands, where the constitution and the penal code count as the legal frame- work, and not a few old religious books.’3 Even though the discussions on Indymedia and Marokko Community still do not meet the ideal of inclusive, critical rational debate, they do suggest that Internet forums can, under specific conditions, facilitate this ideal. The discussions on Marokko Community were more inclusive precisely because the enraged critics of the multicultural society sought the confrontation with Dutch Muslims, whom they held responsible for the assassination. The critical rational character of some of the posts on Indymedia is no coincidence either, as this forum has a rather strict editorial policy. The administrators of this forum remove ‘racist, fascist, sexist, and homophobe posts’ as well as ‘ nonsense, provoca- tions, and other disinformation’.4 The observation that Internet forums can, under particular conditions, approx- imate the public sphere ideal has also been made by Lincoln Dahlberg in his examination of E-Democracy.org. E-Democracy is a volunteer-based project, which tries to make ‘use of the Internet to improve citizen participation and real world governance through online discussions and information and knowledge ex- change’.5 Since its conception in Minnesota in 1994, several local discussion for- ums have been created in the US, UK, and New Zealand. To accomplish fruitful public political debate and a genuine exchange of information and knowledge, the E-Democracy project has employed a combination of rules and guidelines, as well as ‘forum management to structure deliberations towards the ends in- tended’. These efforts seem to have paid off as this project, according to Dahl- berg, in many ways approximates the public sphere conception: it has ‘stimulated reflexivity, fostered respectful listening and participant commitment to the on- going dialogue, achieved open and honest exchange, and provided equal oppor- tunity for all voices to be heard’ (Dahlberg 2001). Despite such examples, the overall majority of the discussions investigated here, even on Indymedia and Marokko Community, did not come near these norma- tive ideals of the public sphere. Consequently, we must conclude that in general the deliberations on Internet forums cannot be considered a digital extension of the Habermasian public sphere.

conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 243 Blogosphere as public sphere What about the blogs? In contrast to the forums, blogs are first and foremost a platform for individual authors. While many blogs offer their readers the oppor- tunity to comment on a blog post, they do not allow them to start main blog posts on their own. Consequently, blog discussions are usually dominated by the point of view of the blogger, supported by most of the commentators. As Geert Lovink has made clear, the homogeneous character of blog discussions is the result of the implicit rules of conduct to which bloggers adhere. He argues: ‘Adversaries will not post on each other’s blogs. At best, they quote and link’ (Lovink 2008, 21). In this sense, blogs seem to be even less of an egalitarian platform of public debate than web forums, which would lead us to the conclusion that they are even less well equipped to facilitate the public sphere. However, this assessment should be reconsidered when we look at blogs as a collective of cross-linked blog entries. As various new media theorists maintain, together blogs can generate a lively public debate by commenting on, and linking to, newspaper articles and other blogs. On the basis of this claim, these theorists subsequently contend that blogs constitute a blogosphere, which serves an im- portant function in public debate by being able to hold the traditional mass media accountable for its mistakes and inaccuracies (Gillmor 2004, 237; Lovink 2008, 7; Tremayne 2007, 263-265). Henry Jenkins even maintains that ‘bloggers will be jousting with mainstream journalists story by story, sometimes getting it right, sometimes getting it wrong, but always forcing a segment of the public to ques- tion dominant representations’ (Jenkins 2006, 216-217). Yet, if we examine the blogs in the hours and days after the Van Gogh assassi- nation, a somewhat different picture emerges. First, it must be noted that the number of blogs commenting on the assassination is relatively small. Even if we take into account that part of the blogs have disappeared since or could not be retrieved through Google Blog Search, 51 blogs is not that many, set against the estimated 30 million blogs which existed worldwide by the end of 2004. More- over, there seems to have been little debate between blogs; none of the examined blogs actually discussed claims made by other blogs, even though some provided links in the so-called blog roll. Neither did the blogs comment much on the mass media reporting. A few blogs did provide links to newspaper articles but gave no further comments. The only exception in this regard was GeenStijl, which strongly criticized various prominent and newspapers for cooperating with the political estab- lishment. Particularly remarkable was that this right-wing shocklog, usually criti- cal of any multiculturalism, took the producers of two television programs to task for the way they had selected young Dutch Moroccans to appear on their respec- tive programs. The blog accused the producers of adopting a stereotypical ap- proach and of being only interested in radical Moroccans, who concurred with

244 digital material the assassination.6 However, GeenStijl, which has been partly owned by the right- wing newspaper De Telegraaf since 2006, is not a regular blog. It is effectively a mass medium in its own right, run by a professional staff of at least a dozen editors. The rest of the examined blogs did not criticize other media, but simply gave personal expressions of anger, frustration, and despair. In form and content, these blog posts were not very different from what could be found on the forums. They certainly did not collectively function as a critical check on the mass media reporting. The discrepancy between the observations in the literature and our analysis seems for a large part due to a difference in focus. New media theorists have primarily examined a small number of American high-traffic blogs, which are devoted to political issues and frequently challenge mainstream media (Lovink 2008, 260). Time and again the same examples are discussed in which bloggers have succeeded in correcting a national newspaper or a high profile television show. The vast majority of personal blogs is excluded in this type of research, since only a few blogs actively monitor other media. In sum, theoretically, forums as well as blogs can, in different ways, contribute to the public sphere, as originally conceptualized by Habermas. In principle, for- ums are highly egalitarian platforms for diverse opinions, since they are open for everyone to participate in a public discussion or start a new one. While blogs are in theory more homogeneous, they may also function as a collective linking and monitoring platform, enacting critical checks on the reporting of mass media and other blogs. Yet, in practice, neither the blogs nor the forums seem to fulfil their public sphere potential. There are certainly examples of blogs and forums which come near the public sphere ideal, but the overall majority does not. Of course, we could abandon the Habermasian normative criteria of inclusive- ness and rationality and adopt a more lenient definition of the public sphere. Recent examples of such an approach can be found in Brian McNair’s Cultural chaos (2006, 136-143), and Yochai Benkler’s The wealth of networks (2006, 11, 177- 178). Although this strategy allows them to arrive at a more optimistic assessment of the influence of online communication on public debate, the concept of the public sphere also loses its critical and normative force as a consequence; it prac- tically becomes a synonym for any form of public communication. We may conclude that the concept of the public sphere, both as a normative and a descriptive concept, does not really help us to assess the contribution of forums and blogs to public debate. If we hold on to a strict normative definition of the public sphere based on the criteria of inclusiveness and rationality, we inevitably have to dismiss the mass of blogs and forums for failing to live up to this ideal. But if we choose to abandon these criteria, and opt to employ the pub- lic sphere primarily as a descriptive concept, we can no longer use it to evaluate online communication in terms of its contribution to democracy and diversity.

conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 245 Multiple public spheres Is the concept of a multiplicity of alternative public spheres more helpful? On the basis of this notion, it has been argued that the Internet is particularly important as an instrument for the emancipation of subordinated social groups. The Inter- net permits, according to John Downey and Natalie Fenton, ‘radical groups from both Left and Right to construct inexpensive virtual counter-public spheres’ (Downey and Fenton 2003, 198). This argument has especially been based on the use of networked ICT by social activists. Research shows that the Internet facil- itates the internal communication of social movements, as well as the organiza- tion of protest campaigns (Arquilla and Ronfeld 2001; Bennett 2004, 130-131; Castells 2004, 83, 154-158; Van de Donk et al. 2004, 4-6; Keck and Sikking 1999, 96). The question is whether a similar claim can be made concerning the forum and blog discussions in the aftermath of the assassination, which primarily in- volved individuals who were not part of a social movement. At first sight, blogs especially seem fit as platforms for the development of a multiplicity of alternative public spheres. As we have noticed in the previous sec- tion, blog discussions are often characterized by participants who strongly concur with the blog owner’s opinions. In this sense, blogs can be interpreted as alter- native platforms on which specific groups debate public issues in their own circle. However, precisely the hierarchical character of blog discussions is problematic from an alternative public spheres perspective. As we have already noticed, it seems to make blogs primarily a platform for individual expression, rather than for the development of a collective point of view. This obviously undermines the potential of blogs as instruments for the emancipation of subordinated social groups. In addition, it must be noted that most blogs, except for GeenStijl, only had a few commentators. Thus, in a quantitative and qualitative sense, it is ques- tionable whether blogs can facilitate the development of multiple public spheres. As it turns out, the forums correspond better with the notion of multiple alter- native public spheres. In contrast to the blogs, the forums, with their egalitarian architecture and thousands of visitors daily, can potentially serve as platforms for the expression of group interests and opinions. As already became clear in the previous section, the forums did indeed seem to function as such, since they pri- marily drew participants who interpreted the assassination likewise. Finally, im- portant to note is that most forum discussions were characterized by emotional and heated discourse. While this type of discourse is problematic from the origi- nal Habermasian perspective, scholars working from the perspective of multiple public spheres have pointed out that such discourse can fulfil an important eman- cipatory role. It allows for the participation of groups who do not master the critical rational discourse used by politicians, intellectuals, and journalists who dominate mass media discussions (Dahlgren 2001, 39; Fraser 1992, 120-122; Pa- pacharissi 2004, 266).

246 digital material In the investigated forum discussions, emotional and heated discourse was specifically important because it allowed a variety of groups to articulate their specific identities and discuss the social tensions resulting from the assassination in their own terms. Particularly Marokko Community provided fertile ground for such discussions. For example, a day after the assassination, one member with the handle ffeiza claimed that ‘Now, you really hear what the Dutch think about the Moroccans. Today at work we had a vicious discussion: All Moroccans should piss off. Your religion is nonsense. This is what my boss told me.’ Quickly, how- ever, another member pointed out that ffeiza made the same mistake as people who blamed the entire Moroccan community for the murder of Van Gogh: ‘if a few “Dutch people” say something, it is not immediately representative for the whole country.’ Someone else added: ‘I don’t know whether these statements are representative of how the Dutch think about the Moroccans. I rather think that these are just emotions that are released after such an event.’ Yet, another argued: ‘This is not that bad. At least he is still discussing with you. It is always better than 7 bullets and a knife in your body.’ To which ffeiza, in turn, responded, ‘I’m not talking about what is better: bullets or discussing. I’m purely talking about the fact that a person can smile at you for two years and then, after something happens, say these kinds of things’.7 While these kinds of exchanges correspond with the notion of alternative pub- lic spheres, this is certainly not to say that all of the statements on the forums constituted a positive contribution to public debate. While some of the discus- sions, such as the above example from Marokko Community, challenged cultural stereotypes, a large part of the investigated forum exchanges consisted of hateful messages. Particularly on the Pim Fortuyn Forum, many xenophobic statements could be read.8 One message on this forum, for example, claimed: ‘Islam is the plague for a free society; consequently, Islam does not belong here. This madness is a disease, which must be totally eradicated.’9 Although less frequently, and somewhat less extreme, intolerant messages could also be found on the FOK!for- um! and Marokko Community. The only exception was Indymedia, which has an ex- plicit editorial policy against ‘racist’ and ‘fascist’ texts. Similar observations have been made by Albert Benschop in his research on the online communication leading up to the assassination of Van Gogh. Benschop, who largely focused on forums, concluded: ‘We have seen how radicalised Isla- mic youngsters used the Internet to hatch their networks of hatred and dissemi- nate their hostile message. This gave rise to a climate for violent jihad, in which the murderer of Theo van Gogh could be recruited.’ On the opposite end of the political spectrum, Benschop observed the online activities of ‘right-wing extre- mist, neo-nationalist and neo-nazi groupings’: ‘With their xenophobic, islamo- phobic and racist statements they created a climate of hatred of foreigners, long before the murder of Van Gogh’ (Benschop 2005). These concerns resonate with Cass Sunstein’s argument that ‘the Internet creates a large risk of group polariza- conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 247 tion, simply because it makes it so easy for like-minded people to speak with one another – and ultimately to move toward extreme and sometimes even violent positions’ (Sunstein 2001, 199). The concern over extremism hints at another analytical problem, which chal- lenges the concept of multiple public spheres as a tool to understand the contri- bution of Internet forums to public debate. The concept is based on the assump- tion that the various social groups first develop their opinions, interests, identities, and organizational links within their own circle, and subsequently in- fluence the larger public debate as played out in the mass media. Yet, if we exam- ine the debate on the assassination, it becomes clear that none of the forums had much of a direct impact on the debate in the mass media. Although some of the newspapers did give short impressions of the more radical statements on forums such as Marokko Community and the Pim Fortuyn Forum, they did not discuss these statements any further. 10 Moreover, none of the forum discussions produced any agreement between the participants about a shared interest or a particular course of actions which should be followed. This was certainly not due to a lack of initiative. Various contributors to the Pim Fortuyn Forum and Indymedia, which on other occasions served as a plat- form for organizing protests, made appeals for cooperation. For example, some of the participants on the Pim Fortuyn Forum called upon fellow members to join a protest of several right-wing organizations against the murder. This protest was supposed to serve as an alternative to the official manifestation organized by the Amsterdam municipality, which had drawn over 20,000 people. Even though a few of the forum members showed some interest, the majority did not even both- er to respond. The following day, de Volkskrant reported that the alternative protest had not been a success as the police had far outnumbered the protesters.11 Other calls for joint action did not produce any major results either.

Conclusion This article has shown that the concepts of the public sphere and alternative pub- lic spheres, frequently used to understand the influence of the Internet on public debate, only have limited value when we examine particular forms of online com- munication in the context of actual societal conflict. More specifically, the investi- gation demonstrated that these concepts could only capture part of the different roles played by forums and blogs in the debate following the assassination of Theo van Gogh. Some of the forum discussions certainly approached the public-sphere ideals of inclusiveness and critical rationality, whereas GeenStijl appeared to fulfil the prom- ise that blogs enhance the rationality of public debate by providing a critical check on the reporting of the mass media. However, the majority of the forum and blog

248 digital material discussions did not in any way match the normative criteria of the Habermasian public sphere. More or less similar conclusions can be drawn concerning the notion of multi- ple public spheres. At first sight, blogs seem to correspond with this concept, but on closer inspection it becomes highly questionable whether they facilitate the expression of group interests and opinions. Forums were even more ambiguous. Clearly, they provided a platform for the articulation of specific cultural identities. Yet, at the same time, forums facilitated the dissemination of hateful messages. Moreover, it became clear that they largely function in isolation from the discus- sion in the mass media, which does not conform to the idea that alternative pub- lic spheres enable subordinated groups to participate in the general public de- bate. As most of the forum and blog discussions fall short of the criteria of either the public sphere or of multiple alternative public spheres, holding on to these con- cepts effectively leads us to dismiss and ignore the vast majority of online com- munication. Yet, as the concerns of Benschop and Sunstein about online extre- mism already indicate, the more or less isolated discussions and statements on the forums and blogs do seem to have a significant social and political impact, albeit much less direct and more diffuse than has so far been theorized. The challenge is to find out how this diffused influence exactly works. To meet this challenge and develop new conceptual tools, we need to do further research on the different forms of online communication in the context of social conflict. A number of questions ought to be addressed. Firstly, our examination showed that many forum discussions revolved around cultural identity struggles. Can this also be observed in other cases? And under which circumstances can this facil- itate the transcending of social stereotypes? According to Mark Poster, electronic communication in general, and online communication specifically, displaces the modern ‘rational, autonomous individual’ with ‘one that is multiplied, dissemi- nated and decentered, continuously interpellated as an unstable identity’ (Poster 1995, 57). This suggests that online communication does not fixate identities but constantly transforms them. Is this also true for forum and blog discussions in situations of social crisis? And is there a difference between forums and blogs regarding identity interpellation? Secondly, what is especially missing so far is information about the offline ac- tivities of the debate participants. To what extent do contributors maintain offline connections? Contrary to Benschop’s analysis of the terrorist network in which Mohammed B. had been active, our investigation showed few indications that people developed offline relationships. Does this imply that most online ex- changes are rather isolated from the traditional forms of social and political asso- ciation, such as clubs, social movements and political parties? And, if this is in- deed the case, how does this affect the public debate?

conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 249 Notes 1. ‘Theo v. Gogh doodgeschoten’, FOK!forum!, 2-11-2004, http://forum.fok.nl/topic/ 622123/2/25; ‘Theo van Gogh vermoord (deel 14)’, FOK!forum! 2-11-2004, http://forum. fok.nl/topic/622354. 2. ‘Commentaar op moord Van Gogh’, Indymedia, 3-11-2004, http://indymedia.nl/nl/2004/ 11/22761.shtml. 3. ‘Vertel mij eens….’, Marokko Community, 3-11-2004, http://forums.marokko.nl/archive/ index.php/t-403666.html. 4. ‘Spelregels van Indymedia NL’, Indymedia, http://indymedia.nl/nl/static/help.policy. shtml. 5. ‘About’, e-democracy, 3-4-2004, http://www.e-democracy.org/about.html. 6. ‘Bedankt Van Jole cs.’, GeenStijl, 2-11-2004, http://www.geenstijl.nl/mt/archieven/ 002829.html; ‘Omroepen op zoek naar kutmarokkanen’, GeenStijl, 2-11-2004, http:// www.geenstijl.nl/mt/archieven/002832.html. 7. ‘Frustaties tussen Marokkanen en Nederlanders’, Marokko Community, 3-11-2004, http:// forums.marokko.nl/archive/index.php/t-404038.html. 8. The Pim Fortuyn Forum was created in the honour of the openly gay, populist right-wing Dutch politician Pim Fortuyn, who was murdered in 2002 by an animal rights activist. Fortuyn was highly critical of Islam, which he called a ‘backward culture’. 9. ‘Theo van Gogh vermoord’, Pim Fortuyn Forum, 3-11-2004, http://www.pim-fortuyn.nl/ pfforum/topic.asp?ARCHIVE=true&TOPIC_ID=30391&whichpage=3. 10. ‘Uitingen van woede op websites’, NRC Handelsblad, 2-11-2004; ‘Ook op internet zorgen na moord op Van Gogh’, Het Parool, 3-11-2004; ‘Uitingen van woede heersen op web- sites’, Trouw, 3-11-2004; ‘Wanhoop en woede op webforum’, NRC Handelsblad, 3-11- 2004; ‘Condoleance.nl stroomt vol met racisme’, de Volkskrant, 3-11-2004. 11. John Schoorl, ‘Voor de kaalkoppen is de maat al heel lang vol’, de Volkskrant, 4-11-2004.

References Arquilla, John, and David Ronfeldt, eds. 2001. Networks and netwars. Santa Monica: RAND. Barber, Benjamin. 1998. The new telecommunications technology: Endless frontier or the end of democracy? In A passion for democracy: American essays, ed. Benjamin Barber, 258- 280. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Benkler, Yochai. 2006. The wealth of networks: How social production transforms markets and free- dom. New Haven: Yale University Press. Bennett, Lance. 2004. Communicating global activism. In Cyberprotest, eds. Wim van de Donk, et. al, 123-146. London: Routledge. Benschop, Albert. 2005. Chronicle of a political murder foretold. SocioSite. http://www.so- ciosite.org/jihad_nl_en.php. Boomgaarden, Hajo, and Claes de Vreese. 2007. Dramatic real-world events and public opinion dynamics: Media coverage and its impact on public reactions to an assassina- tion. International Journal of Public Opinion Research 19 (3): 354-366. Castells, Manuel. 2004. The power of identity. Malden: Blackwell Publishing. Dahlberg, Lincoln. 2001. Extending the public sphere through cyberspace: The case of Minnesota E-Democracy. First Monday 6 (3). http://www.firstmonday.org/issues/is- sue6_3/dahlberg/.

250 digital material Dahlberg, Lincoln. 2005. The Habermasian public sphere: Taking difference seriously? Theory and Society 34: 111-136. Dahlgren, Peter. 2001. The public sphere and the Net. In Mediated politics, eds. Lance Ben- nett, and R.M. Entman, 33-55. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Davis, Richard. 1999. The web of politics: The internet’s impact on the American political system. New York: Oxford University Press. Delli Carpini, Michael, and Scott Keeter. 2003. The Internet and an informed citizenry. In The civic web: Online politics and democratic values, eds. David Anderson, and Michael Corn- field, 129-153. New York: Rowman & Litttlefield Publishers. Donk, Wim van de, et.al., eds. 2004. Cyberprotest. London: Routledge. Downey, John, and Natalie Fenton. 2003 New media, counter publicity and the public sphere. New Media & Society 5 (2): 185-202. Fraser, Nancy. 1992. Rethinking the public sphere. In Habermas and the public sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun, 109-142. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gillmor, Dan. 2004. We the media: Grassroots journalism by the people, for the people. Cambridge: O’Reilly. Habermas, Jürgen. 1989 [1962] The structural transformation of the public sphere: An inquiry into a category of bourgeois society. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hacker, Kenneth, and Jan van Dijk. 2000. What is digital democracy? In Digital democracy: Issues of theory and practice, eds. Kenneth Hacker and Jan van Dijk, 1-9. Thousand Oaks: Sage. Hajer, Maarten, and Justus Uitermark. 2008. Performing authority: Discursive politics after the assassination of Theo van Gogh. Public Administration 86 (1): 1-15. Hurwitz, Roger. 2004. The ironies of democracy in cyberspace. In Democracy and new media, eds. Henry Jenkins, and David Thorburn, 101-112. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jenkins, Henry. 2006. Convergence culture: Where old and new media collide. New York: New York University Press. Keck, Margaret E., and Kathryn Sikkink. 1999. Transnational advocacy networks in inter- national and regional politics. International Social Science Journal 51 (159): 89-101. Knapp, James A. 1997. Essayistic messages: Internet newsgroups as an electronic public sphere. In Internet culture, ed. David Porter, 181-200. New York: Routledge. Lovink, Geert. 2008. Zero comments: Blogging and critical Internet culture. London: Routledge. Margolis, Michael, and David Resnick. 2000. Politics as usual: The cyberspace ‘revolution’. Lon- don: Thousand Oaks. McNair, Brian. 2006. Cultural chaos: Journalism, news, and power in a globalised world. London: Routledge. Papacharissi, Zizi. 2004. Democracy online: Civility, politeness, and the democratic poten- tial of online political discussion groups. New Media & Society 6 (2): 259-283. Pantti, Mervi, and Liesbet van Zoonen. 2006. Do crying citizens make good citizens? Social Semiotics 16 (2): 205-224. Poster, Mark. 1995. The second media age. Cambridge: Polity Press. Rheingold, Howard. 1993. The virtual community: Homesteading on the electronic frontier. Read- ing: Addison-Wesley. Tremayne, Mark, ed. 2007. Blogging, citizenship, and the future of media. London: Routledge.

conceptualizing forums and blogs as public sphere 251

Interfacing by material metaphors

How your mailbox may fool you

Marianne van den Boomen

Operating a computer is quite easy nowadays. We all click our way through our desktops; we send mail; we save documents in folders. We barely realize how these actions are framed by metaphors. Our first association with ‘cleaning a desktop’ has probably more to do with deleting unused icons and files on our PC than with polishing our material desk. We have no problem with the dominant office meta- phors, even when they blend with metaphors from other settings, such as home, menu, or window. Operating these metaphors usually goes smoothly. But, as we all know, some- times things go wrong. Sometimes our actions do not yield the expected results, and our computer suddenly becomes a black box. In this chapter I aim to trace what happens when we operate our PC, and how metaphors enable or disable our access to the machine. I will take a look at the user interface and show how it may fool us with its icons, begging the question: what exactly are icons? Are they signs, are they tools? With a little help from Peirce, Heidegger and Hayles, I will end with a plea for the development of a theory of material metaphor.

A computer is no coffee machine An ordinary PC is in fact an extraordinary apparatus. It is not only a physical machine, able to perform labor, i.e. to transform energy and raw material into a product or an event; it is also a symbol-processing machine (Hayles 2002; 2005). As a symbol-processing device, it translates its internal physical states into ma- chine code as well as human code – code readable by humans. The latter is usual- ly represented on the screen by the graphical user interface (GUI) with its icons, menus, and windows. Here, the PC articulates itself as a set of tools for the pro- duction, reproduction and modification of data products (texts, images, sound- tracks). At the same time the PC is also a toolmaking machine, able to create new tools (programs, scripts, plug ins) which can be fed back into the very same ma- chine. This makes the PC a much more complex device than just a set of tools.

253 At first sight, tools and products are clearly differentiated on the user interface. Products exist as mutable data objects (files); and tools exist as executable sets of commands (programs), or as interfacial signs (icons, buttons, menus). However, at a deeper level these tools and products are intricately nested into each other. Executable programs also consist of sets of files; interfacial signs are representa- tions of executable commands, and thus they are, in the last instance, also files. This complex machine of nested files becomes even more complex when hooked up in a network with other computers, thereby also enabling transference of tools and products to other machines in the network. Yet, users stick cognitively to the assumed clear division between tools and products. After all, means and ends, tools and products, are ontologically quite different, as is the case with a coffee machine: there is a clear difference between the button for cappuccino and the cappuccino itself. We never mistake the button for the coffee. But a computer is no coffee machine. And it is actually quite com- mon in computer praxis to mistake the button for the product itself. This is due to the fact that we cannot have the product without the tool. We cannot read a text document without a word-processor program; we have no access to our mail without a mail program. In order to work with this compound, and differentiate whenever necessary, the usage of the keyboard and the mouse is decisive; these hands-on devices are indispensable parts of the user interface. However, the visual screen with its me- taphorized tools and products seems to attract all the attention. The screen seems to integrate, supersede and cannibalize all other parts of the user interface. This engulfing mechanism is not limited to computer usage as such; the screen pops up as a dominant metaphor for digital media in general, in ordinary speech as well as in new media studies (Turkle 1995; Johnson 1997; Bolter and Grusin 2000).1 This may be explained by the ability of the GUI to translate and articulate all other components into visual representations, thus rendering irrelevant what remains invisible, and rendering unthinkable what remains unmetaphorized. The visual tools on our screen thus seem to work as metaphorical stand-ins for complex machine processes. After the metaphorical translation of machine code into human code, there seems to be no way back. Metaphorical sign-tools acquire a life of their own, cannibalizing everything else that might be there. By showing they hide, by translating they substitute. This mechanism is especially at work in computer icons. These small pictures are shortcuts to specific software commands in order to yield some result through the combination of human and machine actions. However, machine actions are rendered invisible wherever possible. Icons cloak their reference to software in- structions and machine acts; instead, they pretend to refer to particular ‘places’ on a computer (My Documents, My Network, mailbox, folder) or to particular ‘things’ (file, program). Sometimes it is not even clear whether an icon refers to a place, a file, or a program. Take for instance your mail icon. What does it stand

254 digital material for? ‘Well, my e-mail of course.’ But what exactly is implied in the conceptual shortcut ‘my e-mail’; does it refer to a specific program running? Or to a place on your computer, the mailbox, where your mail resides? Or to a set of files, sent to you as e-mail messages? Or perhaps to all of these in one? Usually, when your mail just works as expected, these questions are irrelevant – who cares? But sometimes these questions pop up, as in the following story. It shows how different references may converge or diverge, leading to a lot of user bewilderment.

Somewhere around 1997 a friend of mine had problems with her brand new broad-band connection. She asked me to have a look at her computer. When she clicked on the mail icon an empty inbox showed up. ‘See, no mail. And I’m sure I have mail; I forwarded some from my office. That man who did the installation yesterday said everything was working – just click and go, ma’am. But where is my mail?’ ‘Okay,’ I said, ‘First, are you sure you are online?’ She pointed vaguely at the wires, still hanging chaotically all over the place, swirling to her desk. I hoped they were okay, but I did not mean the cables. There was a connection icon on her desktop, displaying a telephone device.2 Fortu- nately, its settings turned out to be correctly configured; a double-click estab- lished the connection with her Internet provider. And after clicking the ‘get mail’ button in her mail program her mail streamed into her inbox. ‘That’sit,’ I said. ‘You first have to connect, with that icon.’ My friend was puzzled. ‘That telephone icon? I used that to dial up with my modem, but now I have a permanent connection, just like I have at work. There I always see my mail immediately, without having to click on anything. I don’t even have such a telephone icon there.’ I explained that apparently her computer at work was configured that way. ‘That telephone icon stands for any kind of connection, be it by phone line or cable. But you can bypass it. It is possible to connect automatically to your provi- der as soon as you start up your computer. And also to fetch your mail as soon as you start your mail program. We can arrange that, if you like.’ And so we did.

That was all. A clear, comprehensible problem; just a small conceptual error. Yet, the story is illustrative of how human-computer interaction works, how it often fails to work, and how this relates to conceptual reifications, material configura- tions, and hidden steps in between. Basically, my friend took the metaphorized icons literally. She took the mailbox icon for the mail itself, and the telephone icon for using the phone itself. For her, the mailbox icon was not referring to a process, a string of commands set in action in order to obtain a computed result; rather, it functioned as a key to a interfacing by material metaphors 255 specific place, her inbox, where she expected her mail to be, immediately. The icon was not read as a reference, but as the immediate referent itself. The icon had superseded and cannibalized all references, transferences and network labor involved. A shortcut indeed. It is important to note this is not unique to my friend’s computer use. It is a general feature of iconicity. Computer icons function by iconic condensation: a condensation of reference, referent, and meaning into one visual metaphorical sign, thereby substituting all involved complexities with a stable icon. Hence, the inclination to take the icon for a specific state (result, place, or thing) instead of a referential button able to invoke a performative process is very strong. In fact, this is part and parcel of the very function of icons: shortcutting and condensing the signifying and executing processes. Icons can only carry out their signifying and executing job by concealing the involved complexities, substituting them with stable entities. Hence, the mail icon hides the nested processes it refers to: executing the mail program, including its configurations for a particular Internet connection, a par- ticular mail account, and particular incoming and outgoing mail servers located at an Internet service provider. Instead, the icon represents a specific result (re- ceived mail) located at a specific place (the mailbox), as an ontologized entity. The same holds for the telephone icon: it conceals that it is referring to the execu- tion of a connection program, including its configurations and settings. Instead, it represents the contiguous telephone device. This concealment of software and hardware processes cannot be seen as coin- cidental ‘non-representing’; it is a necessary and deliberate act against representa- tion. I propose to call this act of deliberate concealing depresentation. We could then say that computer icons do their work by representing an ontologized stable state, while depresenting the procedural complexity. This is the task we have de- legated to icons. And this is why we are seduced, indeed compelled, to take icons literally – that is, to ontologize them, to condense and collapse them into their own inextricable iconic ontology, their icontology.

Signs, iconicity and indexicality This begs the question: what kind of signs are computer icons? Peirce’s semiotics (Peirce 1873) seems typically apt to solve the riddle of the icon, not only because it unfolds an explicit vocabulary on iconicity, but also because Peirce’s notion of in- dexicality enables a non-essentialist analysis of the relation between signs and the world outside language and signs.3 Peirce’s concept of indexicality does not pertain to just any reference a sign can make to an external object. Peirce distinguishes three basic relations a sign can have to the object it refers to: iconic, indexical and symbolic. The icon refers to its object by resemblance, similarity or analogy, for example the portrait of a person, a

256 digital material traffic sign with a picture of a hollow in the road, or the map of a country. The index refers to its object by an existential, physical or causal connection, for example smoke indicating fire, a fingerprint identifying a person, a sundial indicating time. The symbol refers to its object arbitrarily, that is, by habit, convention or law, for example the flag of a country, the logo of a company, or the alphabet for phonemes. These categories are not mutually exclusive; in a symbol there may be some- thing indexical and something iconic. For example, a traffic sign is always a sym- bol, as it is taken up in a system of laws and conventions regarding the use of forms and colors for these signs. However, a particular traffic sign may be indexi- cally referring to a nearby hollow in the road, and it may do so by an iconic image resembling a hollow. Peirce’s classification also accounts for the fact that signs circulate and may change by use. Icons may become symbols, for instance when the iconic picture of Che Guevara is printed on a T-shirt, signifying not so much the person Guevara but radical left sympathies. Likewise, symbols may be reiter- ated as an index; a yellow letter M is a symbol referring to the brandname McDo- nald’s, but as a sign on a pole it is indexical for the nearby hamburger outlet. Peirce’s dynamic triad may be able to account for the interaction between state, process and system at work in computing semiosis, especially when it comes to computer icons. At first sight, computer icons seem not to be Peircian icons at all, but rather Peircian symbols. After all, they are all arbitrary; what a specific icon stands for we have to learn by collateral experience. But at second sight, computer icons rather seem to be Peircian indices: they all refer causally and physically to a set of software instructions to be executed. Meanwhile, on yet another level icons may articulate other relations since they can refer to their object in three ways: by resemblance (iconic), by existential rela- tion (indexical), or by convention (symbolic). On this level the mailbox icon would be a genuine Peircian icon, since its relation to its displayed object is based on an analogy between postal mail and e-mail. The telephone icon would be an indexical sign: its representation is not based on analogy but on an existential (though outdated) relation with the telephone device. And the icon for Microsoft’s Internet Explorer, the stylized ‘e’, would then be a Peircian symbol, since the im- age is arbitrary and conventional. From one perspective, then, all computer icons can be seen as symbolical or indexical signs, and from another perspective they may be icons, indices or sym- bols. The latter concerns how the object is represented by the sign, the former pertains to the external existence of the object. In Peirce’s terminology, these are different kinds of objects. He called the first one the immediate object – the object as represented by the sign – and the second one the dynamical object – the object as it exists in the world. This dynamical object cannot be expressed by the sign itself, it can only be indicated, and its connection to the sign has to be learned (Peirce 1909).

interfacing by material metaphors 257 This differentiation between objects enables us to flesh out how computer icons work. As we have seen, desktop icons refer to an act of executing machine code. From this perspective, all desktop icons are indexical: they refer to existen- tial, physical chains of causation, to machine processes to be executed. Their dy- namical object is thus machinic code. Whatever their immediate object as ex- pressed in the sign may be (an iconic mailbox, an indexical telephone device, a symbolical logo), their dynamical object is code. But as we have seen, computer icons not only refer to machinic code but also to human code – readable symbols and metaphors. Hence, a computer icon indexi- cally refers to machine code, and symbolically it refers to human code (e.g. ‘mail’, ‘connection’). In that regard, computer icons can be considered Peircian indices (referring to the dynamical object of machine code), wrapped in Peircian symbols (referring to the dynamical object of human code), while they are only contin- gently iconical (if they use pictorial resemblance for representation). Yet, in the praxis of signification this gets inverted: computer icons establish themselves as primarily iconic. While they are rarely genuine Peircian icons, they all exhibit what I have called ‘icontology’–reified iconicity. They do so by equat- ing and substituting the sign with its immediate object of reference, thus negat- ing the indexical and symbolical references to the dynamical object. In order to understand the strange double dynamical object of computer icons – simultaneously machine code and human code – I propose a third kind of ob- ject: a symbolic future object, a not yet actualized object, an object to become, in short: a virtual object. This object is not represented in the sign, neither is it the indexical, actual execution of machine code. It is what might be actualized by the joint venture of human acts and machine processes. It is not just your mail pro- gram running, it is that you might have received mail. It is not just your browser running, it is the web out there where you may find or do something. It is where machine possibility and human effort come together. It is where signs become tools for unknown and unprogrammed virtual objects.

Tools ready-to-hand and present-at-hand This introduces another problem: how can signs become tools? At first sight tools are fundamentally different from signs. Signs are marks able to qualify, refer to, or represent other signs and things in the world; tools are things in the world able to shape and transform other things. But as Heidegger (1927) pointed out, tools exist Um-zu (in order to); their being-in-the-world always refers to a possible (may we say ‘virtual’?) work to be done, taken up in a system of other equipment (Zeug) and labor. Heidegger calls a tool we just use ready-to-hand (‘Zuhanden’); it fits with the acts of our hands, and the goal in our minds. It aligns seamlessly with its Um-zu and does not call for further reflection – we do not think about a ham- mer, we just use it. But when a tool does not function according to its Um-zu, for

258 digital material example when it breaks down, it suddenly becomes a strange separate object. Then it is not ready-to-hand anymore but present-at-hand (‘Vorhanden’): open to questions about what is the matter with it. We then have to reconsider our en- gagement with the object, repair it, replace it, or change our goal altogether. Though computer icons cannot break down like a hammer, they may function as ready-to-hand or present-at-hand. They are ready-to-hand tools when they yield the expected result. We then take their icontology for granted and need not think about them as tools or as signs; we just click and go. But when a click fails, the icon is no longer ready-to-hand but present-at-hand, raising questions about whether the equipment chain is broken somewhere, or whether we just misinter- preted the sign. In Peircian terms: this raises questions about its reference to the object, which seemed to be unproblematically immediate when ready-to-hand, but exposes its dynamical and virtual mediations when suddenly becoming pre- sent-at-hand.4 From this perspective the transformation of the computer icon from an integrated ready-to-hand sign-tool into a decomposed present-at-hand object is not a disturbing inconvenience, but an opportunity. An opportunity to investigate how digital equipment works, how it refers to other equipment and code, how it conceals its indexical dynamics, how it can fool you, and how you can counter this. As Winograd and Flores (1985) put it: ‘Breakdowns serve an extremely important cognitive function, revealing to us the nature of our practices and equipment, making them present-to-hand to us, perhaps for the first time. In this sense they function in a positive rather than negative way.’

Conceptual metaphors My friend, looking for her mail, would probably have found little comfort in Hei- degger’s ready-to-hand and present-at-hand tools, or Peirce’s immediate and dy- namical objects. We are all seduced by the immediate object of the sign and tend to remain trapped in its icontology. We take computer icons as condensed sign- tools, without being aware of the constitutive parts. While this can partly be ex- plained by what I have called icontology, this does not explain why, even in a situation of being stuck with a present-at-hand sign-tool, the sign and the tool part still tend to stick together. What kind of glue keeps them together? For an answer to this question, we have to zoom in on the mechanism of metaphorical substitution encountered earlier. The shortest definition of metaphor is: something which stands for something else. While all signs in fact stand for something else, metaphors are special, since they do so in a double sense. Metaphorical signs condense two references by transferring and incorporating qualities from one object of reference into an- other. Hence, metaphors are mechanisms of transference (from one to another) and condensation (one within another). This transference can be accomplished by words, but equally so by images (Forceville 2008) and physical objects (Guten- interfacing by material metaphors 259 plan 2005). By assigning concepts to words, images and material objects, these ontologically different things are able to blend conceptually. According to the so-called conceptual theory of metaphor (Lakoff and Johnson 1980; Lakoff 1993), metaphors can be analyzed as sets of conceptual correspon- dences across semantic domains, with an underlying basic conceptual metaphor which can be abbreviated as Y IS X, or TARGET DOMAIN IS SOURCE DOMAIN (Lakoff 1993). Might this be useful to analyze our riddle of the sign-tool icontol- ogy? Analyzing the mailbox icon as a metaphor would yield E-MAIL IS POSTAL MAIL as basic conceptual metaphor, and the cross-domain mapping would look like Table 1.

SOURCE DOMAIN: postal mail TARGET DOMAIN: e-mail mailbox inbox of mail program letters, packets messages, attachments sending and receiving send or get mail button sorting, disposing distribution to folders, deleting [postal distribution system] [mail-server network at ISPs] [delivery by postman] [consulting a mail server; fetch mail command]

Table 1: Cross-domain mapping for the conceptual metaphor E-MAIL IS POSTAL MAIL

All elements match well, except the last two in the list. These entities are indeed involved in the conceptual transference, but they are also exactly what is hidden in the iconic metaphor. They are and are not part of the conceptual mapping; they are what I have called depresented, while the other correspondences are represented as such on the interface. Note that this depresentation does not pertain to just un- used parts of the conceptual domains. Unused parts would be ‘stamps’ in the source domain and ‘viruses’ in the target domain – these associations are simply ignored, they have no cross-domain correspondence, and they are not necessary to establish the metaphor of e-mail. But the aspects ‘postal distribution system’ and ‘delivery by postman’ in the source domain do have a counterpart in the tar- get domain – they are indispensable for a successful transference. E-mail is only mail when it is also distributed and delivered. Yet, these acts are not represented in the metaphor connecting/condensing the source and target domain. Lakoff and Johnson’s model of conceptual metaphor thus gives an account of how the mailbox icon connects postal mail with e-mail on the level of the interface and human conceptual cognition, but it ignores the connections to software and ma- chinery. It explains the human code, but not the machine code: the indexical, dynamical operations involved, such as a connection with an Internet service pro- vider, a mail client consulting a mail server, and the subsequent transport of mail to the user’s PC.

260 digital material Schematized (see Figure 1) this model of metaphor consists of an input (source domain) and an output (target domain), mediated by a cognitive human mind which is able to read the metaphorical mailbox icon as immediate object, thus connecting the source and the target. The necessary machine mediations – index- ical references to dynamical objects – are invisible, hidden in a black box of soft- ware and machinery. Without a properly functioning dynamical black box, the output of the virtual object (‘my e-mail’) will not come about.

Figure 1: Input-output mechanism of the conceptual metaphor E-MAIL IS POSTAL MAIL

What is ignored in this model is that the metaphorical icon needs not only human reading but most of all action to invoke the transference – not only action by the user (configuring, clicking) but especially action inside the machine and the net- work. Meanwhile, the user is only able to read the icon as far as this action is depresented and blackboxed. As we have seen, that is what the icon does by ‘icon- tologizing’: equating the sign with its immediate object, effacing its material in- dexical relations to dynamical objects, pretending it stands immediately for the virtual object in the target domain.

interfacing by material metaphors 261 We may conclude that the classic, conceptual theory of metaphor in fact mir- rors this icontology, as it focuses primarily on the interfacial relation with the immediate object, the object as represented/metaphorized by the sign. Though this underscores once more how a sign can conceal and supersede its tool-being, it still provides no proper explanation for how the compound of sign and tool gets glued together. What we thus need, on top of the theory of conceptual meta- phor, is a theory of the processual materiality of metaphor. To my knowledge, there is no such theory yet. In the last section I will tentatively gather some possi- ble building blocks for such a theory.

Material metaphor What is needed is a theory of metaphor which not only maps transferences be- tween different semantic domains – from concept to concept, as does the concep- tual theory – but also between different ontological domains: from concepts to objects, from software instructions to visual icons, from signs to tools. Such a theory should provide an account of the involved material indexicality of sign- tools, of their relation to the dynamical objects inside the black box, and the rela- tion with the hoped-for virtual object. Katherine Hayles’s (2002) notion of material metaphor is a promising starting point. Hayles defined material metaphor as the instance of metaphor where the metaphorical transference does not take place between semantic concepts, but between symbolic signs and material apparatus. Like all metaphors, material me- taphors condense two references, yet they do not blend two conceptual refer- ences; rather, they blend a conceptual reference with a material indexical refer- ence. Hayles proposed the term in the context of her medium-specific analysis of electronic literature. In this field written words can do more than just signify or represent – they may, as material metaphors, be able to perform acts: dance, move, dissolve, mutate, tear apart, destroy previously read words, etc., according to the underlying software code. This kind of e-textual performance can be seen as a radicalization of Austin’s speech act theory. Austin (1962) pointed out how verbal statements such as ‘I promise’ or ‘I baptise this ship’ are not just constative utterances but performative speech acts. By being uttered (in a specific context), such utterances do things in the world, they accomplish a change in a state of affairs. In a similar vein e-text is able to perform ‘digital speech acts’. Though Austin’s speech act theory pertains primarily to language and Hayles’s material metaphor primarily to digital litera- ture, there seems to be no reason to confine material metaphor to the domain of words and texts. Just as images and physical objects may be invoked as concep- tual metaphors, they may be invoked as material metaphors. Whenever an image or an object functions as a symbol and is able to entail a change of affairs when enacted in the proper context, it can be considered a material metaphor. Take, for

262 digital material example, the planting or capturing of a flag – this not only signifies colonization or victory, it evokes it by the very act of planting or capturing. Material metaphors are ubiquitous in ordinary computer interfaces. They exist as sign-tools, as icons and hyperlinks, as pixeled buttons and switches which can indeed be switched on and off. Such material metaphors condense iconicity and indexicality by blending immediate and dynamical objects into one sign-tool. The mailbox icon is a material metaphor, able to invoke indexical material acts, changes in the material machinery of the computer and the network. Conceiving the mailbox as material metaphor thus reveals what is depresented in the concep- tual metaphor. While the conceptual metaphor can explain what happens inside the head of the user, the material metaphor leads us to the hands of user, and from there to and through the interface, right inside the black box of digital ma- chinery. Not that the black box will become transparent. Most parts of this black box will remain in the dark, since we humans are practically blind in this digital do- main. We have delegated the relevant intentional acts to code, which we can exe- cute but which we cannot grasp directly. We are simply not equipped with a per- ceptual or cognitive apparatus to read the digital, to read patterns of numbers and infer their meaning or effects. However, we do have partial, mediated access to the digital. We have this possibility because machinic calculations and transla- tions can be ontologized and represented to us as readable signs, that is as mate- rial metaphors. We are able to read and act upon parts of the code, as far as these are represented as a sign-tool. This may be done by icons, but also by textual configuration menus (‘mail server settings’), hyperlinks or other metaphorized commands (‘get mail’, ‘send mail’). While these material metaphors mostly go by unnoticed, ready-to-hand and icontologized, they are however ‘near at hand’. An analysis of both their concep- tual iconicity and their material indexicality may turn them into keys to the black box, able to close and conceal, but also able to open and reveal. A full-blown theory of material metaphor may thus provide analytical apertures in the digital black box, enabling us to peek inside. In order to develop such a theory, a very heterogeneous set of analytical tools and concepts should be assembled. Though Peirce, Heidegger, Lakoff, and Hayles may be strange bedfellows, I consider their joint forces necessary for this endeavor. The ongoing proliferation of cross- and intermediations induced by digitality results in more and more material-semiotic assemblages in the form of icontologized virtual objects. They could and should be hacked analytically.

Notes 1. For example Sherry Turkle’s metaphorical book title Life on the screen: Identity in the age of the Internet (1995). In Steven Johnson’s Interface culture (1997) the computer interface interfacing by material metaphors 263 equals the screen with its visual metaphors. Even in Bolter and Grusin’s Remediation (1999) the basic principles of mediation – immediacy and hypermediacy – are both defined as ‘styles of visual representation’ (272). See for other examples of screenic hegemony the chapters by Nanna Verhoeff and Ann-Sophie Lehmann. See for a further deconstruction of the notion of indexicality the chapter by Frank Kessler. 2. Average Internet users nowadays would perhaps not even understand the telephone metaphor as network connection icon, not being familiar anymore with dial-up Internet accounts. A telephone icon nowadays usually stands for another application: voice over IP. 3. Cf. Saussure’s structuralist semiology, in which only two ingredients of the sign are distinguished: signifier (material embodiment of the sign) and signified (mental con- cept, produced by the differences in the chain of signifiers, arbitrarily connected to a signifier). In Saussure’s linguistic conception of the sign, any notion of reference to something outside language is disabled. While this precludes the pitfalls of claiming essentialist, natural correspondences between words and things, it also excludes any conceptualization of possible relations to a world outside human language. 4. Cf. Latour’s distinction between intermediaries, which just transmit, and mediators, which transform, translate and modify meaning while processing: ‘A properly functioning computer could be taken as a good case of a complicated intermediary (...) But if it breaks down, a computer may turn into a horrendously complex mediator’ (Latour 2005, 39).

References Austin, John Langshaw. 1962. How to do things with words, eds. J.O. Urmson and Marina Sbisà. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Bolter, Jay David, and Richard Grusin. 2000. Remediation: Understanding new media. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Coward, Rosalind, and John Ellis. 1977. Language and materialism: Developments in semiology and the theory of the subject. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Forceville, Charles. 2008. Metaphor in pictures and multimodal representations. In The Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought, ed. Raymond Gibbs. Cambridge, MA: Cam- bridge University Press. Freadman, Anne. 2004. The machinery of talk: Charles Peirce and the sign hypothesis. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Gutenplan, Samuel. 2005. Objects of metaphor. Oxford: Claridon Press. Harman, Graham. 2002. Tool-Being: Heidegger and the metaphysics of objects. Chicago: Open Court Publishing. Hayles, N. Katherine. 1993. Virtual bodies and flickering signifiers. October (66): 69-91. —. 2002. Writing machines. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. —. 2003. Translating media: Why we should rethink textuality. The Yale Journal of Criticism 16 (2): 263-290. —. 2005. My mother was a computer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Heidegger, Martin. 1954. The question concerning technology. In The question concerning technology and other essays, 1977, ed. William Lovitt, 3-35. Harper Torchbooks. Heidegger, Martin. 1927. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

264 digital material Johnson, Steven. 1997. Interface culture: How new technology transforms the way we create and communicate. New York: Basic Books. Lakoff, George. 1993. The contemporary theory of metaphor. In Metaphor and thought, ed. Andrew Ortony, 202-251. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chica- go Press. Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lucy, Niall. 2001. Beyond semiotics: Text, culture and technology. London, New York: Conti- nuum. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1873. Of logic as a study of signs. In Writings of Charles S. Peirce, 1981, ed. Peirce Edition Project, Vol. 3.82, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1888. A guess at the riddle. In Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, 1932, eds. Charles Hartshorne, Paul Weiss, and Arthur W. Burks, 365-367. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1904. A letter to Lady Welby. In Collected Papers of Charles Peirce, 1958, ed. A.W. Burks, Vol. 8.328. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1909. A letter to William James. In The Essential Peirce: Selected philo- sophical writings, 1998, ed. Peirce Edition Project, Vol. 2.498. Bloomington, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Saussure, de, Ferdinand. 1983 [1916]. Course in general , eds. Charles Bally and Al- bert Sechehaye. La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing. Tilley, Christopher. 1999. Metaphor and material culture. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Turkle, Sherry. 1995. Life on the screen: Identity in the age of the Internet. New York: Simon & Schuster. Winograd, Terry, and Fernando Flores, eds. 1985. Understanding computers and cognition. Nor- wood: Ablex Publishing.

interfacing by material metaphors 265

Hidden practice

Artists’ working spaces, tools, and materials in the digital domain

Ann-Sophie Lehmann

The construction of digital artworks demands a wide range of expertise. Concep- tion, production and technology are closely intertwined; existing technologies have to be adapted to new artistic concepts, and new technologies inspire and create new meanings and contexts. In order to realise a work of art – be it an installation in a gallery or museum, or an online work – an artist has to be engi- neer, programmer, graphic designer, and hardware constructor all at once or has to have access to others who are able to shape technologies and materials as required. In the case of Daniel Rozin’s Wooden Mirror (1999) for example – a work that produces the reflection of any person facing it by slightly shifting the po- lished wooden blocks of which the surface of the mirror is constructed – the cameras, motion sensors, software and wooden blocks were all custom made (Bolter and Gromolla 2003). In a sense, the construction of such complex, inter- active works returns the digital-media artist to an era before the pre-manufactur- ing of artist’s supplies. Before the invention of metal paint tubes in the 19th cen- tury, before standard-sized canvasses or marble blocks were available, artists depended on custom-made materials and workshops with trained assistants, just as the media artist today might depend on programmers and engineers to provide custom-built technology. Even when artist and programmer are the same person, for example the net.art practitioners Jodi (http://text.jodi.org) or Olia Lialina (www.artlebedev.ru/svalka/olialia), the procedures of art making are no less intri- cate or complex. Thinking about the versatile practice of new media artists leads to the question of what this practice might look like. One way to find out is by studio visits or reading and watching interviews with artists (as can be done in the wonderful on- line archive of artist’s talks compiled by the Tate Gallery, London: www.tate.org. uk/onlineevents). Another way is to look at the ways media artists represent their own practice. Throughout history, artists have taken care to display, advertise and explain their art-making skills in genres specifically created for this purpose. Some of the first representations of artists at work may be found in illuminated

267 manuscripts, and in the early Renaissance, the representation of St. Luke painting the Madonna became a way to depict artistic practice and skill. Within a century the Christian iconography of the painting evangelist evolved into the independent self-portrait at the easel, and the atelier scene. Both genres were still widely pop- ular in the 19th and early 20th centuries, adapting their specific iconography to changing artistic practices and new technologies. Because today’s multifaceted media artist as described above might also be interested in the public display of her versatile skills, one could expect a continuation of the iconography of ‘the artist at work’ into the digital age. But is practice represented in the age of digital art? Do artists draw attention to the processes and procedures underlying their work? The question about a contemporary iconography of the representation of artistic practice raises more general questions about the spatial, material and the- oretical aspects of this practice: what kind of materials and tools are used to con- struct media art, and how do artists employ these tools and materials in their creative spaces? How are these creative spaces defined and located, and can they and the creative processes within be visualised? My first tentative answer to these questions is negative – digital modes of pro- duction do not appear to favour the representation of the artist at work because the very process of making is rendered invisible by the medium itself. However, this hypothesis must be tested first. In order to determine whether or not repre- sentation of practice is absent in the creation of digital art, this article will reflect on four aspects relevant to the question at stake. Beginning with a brief review of representations of artistic practice in the pre-digital era, a more thorough analysis of the location and designation of creative spaces in the digital era will follow. The representation of digital tools and materials used by media artists will then be focused on, incorporating a brief comparison with the representation of prac- tice in a field related to media art – computer graphics and animation.

The representation of artistic practice and creative spaces in the pre-digital era In the pre-photographic era artistic practice was represented in genres displaying artists working in their workshops. Needless to say, these scenes are not objective representations of generic practices, but carefully staged scenes designed to en- tice the viewer in the display of artistic skill. At the same time, these scenes served to invest an artist’s working space with near magical qualities. The careful pre- sentation of the ‘artist at work’ with brushes and paints (or their equivalents) in a studio space adorned with models, preliminary sketches and unfinished works evoked the aura of creation (Lehmann 2006; Pardo and Cole 2005). The images suggested that these spaces not only contained the materials and tools necessary to make works of art, but also housed the inspiration and genius necessary to conceive them. Furthermore, the images enhanced the mystery of artistic creation

268 digital material Figure 1: The Workshop of Jan van Eyck, etching from the series Nova Reperta by Jacobus Stradanus, 1555 through an interesting pictorial paradox. On the one hand, atelier scenes allow us to witness the act of creating a painting, seemingly instructing the viewer in the actual making of pictorial illusions. Yet while we observe the processes of paint- ing – paint being mixed, a brushstroke applied – the acts displayed before our eyes are far too complex to be copied purely based on the visual information provided. Showing art making therefore does not necessarily give away the artist’s secret. On the contrary, the display of skill makes the process of creation appear all the more mysterious. After 1900 photography and then film would replace the painted depictions of the artist at work. The latter provided more information about art making as it recorded the creative process over time. Yet these films – like Hans Cürlis’s series Schaffende Hände from the 1920s, Hans Namuth’s Jackson Pollock (1951), Henri- Georges Clouzot’s Le mystère Picasso (1956) and many art documentaries made since – do not escape the paradox described above and display a ‘fetishization of the actual moment of creation’ (Hayward 1988, 8). To this day, especially the studio space lends itself to the idealisation and mystification of practice. Even with the artist dead and gone, the deserted studio continues to breathe the aura of creation and is treated as a shrine, with the material remains as relics. The recent transfer of Francis Bacon’s entire studio contents from London to and the exhibition of Perry Ogden’s beautiful photographs of Bacon’s chaotic workshop as works of art in their own right are perfect examples of the cultural hidden practice 269 value attached to the traditional creative environment (for a visual impression, see www.hughlane.ie/fb_studio). It can be concluded that the representation of practice was – and still is – clo- sely tied to the aura of materials and spaces. This ‘materialist’ notion is incorpo- rated in the very naming of the artist’s space: the term atelier derives from the Latin atele, which referred to the wooden shavings in a carpenter’s workshop. These wooden scraps and other litter from his studio (cigarette buds, lost socks, old cloth) are at the heart of the work of Jedediah Caesar. Caesar collects debris in boxes, fills these with liquid resin and then saws the transparent cubes into thin slices. The results are beautiful, archeological samples of the studio, which em- body as well as question the representation of material practice.

The designation and location of creative spaces in the digital era New media have led to the formation of new creative spaces; spaces that seem to have caused a dislocation of the materiality of the traditional working space. In order to situate digital artistic practice and its representation, this section will attempt to trace and outline the physical, metaphorical and theoretical appear- ances of these new spaces. Beginning with the designation of the new spaces, it is remarkable that in new media art practice, a working space is frequently referred to as a laboratory rather than a studio or atelier – traditionally, the spaces of the production of art and science have been separated since the Renaissance (Alpers 1998). Often abbre- viated as media lab or design lab, the new working space is a sharp contrast to the traditional concept of the studio. Obviously, this shift owes much to the es- sential role of technology in new media art. Also, the notion of creation asso- ciated with the traditional studio might be less appealing than the notion of ex- periment associated with the laboratory. Yet the laboratory, just like the studio, carries its own traditional set of connotations, which are deemed highly proble- matic by some scholars. Bruno Latour has criticised the laboratory as the ultimate black box; as a place where experiment and invention are kept from public view, and only finite results are allowed to emerge after having been carefully wrapped in impenetrable layers of scientific reasoning (Latour 1987). Although the artist’s laboratory has come to signify the cross-disciplinary link between art and science and could therefore symbolise a partial opening of the black box, the production and making of art still seem to be hidden behind the walls of the lab. Conse- quently, there is no equivalent to the traditional depiction of the atelier described above, no laboratory-iconography representing the work that goes on inside. This obscuring of creative practice is matched by an apparent reluctance to describe the technological processes behind digital artworks with words. In re- cent overviews of new media art, very little attention is paid to the actual produc- tion of the artworks discussed (Greene 2004; Paul 2003; Stallabrass 2003).

270 digital material Although net.art plays with digital technologies and addresses their impact on art, society and politics, the actual technologies and procedures behind the indi- vidual artworks remain obscure. Artists simply ‘draw links between sites’; ‘build online artworks’; or present ‘a sophisticated piece of programming’ (Stallabrass 2003, 27-29). When artists themselves refer to their own practice, we get a notion of their presence behind the computer, yet we have no idea what they actually do with the computer. In a 1997 interview net.art pioneer Vuk Cosic describes how he has neighbouring studios with Heath Bunting, Alexei Shulgin and Olia Lialina, emulating the studio set-up of Picasso and Braque in early twentieth-century Paris: ‘We steal a lot from each other, in the sense that we take some parts of codes, we admire each other’s tricks’, and the Belgian duo Jodi wrote in the early 1990s: ‘it is obvious that our work fights against high tech’ (Stallabrass 2003, 34, 38). The ‘drawing’ of links and ‘building’ of sites, the comparison with Braque and Picasso, the fight against ‘high-tech’ all draw on traditional terminology and metaphors. The vocabulary for the description of the technological aspects of new media art practice on the other hand is limited. So how do we imagine the code- tricks Cosic mentions? How do we differentiate between high- and low-tech if technology is neither a verbal nor visual issue in the self-reflection of practice and in the critical analysis and public presentation of art works? Maybe technol- ogy is still considered dull to the wider public? The result being that ‘techno-talk’ is kept to a relatively small, artistic community that possesses sufficient technolo- gical understanding.1 Interestingly, the notion of the laboratory with its metaphorical connotations of secrecy and highly specialised technological processes, in combination with the textual silence surrounding these processes, contradicts a vital yet somewhat uto- pian ideal proclaimed by scholars of new media culture and theory like Henry Jenkins and Pierre Lévy. This ideal envisages new media as open-source, enabling technologies, which facilitate and inspire the participatory production of culture.2 The contradiction between the ‘black boxing’ of artistic practice and the ideal of a participatory culture might be due to the mechanisms of the art market – above all the demand for originality – to which eventually even the most non-conformist artist may succumb. In order to solve this conflict, open the ‘black box of practice’ and represent the new media artist at work, a means to facilitate the description and visualisation of the technologies used in art practice must be found. In addition to the symbolic and physical shift of the site of production from open studio to closed laboratory, new media have had a profound impact on the notion of space. In general, new media initially seemed to emphasize the tradi- tional division of space into metaphorical and/or virtual spaces on the one hand and actual, physical spaces on the other. More recently, scholars like Katherine Hayles (2002) and Mark Poster (2004) have argued that the inherent dichotomy of real and non-real spaces should be discarded in favour of a model that is based upon Michel Foucault’s concept of heterotopias, sites ‘that have the curious prop- hidden practice 271 erty of being in relation with all the other sites’ (Foucault 1986). This model sug- gests that through new media, virtual and physical spaces intersect each other simultaneously, continuously creating new spaces, all of which co-exist in a non- hierarchical structure. New media artworks are a perfect illustration of these new spatial heterotopias. In new media art works – as George Legrady, theorist and practitioner in the field of digital media, wrote as early as 1999 – metaphorical and virtual spaces always intersect with physical spaces: ‘In the process of interacting with the digital world, we can consider real space as the site where our bodies come into contact with the technological devices by which we experience virtual space’ (Legrady 1999, 105). Legrady describes the embodied visual or sensual experience of the viewer when looking at new media art in physical spaces like museums but also on computer screens. The artworks themselves are, as he emphasises, immater- ial, however: ‘Artists who create in digital media can produce works that do not require embodiment in a physical object. These works are free from the con- straints of materiality as they exist as numeric data’ (ibid., 106). Legrady argues that the artwork, ‘free from the constraints of materiality’, arrives at an intersec- tion of the virtual and the real when it is being viewed and experienced. In his argument, Legrady puts the immateriality of the artwork first, but what about the other end of the process, the initial making of the art work? Before becoming what Legrady calls ‘immaterial’, there must have been a form of interaction be- tween the maker and the digital building blocks of the artwork under construc- tion, equally embodied as the experience of the viewer of the finished piece. It follows that the artwork only seems to be immaterial in between making and viewing, while the processes of production (when the artwork is made) and per- ception (when the artwork is experienced) imply materiality through human con- tact. Just as the act of perceiving is bound to a physical location, so the physical interaction between the artwork and its maker must have a location of some sort, somewhere within the heterotopia of intersecting virtual and physical spaces. Where then could the creative space of the new media artist be located, and how do artists describe it? An artist of the Amsterdam KKEP collective (www. kkep.com) once told me about the process of making a collaborative piece in the early years of the Internet. While she was in Amsterdam and her collaborator in New York, they would work in the ‘natural’ shifts dictated by the time difference and send their work back and forth to one another via the Internet. Not only did they get twice as much work done as they would have in the same time zone, they also profited from the creative input of the different environments they lived in. I interviewed Joanna Griffin, who works with the visualisation of satellite data, at the Utrecht Impakt Festival 2004 about her ideal working space. She described it as ‘a place where I can plug in my computer and make coffee’. In both cases, the physical location of the artist overlaps with the creative space to a certain extent, yet the latter is obviously much more than somewhere to plug

272 digital material in the computer and make coffee. The creative space is much more difficult to mark out. Can it be found at the desk, in front of the computer, or rather at the intersection of the physical and the machine world, the human-computer inter- face? Is it the computer itself, like the practice of case-modding suggests, creating visual spectacle by turning the outside of the computer into a personalised arte- fact (Simon 2007); is it inside the computer where software programs like Photo- shop, Maya or Paint mimic the artist’s studio with its traditional tools and materi- als; or is it in the virtual space beyond the machine? Or is it in all these places at the same time: an oscillating creative space; an artistic new media heterotopia? While the last option, the oscillating creative space, is the most likely answer, this space is at the same time the least tangible and concrete. More insight into the possible structure of this creative working space may be gained from the field of computer science. In order to design collaborative virtual environments, much research has been carried out into the spatial experience of users who engage and work with digital technologies. A basic outcome has been that users move about in multiple, simultaneous and hybrid spaces. Letting go of the spatial dichotomy between (pure) physical and virtual spaces provides a parallel with the theory of the digital heterotopia as described by Poster. Computer science, however, needs to move beyond theoretical concepts in order to translate the spatial hybrids back into concrete designs. During this process, the new spatial conditions (which, as illustrated above, tend to evade exact positioning) need to be redefined outside the restrictive terminology of geographical location. In order to do so, Paul Dour- ish, Professor of Computer Science at the University of California, Irvine, intro- duced the distinction between space and place in his call for a social design for collaborative virtual environments (Dourish 2001). This concept, borrowed from the social sciences, allows for a non-geographical definition of the new spatial situation because it adds yet another layer to the hybridisation of digital and phy- sical space: the flexible meaning of spaces in their form as place. According to Harrison and Dourish, spaces are part of the material out of which places can be built. Dealing with physical structure, topology, orientation and connectedness, spaces offer opportunities and constraints. Places, on the other hand, reflect cul- tural and social understandings. Places can also have temporal properties; the same space can be different places at different times (Harrison and Dourish 2001, 73).3 Dourish’s differentiation between space and place also helps to identify the creative working space of the artist: it is a socially and culturally shaped place, created from the hybrid fabric of virtual and physical spaces. On a conceptual level, this definition brings us closer to the whereabouts of the artist at work in the digital domain. But it still does not help to visualise this place. On the con- trary, the oscillating, creative virtual and physical space/place seems to resist re- presentation even more than it evades verbal description, maybe because there is no fixed space left to depict anymore. hidden practice 273 The visibility of digital tools and materials While the creative space seems to defy representation, there are other ingredients of the art-making process that do not. These are the tools and materials of the new media artist in or at the computer. Just like the creative space, tools oscillate between a physical and virtual presence, because the keyboard, mouse, pen – or in the case of touch screens the hand itself – are tangible devices translating movement into digital action on the screen. Most of the time, the virtual part of the tool is represented by an icon referring to a familiar device of non-digital origin, like the brush, pen, eraser or spray-can; in other cases the specificity of a digital action has been related to icons previously alien to the studio like for in- stance the lasso or the magic wand.4 The physical tool can operate a variety of different, even opposing, virtual tools. For example, the mouse controls the eraser as well as the clowning device in a paint program. Yet in spite of their hybrid structure and seemingly simplified functions, the tools demand a user just as skilled and sensitive to their creative potential as do ‘traditional’ tools, as Malcolm McCollough pointed out in his important study, Abstracting craft (1996). Recently, Richard Sennett argued along the same lines in his manifesto for a re-evaluation of craftsmanship (2008). Digital materials are more evasive than tools because they have no physical component but are entirely virtual. Yet even in the virtual domain, they oscillate between two shapes. On the surface, they resemble artistic material of the physi- cal domain (images, paint, brushstrokes, colour, etc.). On a different level they are software, part of software, or in their purest form, code. A simple example is the HTML code attached to colour shades. The fact that digital tools and materials are ultimately represented in such forms could turn them into an interesting ele- ment of the hypothetical representations (so far) of the new media artist at work. However, where the brushes and palettes, chisels and rulers, marble slabs and paint tubes, paper and charcoal of pre-digital artists figure prominently in the (self)-portraits discussed above, there is no comparable elevation of their digital counterparts discernable yet. It is indeed hard to imagine a depiction of a mouse or a brush icon being done as lovingly and romantically as, for example, the tools in François Bonvin’s Attributes of Painting where palette and brushes symbolise the creative process. Taking into account the recognition of digital craft and craftsmanship, it could be merely a question of time until digital tools are used in representations to evoke the magical aura of artistic creation. In this context, we may observe that digital tools and materials have not shed the iconic or symbolic bond with their precursors, as the media theorem of the ‘horseless carriage’ syndrome would have it. On the contrary, the current devel- opment of design software strives for an ever more perfect imitation of the mate- riality and tangibility of traditional artistic tools. The desire for a reconciliation of

274 digital material Figure 2: François Bonvin, Attributes of painting, late 19th century (Courtesy Barber In- stitute of Fine Arts, Birmingham) the senses of vision and touch, separated by the digitalisation of creative pro- cesses, is present in the amazingly precise imitation of artistic materials, from different sorts of digital canvas to virtual oil-paint that actually needs to dry, to applications simulating the direct/immediate touch and feel of virtual paint and brushes in 3D environments (for example, Baxter et al. 2004). These developments in the design sector push towards the frontier of what Jay David Bolter and Richard Grusin have called the myth of ‘transparent immediacy’ (Bolter and Grusin 1999). In this ideal and never completely realisable state, the user could become ignorant of all traces of mediation and ‘handle’ digital materi- als and tools directly. One might ask if the continuous effort to recreate tradi- tional materiality in virtual environments does not restrain the development of tools and materials of an essentially digital nature, without precursors in the non-digital domain. So far, the metaphor of the painter’s, sculptor’s or architect’s tools and materials proves to be much harder to shake off than that of the creative space where the tools and materials are handled, which easily gave way to new forms of hybridisation. It is interesting to see how digital tools, now they have become tangible and have re-appropriated, as it were, the aura of traditional creation, also become hidden practice 275 attractive for representation. I will illustrate this with two examples; one is an educational application, the other an artwork. The I/O Brush is a multimedia tool for children, developed by researchers in the MIT Media Lab. It is an oversized brush with a wooden handle and bristles that incorporates a small camera. With the brush, the children are able to film a cer- tain structure or surface and then ‘paint’ with this image on a digital canvas (the application is reminiscent of the ‘image-hose’ in paint programs). The central notion is the effortless incorporation of real-world materials into digital art proj- ects. In the articles describing the I/O brush (Ryoaki 2004) and on the MIT website (http://web.media.mit.edu/~kimiko/iobrush), photographs and short films show the fun and ease with which the children use the ingenious combination of digital technology and tangible tool. Watching the little artists at work, the viewer is immediately convinced of the success of the brush.

Fugure 3: Child working with I/O Brush

Daniel Rozin’s art project Easel (1998) functions in a comparable way. A computer screen is set on a painter’s easel so that it appears as a traditional canvas. On the ‘canvas’ gallery visitors may combine and modify live video images and material from the Internet with a digital device mimicking a brush. Rozin describes his work as ‘a group made of two pieces that build on the concept of painting with video. The pieces in this group are truly interactive as the visitors are encouraged not only to incorporate their image into the piece but to actively paint and change the whole appearance of the piece, becoming the artists themselves’ (http:// smoothware.com/danny/neweasel.html). It is essential to this concept that Ro- zin’s artwork is neither just the easel with the digital canvas, nor the various

276 digital material Figure 4: Computer animator at work works the eventual users will create. The work of art is the sum of the whole interactive process of creating images. In both cases, the focus lies on image-making, and the visuals explaining the I/O Brush and Easel present us with the creative engagement of users: a child hand- ling the brush, a gallery visitor painting. These representations, which are ob- viously related to the iconography of the painter at his easel and the depiction of the artist at work in the art documentary discussed above, form part of a visual tradition I want to call ‘showing making’. The difference is that they do not show the creators of I/O Brush or Easel at work, but those who interact with the finished product. We see how intricate technologies have disappeared behind the meta- phor of painting, enabling others to use them within the familiar frame of tradi- tional artistic practice. The creative practices of those who constructed these tech- nologies remain hidden.

The making-of in computer graphics and animation So far, the search for the representation of artistic practice in the digital domain has been rather unsuccessful. Yet there is an area of digital image-making where hidden practice 277 processes of production are almost excessively represented: the field of computer graphics and . Here, ‘showing making’ has even been de- fined as a separate genre, the making-of. As a genre the making-of is much older than computer graphics, but through the use of digital image manipulation in film, it has gained tremendously in popularity (Hight 2005). This is due to the new form of image creation. Artificially created photo- and hyper-realistic images captivate viewers because they have no indexical equivalent in the real world. Things, people, places that never existed, or do not exist anymore (e.g. dino- saurs), and events that never took place or are impossible to film in the real world may be visualised with the help of a computer (cf. Jones 1989, Moskovich 2002). As such, these spectacular visuals seem to undermine the paradigm of indexicality associated with photography and film.5 A way to appeal to the fascination and apprehension caused by computer gra- phics is to show how these images were generated. This can be for explanatory as well as commercial reasons. In a traditional making-of, the viewer gets a peek ‘behind the scenes’, listens to the director’s erudite commentary, watches actors being interviewed on the set and witnesses hilarious bloopers. The making-of of computer-animated scenes looks rather different. It is much more static. Most of the time we see animators or technicians sitting in front of computers, displaying skilful manipulation of tools and digital materials while the images they create come into being on a screen. Glancing over the shoulder of computer wizards, we might witness the different stages of a spectacular stunt, like the ‘bullet time’ effect in the Matrix Trilogy (Wachowsky Brothers 1999-2002) or the building of an underwater anemone in Finding Nemo (Stanton and Unkrich 2003) on its way to photorealism, from wire-frame animation to a full-coloured and shaded se- quence. The formal set up of these making-ofs bears a close resemblance to the iconography of the atelier scenes discussed above. The genre also answers to the same visual paradox. Practice is displayed with- out giving away the secret of the actual ‘how to’. Showing the computer animator at the screen does not deconstruct visual illusion. If this were the case, we would probably not enjoy watching making-ofs. Yet, regardless of their promise to reveal the making of illusion, the genre does not destroy but rather enhances the plea- sure of looking. Part of this pleasure is achieved because we learn about the amount of work and skill invested in the creation of illusionist imagery. This knowledge causes the viewer to admire the dexterity and competence of the ma- ker(s). Knowing how much effort has been invested in its creation might also heighten the desire to become immersed in the image (Hediger 2005). Moreover, the stimulation of awe is of economic value as the making-of is a way to display the power to shape technology (‘only we can create these images’).

278 digital material Hidden practice Although a fixed mode to represent practice does exist, new media artists gener- ally do not use the making-of to reflect on their practice. This might be for a number of reasons, such as the commercial aspect and the predetermined ap- pearance of the genre. But predominantly, an artist might not employ the visual strategies of the making-of because it is so closely tied to the creation of photo- realist or at least figurative imagery. This is also the reason why the making-of can seamlessly tie back into the visual vocabulary of the painter in front of the easel. Mimicking reality and creating visual illusion profits by showing or show- ing off practice, be it in the 16th or in the 21st century. Yet today’s new media creative practices encompass infinitely more strategies than the representation of realistic computer-generated imagery. Artists who operate within this set of para- digms seem to prefer not to represent themselves (at work) at all. To summarise, the process of artistic practice seems to be rendered invisible by a variety of factors: the metaphor of the laboratory; the difficulties in describing and visualising the procedures of data programming; the hybridisation of creative space; and the multiplicity of artistic practice within this space. Practice itself does become visible, but only in certain instances, dissociated from the artist. It ap- pears in the digital tools mimicking analogue predecessors, in digital materials like software and data, or in interactive art-works engaging the viewer/user. How- ever, the embodied representation of the artist at work only resurfaces when crea- tive practice remediates traditional modes of art making, like the affirmative crea- tion of realities in computer graphics and animation. Two conclusions are possible. Either the representation of artists at work has become obsolete in new media art practice and the mystification of artistic crea- tion has finally been discarded, or the representation of practice has become just as hybridised as the space in which it takes place. It has been shown above that the representation of practice can mystify or even fetishize the creative act. At the same time, ‘showing making’ counteracts mystification because it can reveal the intricate interactions between actors, technologies, tools and materials, making artistic creation and visualising procedures comprehensible. As such, the poten- tial of the genre is much too exciting to be abandoned. Most likely, creative prac- tice in the digital domain is still in search of representation.

An earlier version of this essay appeared in Computers and the history of art vol. 3, eds. A. Bentkowska-Kafel, T. Cashen, and H. Gardiner, Chicago: Intellect Books 2009.

Notes 1. An exception is Olia Lialina’s article ‘A Vernacular Web. The Indigenous and The Bar- barians’, http://art.teleportacia.org/observation/vernacular.

hidden practice 279 2. For a critical discussion of the ideal of participatory culture, see the chapters by Mirko Tobias Schäfer and Eggo Müller in this book. 3. Michel de Certeau defines space and place in an opposing manner, see the chapter by Sybille Lammes in this book. 4. So far, little research has been conducted on the history and development of tool meta- phors for paint programs. For a general overview see, Alvey Ray Smith (2001). On the sometimes confusing, metaphorical relation of computer icons with computer pro- cesses, see the chapter by Marianne van den Boomen in this book. 5. This complex issue is a frequently discussed problem in new media studies, see the chapter by Frank Kessler in this book. See also William J. Mitchell (1992), Barbara Sa- vedoff (1997) and Lev Manovich (2001).

References Alpers, Svetlana. 1998. The studio, the laboratory, and the vexations of art. In Picturing science, producing art, eds. Peter Galison, Caroline A. Smith, 401-417. New York: Rout- ledge. Baxter, William, Jeremy Wendt and Ming C. Lin. 2004. IMPaSTo: a realistic, interactive model for paint, NPAR ‘04: Proceedings of the 3rd international symposium on non-photorealistic animation and rendering. ACM June 2004. Bolter, David Jay, and Richard Grusin. 1999. Remediation: Understanding new media. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Bolter, David Jay, and D. Gromala 2003. Windows and mirrors: Interaction design, digital art, and the myth of transparency. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Cole, Michael, and Mary Pardo eds. 2005. of the studio: Renaissance to . Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Couldry, Nick, Anne McCarthy eds. 2004. Mediaspace: Place, scale and culture in a media age. London: Routledge. Dourish, Paul. 2001. Where the action is: The foundation of embodied interaction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Foucault, Michel. 1986. Of other spaces. Diacritics 16 (1): 22-27 (also at http://foucault.info/ documents/heteroTopia/foucault.heteroTopia.en.html). Greene, Rachel. 2004. Internet art. London: Thames and Hudson. Harrison, Steve, Paul Dourish. 2001. Re-place-ing space: The role of space and place in collaborative systems. Computer supported cooperative work: Proceedings of the 1996 ACM con- ference on Computer supported cooperative work, 67-76. Boston, Massachusetts. Hayles, N. Katherine. 2002. Flesh and metal: Reconfiguring the mindbody in virtual envi- ronments. Configurations 10 (2): 297-320. Hayward, Philip. 1988. Echoes and reflections: The representation of representation. In Picture this: Media representations of visual art and artists, ed. Philip Hayward, 1-26. London: John Libbey. Hediger, Vinzenz. 2005. Spaß an harter Arbeit: Der Making of-Film. S. 332-341. In Dem- nächst in ihrem Kino: Grundlagen der Filmwerbung und Filmvermarktung. Marburg: Schüren Verlag. Hight, Craig. 2005. Making-of documentaries on DVD: The Lord of the Rings trilogy and special editions. The Velvet Light Trap 56 (3): 5-17.

280 digital material Jones, Beverly. 1989. Computer imagery: Imitation and representation of realities. Leonardo: Journal of the International Society for the Arts, Sciences and Technology. Supplemental Issue: Computer Art in Context: 31-38. Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Legrady, George. 1999. Intersecting the virtual and the real: Space in interactive media installations. Wide Angle 21 (1): 104-113. Lehmann, Ann-Sophie. 2006. Wat de hand weet: De kunstenaar aan het werk. In Atelierge- heimen: Over de werkplaats van de kunstenaar vanaf 1200 tot heden, eds. Mariette Haveman, E. de Jong, Ann-Sophie Lehmann, and Annemiek Overbeek, 120-141. Amsterdam: Kunst en Schrijven. Manovich, Lev. 2001. The language of new media. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. McCullough, Malcolm. 1996. Abstracting craft: The practiced digital hand. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Mitchell, William J. 1992. The reconfigured eye: Visual truth in the post-photographic era. Cam- bridge, MA: MIT Press. Moskovich. Julia. 2002. To infinity and beyond: Assessing the technological imperative in computer animation. Screen 43 (3): 293-314. Paul, Christiane. 2003. Digital art. London: Thames and Hudson. Poster, Mark. 2004. Digitally local communications: Technologies and space. Paper pre- sented at conference The global and the local in mobile communication: Places, images, people, connections. Budapest. (http://www.locative.net/tcmreader/index.php?cspaces;poster). Ryoaki, K., S. Marti, H. Ishii. 2004. I/O Brush: Drawing with everyday objects as ink. Pro- ceedings of the SIGCHI conference on Human factors in computing systems, 303-310. Vienna, Austria. Savedoff, Barbara. 1997. Escaping reality: Digital imagery and the resources of photogra- phy. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (2): 202-214. Sennett, Richard. 2008. The craftsman. London: Allen Lane. Simon, Bart. 2007. Geek chic: Machine aesthetics, digital gaming, and the cultural politics of the case . Games and Culture 2 (3): 175-193. Stallabrass, Julian. 2003. Internet art: The online clash of culture and commerce. London: Tate Publishing. Smith, Alvey Ray. 2001. Digital paint systems: An anecdotal and historical overview. IEEE Annals of the 23 (2): 4-30. Wilson, Steven. 2002. Information arts: A survey of art and research at the intersection of art, science and technology. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

hidden practice 281

About the authors

Marianne van den Boomen is lecturer-researcher at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. Her research focuses on media philosophy and metaphors.

Marinka Copier is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. Her research focuses on games, (role) play cultures and education.

Isabella van Elferen is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. In her research she seeks links between media, mu- sic, and philosophy.

Frank Kessler is professor of media history at the Department of Media and Cul- ture Studies at Utrecht University. His research focuses on early cinema, emer- ging media and theoretical reconsiderations of the dispositif.

Erna Kotkamp is lecturer-researcher at the Department of Media and Culture Stu- dies at Utrecht University. She conducts research on the methodology and design of e-learning software in relation to learning theories.

Sybille Lammes is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. Her main research subjects are related to games and digital cartographies as socio-spatial cultures.

Ann-Sophie Lehmann is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Cul- ture Studies at Utrecht University. Her research is concerned with the history, theory, and practice of image making in old and new media cultures.

Jos de Mul is professor of philosophical anthropology at the Erasmus University of Rotterdam. His versatile work includes many publications about the philoso- phical dimensions of new media cultures.

Eggo Müller is associate professor at the Department of Media and Culture Stu- dies at Utrecht University. Television as medium, popular culture and participa- tion are his main research areas.

283 David B. Nieborg is PhD student at the Amsterdam School for Cultural Analysis (ASCA) and lecturer at the University of Amsterdam. His publications explore the interaction between commercial game culture, technology, marketing, and mili- tary communities.

Eva Nieuwdorp is teacher-researcher at the Department of Media and Culture Stu- dies at Utrecht University. She is writing a PhD about pervasive games.

Thomas Poell is lecturer-researcher at the Department of Media and Culture Stu- dies at Utrecht University. His research mainly deals with historical questions of media and democratization.

Joost Raessens is associate professor at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. His main research interests are playful identities, serious games and the playful use of media.

Douglas Rushkoff is a writer and professor of media culture at New York Univer- sity’s Interactive Telecommunications Program and a founding member of Tech- norealism. His research focuses on media, society, and change.

Mirko Tobias Schäfer is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Cul- ture Studies at Utrecht University. His research focuses on participatory culture and culture industries.

William Uricchio is professor and director of comparative media studies at MIT and professor of comparative media history at Utrecht University in the Nether- lands. His research considers the transformation of media technologies into cul- tural practices.

Nanna Verhoeff is associate professor at the Department of Media and Culture Studies at Utrecht University. Her research concentrates on emerging media, in particular on historical as well as contemporary screen media as sites for virtual mobility.

Imar de Vries is assistant professor at the Department of Media and Culture Stu- dies at Utrecht University. His research areas include mobile telephony as ideal communication and media archaeologies.

Berteke Waaldijk is professor of language and culture studies at Utrecht Univer- sity. Her research concentrates on the history of gender, culture and citizenship.

284 digital material Index

A anthropomorph 122, 124, 173 Abu Ghraib 193 Apoptygma Berzerk 121-122, 127- access 136, 142 130 accumulation 149-150, 155 apparatus 11, 21-23, 25, 27, 29, actor 9-10, 121, 128-129, 162-163, 31, 33, 83, 86, 88, 104, 210, 212, 169 220, 253, 262 actor network 161-162 apparatus theory 21 actor-network theory 162, 168 gaming apparatus 21, 26, 32 advertising 45 application 210 aesthetics 15, 95, 101-102 appropriation 9, 13, 15, 147-148, affordances 10, 12, 15, 84-85, 137, 150-153 144, 151, 153, 155, 194 Apter, M. 205 afilmic 192-193, 195 arcade hall 37 Age of Empires 223, 229 archive 135, 193 agency 13, 25, 121-124, 126, 128, archiving 13, 149-150, 155 130-131, 151 Argent Dawn 159 agent 13, 23, 121, 124, 126, 130- Aristotle 175 131, 144 Arnold, M. 85 Agent Smith 121 art 98, 270 Ahrendt, R. 130 digital art 268 Aibo 151, 157 net.art 271 Aktenzeichen XY 52-54, 56 new media art 267, 270, 272 al Qaeda 38 artificial intelligence 121 Alberti’s window 201 artwork 267 algorithm 139 attention deficit disorder 177 amateur culture 59 attention economy 176 American Idol 50 attention span 177 America’s Army 11, 36, 141, 145 attraction 110-111, 115 America’s Most Wanted 51-52 Attributes of Painting 274 analog/digital 136, 138 audience 139, 175, 179 Anderson, D. 160 active audience 50-51 Andrejevic, M. 50-51, 55 augmented reality 200 animation 193, 215, 268, 277-279 aura 96-99, 103, 268-270, 275 anime 145 Austin, J.L. 262 anonimity 110 authenticity 41, 45, 96, 187-188 anthropology 9 authorship 55, 114, 137, 145, 181

285 automation 191 Bradley, B. 110 autonomy 124 branding 36 avatar 23, 125, 160, 163, 217, 219, Braque, G. 271 228-229 Brecht, B. 53, 112 bricolage 152 B broadband 139 Bacon, F. 269 broadcast 43, 53-59, 61, 174, 176 Baker, V. 168 Brown, B. 213 Barbrook, R. 108 browser 258 Barlow, J.P 107 Bruns, A. 148-149 Barthes, R. 114, 145, 191-192, 194 Buffalo Bill 111 Battlefield 2 39 bulletin boards 65 Baudrillard, J. 22, 220 Bunting, H. 271 Baudry, J.-L. 21 Bush, G. 103 Bauhaus 123 business model 109, 117, 148, 153 Bazin, A. 188, 195 Beavis and Butt-head 180 C Bela Lugosi’s Dead 123 cademe 191 Benjamin, W. 12, 95, 114 Caesar, J. 270 Benkler, Y. 245 Caillois, R. 199, 205 Benschop, A. 247, 249 calculation 191 Bey, H. 108 calculus 179 Big Brother 50-51, 54-56, 59 Call of Duty 4: Modern Warfare 35, BitTorrent 152, 157 39 black box 253, 261-263, 270-271 Callon, M. 162 Blackboard 12, 65, 68, 75 camera 189-190, 267, 276 Blizzard Entertainment 163 Cameron, A. 108 blogs 15, 58, 136-137, 144, 240, Campbell, S. 86 244, 246, 248-249 capitalism 25, 38 blog post 244-245 Cartesian 112 blog roll 244 analysis 181 blogosphere 244 imagery 112 Bob Dylan 122 split 112 body 83, 123, 175, 214, 216-217 cartography 14, 181, 219, 223, Bolter, J.D. 254, 264, 275 225, 227, 232-233 Bonvin, F. 274 Casetti, F. 26, 29 Boomen, M. van den 3, 15-16, 118, Castells, M. 83, 160-161, 169 253, 280, 283 Castronova, E. 165 Borg 124 causality 105 bot nets 152 causation 191, 258 Botfighters 199 Cavell, S. 194 Botting, B. 124 Centre Georges Pompidou 9

286 digital material Certeau, M. de 14, 219, 223-227, ideal 81-82, 84-85, 88, 90-91 229-230, 280 instrumental 85 chaos math 181 mobile 81, 83, 85, 87, 89, 91, character 168, 175, 179 93 in-character 163, 169 communication studies 8 out-of-character 169 communitarian 183 chat 70, 113, 144, 152, 164 community 25, 36, 40, 53, 56, 87, cheat code 179 108, 126, 138, 140-142, 144, 148- chip 142 149, 152-153, 155, 164, 176, 241, cinema 8 271 early cinema 193 fan 149, 154 cinematography 124, 187 production 148 citizenship 12, 53-54, 107, 109, virtual 8, 109, 177 111, 113-115, 117-119, 243 complexity 74-75, 162, 169 national 107 computer 7, 99, 101 civic engagement 148 graphics 149, 268, 278-279 civil society 54 icon 10, 255-259, 261, 280 Civilization 223-224, 227-228, 231 computer science 273 Claroline 65 computer-generated imagery 154, class 108, 111, 115 279 Clouzot, H.-G. 269 configuration 255, 261, 263 code 163, 168-169, 227, 231, 271, connectivity 82, 84-85, 87-88, 90- 274 91, 109, 139, 143, 183, 215-216 human code 253-254, 258, Consalvo, M. 167 260 console 183, 210-211, 213, 219- machine code 254, 258, 260 220 collaboration 122, 137-138, 149, construction 149, 155 151-152 consumer capitalism 182 collaborative 40, 138, 140, 168, consumer-producer 221 272-273 consumers 32, 57, 114-115, 117, intelligence 53 143, 147 learning 66-68 consumption 11, 13, 50, 54, 110, media 143 113-115, 138, 150 play 162 content 12-13, 27, 71, 142, 144, collective intelligence 114, 117, 148-149, 154, 176-177 138, 143, 148 control 89, 112, 114, 116 collectivism 149 convergence 148, 213, 217 colonialism 112 convergence culture 31 commerce 37, 110, 113, 115, 118 conversion 191 commercials 104, 175 cookie 117 communication 12, 68, 71-72, 81- Cooley, H.R. 214 82, 84, 86-87, 91, 108, 110, 116 Coombes, A. 111 index 287 Copier, M. 13, 159, 184, 207, 283 Darth Vader 121, 124, 174 copy 98, 194 Darwinism 101 copying 149, 151 data 72-73, 84, 100, 117, 136, 138, copyright 56, 140, 145 141, 149, 152, 154-155, 190, 272, Corvus Corax 128 279 Cosic, V. 271 data carrier 9 counter public 109, 239, 246 data records 100 Counter-Strike 42 database 95, 100-103, 105 counterculture 178 art 104 craft 274 design 100 Cronenburg, D. 124 ontology 12, 99-100, 103, 105 Cronkite, W. 174 relational 100 cross-media 54-55, 59 Davenport, G. 110 Crutzen, C. 74 Davis, A. 74 cult value 95, 97-98 Declaration of Independence 108 cultural deconstruction 26, 29, 113, 176, freedom 148 180 heritage 135, 137, 140 Deleuze, G. 21, 125 production 137, 153 demo scene 149-150 cultural studies 8-9, 50 democracy 8, 38, 99, 108-109, culture 240, 245 music 131 Depeche Mode 126-127 writing 114 depresentation 256, 260 culture industries 148, 150, 154 design 10-11, 13, 33, 42, 66, 70, Cumiskey, K. 87 110, 113, 138, 147, 151-153, 201, curator 102 267, 270, 273, 275 Cure, The 126 desire 22, 26-27, 32, 84-85, 88, Cürlis, H. 269 90 cyber-discourse 8 desktop 253, 255 cyberculture 124 Deus ex machina 175 cyberspace 8-9, 22-24, 26, 33, device 81, 88, 201 108-109, 124 mobile 12, 81-83, 86-88, 91 cyborg 122, 126, 131 Dewey, J. 66 Cyworld 141 dialectic 123 Digg 138 D digital daguerreotype 195 activism 116 Dahl, O-J. 72 and analog 188, 190-191 Dahlberg, L. 243 digital art 12, 15, 268 Dalgaard, D. 65 digital artefacts 10 dance 111 digital culture 7, 9-10, 109, Daniel, S. 105 136, 139-140

288 digital material digital divide 8, 109 E digital material 7 e-books 136 digital materialism 8 e-commerce 177 digital mysticism 8 E-Democracy.org 243 digital recombination 99, 102- e-journal 142 103 e-learning environment 65, 67, digital turn 13, 135, 138-139, 69, 71, 73, 75, 77 145 e-mail 10, 39, 70, 136, 164 digitalization 187, 190 Easel 276-277 Digital Rights Management 152 Ecole de filmologie 192 digitalization 136, 142 Edison 111 Dijck, J. van 57-58 eDonkey 152, 157 discipline 114 education 45, 74-75, 107, 114-115 discourse 81-82, 84, 192-193, 195, edutainment 29 246 Electronic Body Music 126 discourse analysis 8 electronic writing 9 discussion forum 70, 73 Elf Fantasy Fair 161 DiskoAibo 156 Elferen, I. van 13, 121, 283 dispositif 10, 14-15, 194-195, 210, emancipation 86, 108, 115, 246 213, 221 women 113 dissemination 83 embodied interaction 202 distribution 37, 56-57, 135-136, embodiment 110 139, 142, 144, 150-152, 193 emote 164 diversity 245 encoding 29 DIY () 176-177 encryption 140 documentary 187, 190, 192-193, end user license agreement 113 195-196, 269, 277 engineer 267 Donkey Kong 211 Enron 143 DOS computer 177 entertainment 11, 37, 81, 107, 110, dot.com bubble 177-178 113-115, 118, 139, 183, 227, 242 Douglas, F. 115-116 industry 111, 115 Dourish, P. 202, 273 enunciator 193 Downey, J. 246 epic 174 download 57, 113, 152, 154 Eshun, K. 122 Dracula 123 essentialism 110 drawing 214 ethnicity 108, 115-116 drum computer 122, 128-129 ethnography 160, 162-163, 165 Duchamp, M. 101 auto-ethnography 160, 164, Dungeons and Dragons 160 168 Dutch Photo Museum 102 practice theory 52 dystopia 8, 22, 24, 49-50, 59, 108, virtual ethnography 8 121, 126 Everquest 160, 165 index 289 Exchangeable Image File 154 Foucault, M. 145, 271 exclusion 107-108, 110 fractal 181 exhibition value 12, 95, 98, 102- frame 28-29, 32, 166, 169-170, 103, 105 193 eXistenZ 124 Frankenstein 121, 123, 126 eyeballs 177 Frasca, G. 29 Eyespot 154 freedom 114-115, 118 freeware 176 F Freud, S. 122 Facebook 155 Friedberg, A. 216, 219 Faithless 124 Friedman, T. 224-225, 227-229 fan Friendster 138, 141 archives 149 Front 242 126 communities 50, 179 frontier 230 culture 54, 145 Fuller, M. 16, 224, 227 fantasy 34, 112, 124, 166, 170, 199- functionality 70-71, 212 201 futurism 182 Fantasy 160-162, 165, 168, 170 fascism 99 G Feindflug 126 Gadamer, H.G. 97 Felix, B. 59 gadget 210, 212, 214, 216, 219 feminism 110, 115 Gailitis, V. 233 Fenton, N. 246 game 10, 24, 108, 123, 141, 160, Ferry Corsten remix 128 165, 176, 199, 205, 227 fetish 269, 279 game characters 211 file sharing 142, 147, 152 game console 153, 210, 216 file-transfer protocol 152 game culture 40, 180 film 14, 135-136, 140, 188, 191, game devices 211 195, 269, 278 game engine 37 film studies 26 game industry 31 filter 189 game play 160, 166, 168, 211, Finding Nemo 278 230 Fine, G.A. 161, 166, 169 game research 165-167 First Person Shooter 35, 42 game space 41, 165-166, 169, FirstClass 65 206 Fitna 103 game theory 41 Flickr 109, 141, 154-155, 193 game world 199-200, 204 Flores, F. 259 Game Boy 151, 156, 209 FOK!forum! 239, 241-242, 247 game studies 8, 26, 32, 112 Food Force 21, 26-32 gamers 13, 35, 173, 182 format 45, 51, 55, 58, 60, 70-71, games 13-14, 35, 136, 140, 143- 143, 210 144, 159, 211, 223

290 digital material advergame 37 Goldberg, M. 68 board game 161 Google 51, 56 card game 161 Google Blog Search 240, 244 edugame 22, 24, 37, 41, 45 Google Earth 233 epistemic game 25 Google Video 56 Fantasy role-playing game 160 Gothic 122-126, 129-131 mobile game 200 novel 122-124, 129-131 multiplayer game 36, 211 theory 122 online role-playing game 13, governance 243 159 government 143 pervasive game 14, 165, 167, GPS 233 170, 199 graphical user interface 152, 253 serious game 11, 21, 23, 25, Green, G. 89 27, 29, 31, 33 Green, N. 92 simulation game 179, 224, Griffin, J. 272 227-228 Grokster 142 single-player PC game 26 Grudin, J. 201 strategy game 228-230, 232 Grusin, R. 264, 275 war game 33, 35, 161 Guattari, F. 125, 131 gamezone.com 113 Gunning, T. 190-191, 195 GATE 33 Gygax, G. 160 gaze 112, 116-118 Gee, J.P. 25, 28, 203, 206 H GeenStijl 240, 244, 246, 248 Habermas, J. 15, 239, 241-242, gender 108-110, 115-117 245, 249 Generation C 147 hack 125, 167 genetic engineering 100-101 hackers 153 genre 113 Haley, N. 60 Gergen, K. 83, 87 hands-on 15 ghost writing 215 hardware 9, 15, 72, 181, 201-202, Gibson, W. 124, 152 207, 220, 256 gift economy 176 Harrison, S. 273 Gitelman, L. 108 Harry Potter 40, 149 globalization 109, 233 Hayles, N.K. 253, 262-263, 271 Go Game, The 199, 202, 204, 206 Hedges, C. 41 Goarmy.com 36 Heidegger, M. 15, 253, 258-259, God is a DJ 124 263 Godard, J.-L. 193 Heliö, S. 205 Goffman, E. 165-166, 169-170, Helium Vola 130 204, 206 heterotopia 271-273 Gogh, Theo van 15, 239-240, 243, holograph 181 247-248 home page 143 index 291 homebrew 153, 221 imperialism 111-113, 115 homecasting 57 IMS Global Learning Consortium Homo ludens 162, 165, 167 69 horseless carriage 274 in-game postal system 159 HTML 274 inclusion 107-108 Huizinga, J. 162, 165-167, 170, indexicality 14-15, 105, 188, 190- 203 193, 196, 256, 262-263, 278 human-computer interaction 201, indexing 149, 152 255 Indymedia 241-242, 247-248 human-computer interface 201, information 31, 66, 71-72, 82-84, 273 89-91, 103, 110, 123, 131, 137- Hutcheon, L. 129 138, 190, 192, 194, 269 hybrid media 54 information age 136, 148, 177 hypermediacy 113, 124, 131, 264 information management systems hypertext 8, 114, 193 149 Hyves 109, 155 information retrieval 155 informatization 96 I infrastructure 81-82, 84, 89, 111 I Love Bees 199 institutionalization 51, 57, 59 I/O Brush 276-277 Integrated Development Kit 153 icon 15, 188, 256-257, 274 intellectual property 140, 143-145 iconicity 256, 258, 263 interaction 12, 66, 68, 71-73, 75, iconography 268, 270, 277-278 85, 121, 137, 162, 231, 272, 279 identification 41, 227-228 social 83-84, 86 identity 23, 86, 110, 115, 117, 170, interactive 248-249 audience 53 ideology 8, 11, 21, 24, 32-33 map 219 im/materiality 9 media 178 image 110, 116, 190, 192-195, 268, television 11, 49 276-278 interactivity 23, 26-27, 37, 39, 52- cinematographic image 187 53, 55, 60, 108, 141, 175-176, digital image 14, 99, 187 193, 211-212, 267, 276 image-event 191 interface 9, 11, 14-15, 51, 54, 56, imagery 193 58, 149, 177, 200-201, 207, 210, imaginary 122 219-220, 253-255, 257, 259, immaterial 8, 272, 278 261, 263, 265 immateriality 272 design 212 immediacy 82, 84, 88, 90, 113, game interface 130, 201-202 264, 275 liminal interface 205, 207 immersion 108-109, 111-113, 117, user interface 10, 102 278 intermedial 107, 117 Impakt Festival 272 intermediary 201, 264

292 digital material Internet 81, 107, 147 Kuro5hin 140 Internet Archive 149 Internet community 177 L Internet journalism 177 L.H.O.O.Q. 101 Internet radio 121 La chambre claire 192 Internet studies 8 labor 55, 109, 142, 153, 256 interpassivity 22-23, 27 laboratory 270-271 intertextuality 40, 145 Labyrinth der Sinne 128 IP-number 117 Lakoff, G. 28, 260, 263 IPO (initial public offering) 177 Lammes, S. 3, 14, 16, 184, 223, iPod 35, 121 283 Landow, G. 108, 110, 113 J language 74, 138 Jackson Pollock 269 programming language 151, Jacobson, I. 74 201 Jakobsson, P. 166, 169 Lanham, R. 108, 113 Jefferson, T. 142 Latour, B. 12, 16, 162, 264, 270 Jenkins, H. 27, 31, 51, 59, 148, law enforcement 89 224-225, 227, 231-232, 244, 271 Law, J. 162 JenniCam 193 Le mystère Picasso 269 Jodi 267, 271 Legrady, G. 272 journalism 189 Lehmann, A.-S. 3, 16, 233, 267, joystick 176-177 283 Jurassic Park 101 Les immatériaux 9 Justin Timberlake 127 Lévy, P. 143, 147, 271 LexisNexis 241 K Lialina, O. 267, 271 Kac, E. 101, 105 libertarianism 182 Kahle, B. 143 license 149, 154 Kathy’s Song 121, 127-129 Licoppe, C. 84 Katz, J.E. 90, 93 lifeworld 203, 206-207 KaZaa 144 linearity 182 Kerr, J. 205 Ling, R. 85-86, 88 Kessler, F. 14-15, 187, 280, 283 linguistic turn 95 keyboard 14, 26, 254, 274 LinkedIn 155 Kittler, F. 124 links 86 KKEP 272 Linux 140, 151 knowledge production 66-67, 162 Liout, J.-L. 195 Kopomaa, T. 86 Little Sound DJ 156 Kotkamp, E. 12, 65, 283 live-action roleplaying 161 Kraftwerk 126 liveness 214-215 Krupp 111 LOCKSS 142-144 index 293 Lord of the Rings 40 Match of the day 104 Lovink, G. 244 material 16, 22, 36, 112, 130-131, Løvlie, A.S. 41 187, 194, 269, 273 Lucasfilm 154 material environment 217 ludic space 203 material object 10, 210, 212, ludology 225 220, 260 ludus 199, 205 material turn 9 Lyotard, J.-F. 9 material-semiotic 263 materiality 21, 131, 214, 272, 275 M Matrix, The 121, 125, 278 machine 14, 121, 123, 125, 127- Matuszewski, B. 187-189 129, 131, 220 Maya 273 magic circle 13-14, 159-171, 203, McCarthy, A. 215 207 McChesney, R. 108 mainframe 100 McClintock, A. 115 making-of, the 278 McCollough, M. 274 manga 145 McNair, B. 245 manipulation 140, 189-191, 195 Mead, W.R. 38 value 12, 95, 102-103 meaning 21-22, 32 Manovich, L. 101, 105, 108, 188- mechanization 101 189, 212, 280 media manuscript 179 media determinism 105 map 182, 223, 225-229, 231-232 media development 99 and tour 14, 219, 223 media industry 27, 50, 55, 135, digital map 14, 224, 233 148-149 mapping 223-224, 227-230, media literacy 32, 138, 177, 232 195, 206 market 50, 114, 145, 155, 182, 215, media ontology 136 271 media player 220 marketing 35-36, 40, 50, 117, 210, media text 21, 32, 149-150, 212 152, 154 Marokko Community 241-243, media theory 124 247-248 old and new 13, 217 Marokko Media 241 media studies 8-9 Maslov, A. 101 mediatic turn 95 mass culture 183 mediation 82, 86, 121-122, 125- mass media 58, 89, 138, 239, 241, 126, 128, 259, 261, 275 244-246, 248 mediator 264 massive user interaction 149 medium specificity 8, 15, 21, 99, massively multiplayer online role- 240 playing game 136, 141, 160- Mega Mona Lisa 103 163, 165, 169

294 digital material memory 11, 13, 108, 125, 129, 131, moderation 240, 243 136, 139, 221 modernism 112 memory institution 137, 139-140, modification 151, 232 142 modular 151 Mennecke, T. 157 Mona Lisa 96-98, 102-103 meta-game 180, 182 monitoring 50, 55, 89, 117, 240, meta-information 112 245 metadata 154-155 Montola 167 metaphor 10, 15-16, 28, 61, 149, Moodle 65 165-167, 173, 177, 180, 201, 210, Mosaic 139 221, 253, 258-259, 262, 270- mouse 26, 274 272, 275, 277, 279-280 mp3 10, 121 conceptual metaphor 14, 101, MSN 113 213, 260-263 MTV 128 material metaphor 15, 100, Mul, G. 102, 104 262-263, 265 Mul, J. de 12, 95, 283 method 73, 212 Müller, E. 11, 49, 156, 283 methodology 162 multidisciplinary 8 micro politics 51 multitasking 219 Microsoft 140, 144, 153 Murdoch, R. 176 Microsoft Office 177 museum 113-114 Middleton, R. 122, 126 music 13, 109, 121-123, 125-131, military-industrial complex 39 139-140, 142, 144, 149, 161 millennium bug 121, 123 cybergothic 121 Miller, L. 108 Gothic 130-131 Miller, M. 57 industrial 126, 128, 131 mind 95 music industry 142, 147, 152 Minitel 9 Myerson, G. 84 mise-en-abyme 219 MySpace 35, 109, 138, 155 misinformation campaigns 138 mystic writing pad 215, 221 Missy Elliott 127 myth 89, 173 MIT Media Lab 276 Mitchell, T. 111-112, 114 N Mitchell, W.J. 105 N@tschool 65 Mitchell, W.J.T. 9 Nakamura, L. 108 mobile phone 81, 83, 85, 87, 89, Namuth, H. 269 91, 93, 125, 159, 201 Nanoloop 156 mobility 14, 201, 209-210, 214, Napster 13, 49, 142, 147, 151-153 216-217 narrative 105, 124, 126, 128, 173- modding 29, 167, 273 174, 178, 181-183, 224 mode of address 22, 26 narrativity 13 modem 176 narratology 125 index 295 narrowcasting 57 Nieborg, D.B. 11, 33, 35, 45, 145, NASDAQ 178 284 National Exhibition of Women’s Nieuwdorp, E. 14, 165, 170, 199, Labour 116 284 navigation 179, 182, 219, 232 Nintendo 221, 227-228, 232 Neo 125 Nintendo DS 209 Net.Goth 126 noise 122, 126, 131 netlabel 149-150 Nokia N-Gage 211 network 11, 13, 49, 53, 81, 83, 91, nomadic 125 121, 136, 139-142, 144, 152, 155, Nora, P. 131 160-161, 168-169, 181-182, 196, NRC Handelsblad 241 249, 254, 261, 263 Nye, J. 38 mobile 87 Nygaard, K. 72 network society 91, 160, 169 network theory 161 O news network 140, 143 object 114, 214, 220 social network 85, 87, 141, and subject 233 143, 167 dynamical object 257 Neue Deutsche Härte 128 immediate object 257 Neuromancer 124 physical object 272 new economy 8 theoretical object 210, 213, 220 new media 16, 27, 32, 82, 108, object orientation 72-75 121, 135, 138, 188, 193, 232-233, objectivity 189 271-272 Odin, R. 26-27, 31, 192 early cinema 108 Oedipus 22-24, 32 film 111 off-the-shelf 37 Internet 178 Ogden, P. 269 radio 108 one-way media 175 telephone 108 online communication 239-240, new media art 95, 99 245, 247, 249 new media economy 55-56 ontology 9, 95, 105, 188, 191, 194 new media objects 9 open access 150 new media studies 7-8, 10 open source 140, 142, 144, 150, news 137-138, 176, 239, 241 167, 181, 183, 271 film 193 Orkut 155 photography 187, 189 Other, the 116, 122 television 104 Overpeer 157 news media 32, 45 ownership 140 newspapers 242, 244, 248 O’Reilly, T. 138, 153-154 Nichols, B. 196 nick name 241

296 digital material P pervasiveness 81 P2P, peer-to-peer 121, 142, 147, Pew Research Center 38 152-153 philosophy 8, 95 Packard, P. 28 photography 14, 96, 98, 135-136, paidia 199, 205 140, 187, 190-191, 193-195, 269, Paint 273 278 paint program 276 photorealism 278-279 pamphlet 111 photoshop 151, 273 Panoramio 233 Picasso, P. 271 paradigm 73-75, 278 PictoChat 211 paraludic 205, 207 Pim Fortuyn Forum 241-242, 247- paratelic 205-207 248, 250 Pargman, D. 166, 169 piracy 135 Paris Hilton 98 pixel 136 Parool, Het 241 platform 37, 135, 154, 183, 193, participation 11, 13, 26, 108, 117, 212-213, 220, 239, 245-246, 248 137, 144, 246 play 160, 182, 199, 205, 216, 232 explicit 148, 152-153, 155 and game 206 implicit 148, 153, 155 and reality 199, 201, 206 political 107, 115, 117 instrumental play 163, 168 space of participation 52-58, role play 160, 164, 169 60 rules of play 26, 167, 199, 204, participatory culture 11, 13, 32, 206 49, 51, 59-60, 109, 135, 144, player 21, 112, 141, 162, 168, 200, 147, 149, 151, 153, 155, 157, 271, 202, 205-206, 223-224, 227- 280 232 PDA 201 player-character 159, 164, 168 pedagogy 67, 70, 75 Playing the Angel 127 Peirce, C.S. 15, 188, 195, 253, Pocketnoise 156 256-257, 259, 263 Poell, T. 15, 239, 284 Pelletier, C. 24-29, 32 point of view 30, 42, 226, 246 Pentium 139 politics 95, 102, 104, 138 perception 121, 190, 272 Pong 176 performance 112, 126 popular culture 27, 36, 38-39, 81, performance arts 8 140 performative 84, 125, 196, 224 193 performativity 214, 256 portability 82 perpetual contact 89-91 portal 176 personal electronic device 215 Poster, M. 249, 271, 273 perspective painting 178 posthuman 124 persuasion 40-41 postmodernism 112 pervasive game 199 poststructuralism 113 index 297 power 32, 38-39, 43, 45, 53, 55, publishers 138 66, 103, 108, 110, 113-114, 116- PvE (Player versus Environment) 118, 144-145, 156, 169, 194, 224, 163 230, 232 PvP (Player versus Player) 163 hegemonic 38, 45, 232 ludic power 232 Q Power Unlimited 35 Qntal 130 predicate logic 100 query 100, 103 Prensky, M. 25, 28 presence 30 R absent presence 87, 89, 122, Rabinovitz, L. 115-116 128 radio theory 53 present-at-hand 258-259 Raessens, J. 3, 11, 14, 16, 21, 45, printing press 140, 179, 181 184, 284 privacy 82, 90-91, 117, 143-144 Rammstein 131 pro-ams 147 Rath, C.-D. 53 procedural programming 72-73 Raymond, E. 61 procedure 271 re-enactment 123 processor 10, 142 readership 114, 181 producers 57, 143-144 ready-to-hand 258-259, 263 production 11, 37, 50, 54, 57, 135, Reagan, R. 98, 103 138-139, 150, 189-190, 193, 267, real 271-272, 278 real virtuality 105 means of 99, 101, 151 vs imaginary 166, 169 produsage 148 real, the 130, 187-193, 200 profilmic 192, 195 reality programming 151, 174, 181, 267, and fantasy 166 271 reality television 54-55 Project Gutenberg 149 reception 54, 57 propaganda 11, 36, 111, 115 reconfiguration 26, 29 prosumer 49 recording 126 protest campaigns 246 referent 188, 191, 256 protocol 56, 82, 143 reframing 178-179 psychoanalysis 22 religion 95, 173, 179, 240, 243 Psychological Operations 43 remediation 8, 123, 130, 264 public remote control 175-176 and private 53, 87, 90 renaissance 173, 178, 180, 182 public debate 239 representation 16, 23, 37, 39, 72- public domain 149 74, 104, 107-109, 111-112, 114, public opinion 43 116, 137, 163, 187, 189, 192, 196, public space 87, 108, 115 201, 224, 226, 233, 268, 270, public sphere 15, 199, 239 273-274, 277, 279

298 digital material reproduction 98, 103 screen 14, 165, 190, 201, 204, 207, digital 99, 103 209-213, 220, 254 mechanical 95-96, 98-99, 102 screen media 216 retouching 187, 189 screen space 215, 221 retrieval 11-12, 100 screens within screens 180 Return of the Jedi 174 search request 152 revolution 107, 113-114, 176, 178 Searle, J. 192 Revver 56 Second International 115 rhizomatic 110 security 88, 91 Richardson, I. 216 self 23, 87, 113, 122 Rise of Nations 223 self-governed learning 66 Robocop 101 semantic domain 260 robot 101 semantic information retrieval robotics 151 154 Rodney King videotape 195 semiotics 15, 188, 202, 207, 224, Rodowick, D. 190-191, 194 256, 263 Rodriquez, H. 167 Sennett, R. 274 role play 10, 159-160, 162-164, 168 September 11 38, 90 role-play guild 159, 163 Serres, M. 12 role-play server 159, 163, 168 server 152, 183 Rony, F. 116 set theory 100 Roomba 151, 157 Shaffer, D.W. 25, 28 Rosen, P. 189 Shakespeare, W. 145 Rozin, D. 267, 276 shareware 176 Rule, J. 89 Shelley, M. 121, 126 rules of play 112, 164 Shulgin, A. 271 Rushkoff, D. 13, 125, 173, 284 sign 188, 202, 206, 253-254, 256- Ryan, M.L. 108, 112 259, 262-263 sign-tool 15, 254, 259-260, S 262-263 Saddam Hussein 193 signifier 9, 97, 122, 203, 264 Salen, K. 164-167 Silicon Valley 108 Saussure, F. de 203 Simpsons, The 180 Schäfer, M.T. 3, 13, 16, 147, 184, Simula 72 280, 284 simulacrum 125 Schaffende Hände 269 simulation 29, 32, 37, 39 Schwartz, D. 189 slash fiction 149 Schwarzenegger, A. 175 Slashdot 49, 140 science and technology studies 8, Smythe, D. 56 162 sociability 81-82, 85, 91 science fiction 126, 232 social social conflict 240, 248-249 index 299 social constructivism 65, 67, special effects 174 70-71, 75 spectacle 109 social group 86, 88 spectatorship 32, 124, 193 social media 135, 141-142 spectral 125-126 social movement 246 speech act 192, 262 social network analysis 143 Spielberg, S. 101 social network site 138, 141, spreadsheet 100 155 SQL 100 social relations 111 Squire, K. 32 social space 136 Star Trek 124 vs personal 194 Star Wars 121, 149, 154, 174 socio-technical ecosystem 149 Star Wars MashUp editor 154 socio-technical system 85 Steps, The 21 233 sociology 8-9 stereotype 108 soft power 38-39, 43, 45 stock 189, 196 software 9-10, 15, 72, 74, 151, 176, Stoker, B. 123 181, 201-202, 207, 211, 220, Stone, S. 23 254, 256-257, 260-262, 267, storage 11-12, 142, 150, 190 273-274 stories 13-14 software design 148-149, 154- storytelling 173-175, 178, 180 157 strategic communication 42-43 software development 151 Subcomandante Marcos 161 software object 65, 67, 69, 71- subculture 13, 126, 149 73, 75, 77 cybergoth 128 software studies 8 Goth 122, 131 Sony PlayStation 211 subject 22-23, 233 source domain 260 subject position 113 Sourceforge.net 150 subjectivization 22-23 Souriau, E. 192, 195 Suits, B. 204 Southpark 180 Sunstein, C. 247, 249 space 11, 82-84, 110, 116, 126, 129, surfer 181 160, 215-216, 219, 223-228, surveillance 8, 89, 116-117 230-233, 271-272, 279 suspension of disbelief 202 and map 229 symbol 97 and place 223, 225-227, 233, symbol processing 253 273, 280 symbolic gifts 86 imaginary space 130 symbolic order 22-23, 26-29, 31- physical space 272 32 space of flows 83, 86 synthesizer 122, 126, 128 spatial story 223-225, 227, systems theory 181 229-231 virtual space 110, 271-273

300 digital material T tool 9, 11-12, 15, 29, 32, 37, 39- tactility 214 40, 45, 65, 68-70, 144, 167, 174, tags 114, 141, 154 212, 215, 253-254, 258-259, Tamagotchi 23-25 263, 267, 275 Tanzwut 122, 128-131 materials 267-268, 270, 273- target domain 260 275, 279 Tate Gallery 267 topology 273 Taylor, T.L. 160, 163, 165 touch 14, 209-211, 275 techno-intimacy 87 touch screen 209, 211-214, 274 technoculture 126 transference 254, 259, 261-262 technological determinism 8 transmutability 151 technological imaginary 83 transparency 113, 214 technology 15, 21, 23, 29, 113, Trinity 125 121, 139, 188, 190, 194, 267, Trouw 241 270-271, 277, 279 truth 187, 189, 192 ICT 107 Tsar Nikolas II 187 music 121, 128, 130 Turkle, S. 23, 29, 32 wireless 81-84, 88-90 Turner, V. 205 Technorati 138 Telegraaf, De 241, 245 U teleologic 108 ubiquitous 82 teleplay 174 connectivity 82, 84, 86-87 television 52, 174 gaming 200 Terminator 124 uncanny 121 text UNESCO 143 digital 113-114 United 93 193 messaging 84-88 United Nations World Food Pro- textual form 194 gramme 27 theatre 111 universal machine 151 TheForce.net 149, 154 Unreal 37 thick description 160, 162 upload 56-57 Thing 22 Uricchio, W. 13, 135, 284 thingness 214, 220 user 49, 85, 110, 112-113, 115, 117, Thompson, H. 90 124, 148, 194, 214, 216, 220 three-dimensional 179 user groups 179 Tijdschrift voor Genderstudies user interaction 11, 13, 15, 52, 118 55, 105 timespace 125 user participation 148 Toffler, A. 43 user strategy 84 Toffler, H. 43 user-generated content 50, 57, Tom Clancy’s Ghost Recon Advanced 155 Warfighter 2 35, 39 user-generated data 117 index 301 uses and gratifications 155 VNV Nation 127 utopia 22, 24, 81, 84, 108, 121, vocoder 129 126-127, 271 Volkskrant, de 241, 248 utopian 8-9, 12, 49-50, 55, 59, Vries, I. de 12, 81, 284 156 Utrecht Media Research 8, 15 W W4 (WHO, WHAT, WHEN, WHERE) V 102 Vacanti, C. 101 Waaldijk, B. 12, 107, 284 vanishing point 178 Walther, B.K. 205 Vaughan, D. 195 War on Terror 36, 38 VCR 176 Wario: Master of Disguise 209 vectral 125 Warhol, A. 98 Vent d’Est 193 Water Cooler Games forum 29 Verhoeff, N. 14, 33, 209, 233, 284 Wayback Machine 143-144 videme 191 web 107, 109-110, 113, 117-118 video 193, 276 forum 15, 70, 159, 239, 241, video blog 57 243, 245, 247, 249, 251 video clip 128 Web 2.0 13, 100, 107, 109, 114, video sharing 11, 56, 59 117-118, 138, 140, 148, 153-154 viewer 113, 115-116, 194, 269, 272, WebCT 12, 65, 67 278 Weinberger, D. 109, 114 viral 58 Wells, I.B. 115 Virilio, P. 22 wetware 9 virtual 14, 16, 274 Wikinomics 63, 147, 158 and physical 272 Wikipedia 49, 141, 150, 157 and real 272 wikis 100, 136-137, 144 virtual mobility 216 Wild West 108 virtual object 258, 261-262 Wilders, G. 103 virtual pet 23 Williams, A. 130 virtual reality 8, 105 WinAmp 152 virtual space 9, 52, 217, 219, window 213-214 239 Windows 177 virtual, the 9, 21, 130, 200 Winograd, T. 259 virtual travel 213, 216 Winston, B. 187-190, 195 virtual worlds 30, 141 Wired 56 virtuality 9, 103 wireless 124, 212 vision 189, 275 wisdom of the crowds 109, 148 camera vision 189 wizard 177 visual culture 11, 15 Wolfrey, J. 124 visual illusion 278 Wollen, P. 188 visualisation 272 Wolting, F. 59

302 digital material Wooden Mirror 267 Y Woolf, V. 112 Yahoo 155 work of art 95-96, 98, 101, 103, Yee, N. 163 105 YouTube 10, 50-51, 56-60, 109, world exhibition 12, 107 118, 154-155, 193 world exhibitions 109-118 Yttri, B. 85-86 World of Warcraft 13, 159-164, 168- 169 Z World Wide Web 143, 177 Zapatista 161 Worth, S. 191 Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung 95 Zimmerman, E. 164-167 X Žižek, S. 11, 21-24, 27, 29, 32 Xbox 35, 151, 153, 156 Zoonen, L. van 108

index 303 media matters

edited by boomen, den van marianne sybille lammes, ann-sophie lehmann, joost raessens, schäfer tobias mirko and

Tracing New Media Tracing in Everyday Life and Technology amsterdam university press university amsterdam Digital Material

edited by marianne van den boomen sybille lammes Digital Material ann-sophie lehmann joost raessens mirko tobias schäfer ­ ­

­

-

playing games and playing - learning,fromrole - from touch screens to blogging and assembled their material’ ‘digital into an an accompanied by versatile popular and academic discourse. New Media Studies alignment of new media yielded to a lished academic discipline, and this begs ­showcase of current research in the digital culture indeed all about ‘you’, the understanddigitalmachinerythe how and Netherlands.the e crystallized internationally into an estab­ an into internationally crystallized the question: where do we stand now? this constitutes us as ‘you’? The contribu tors of the present book, all teaching and thology, covering issues ranging from desk 2.0 metaphorstopWeb to ecosystems, in the programDigital the and Media New in materialist’perspective. media are taken for granted, and which riddles are still unsolved? Is contemporary participating user, or do we still not really researching new media and digital culture, host of innovations, trials, and problems, field, from what may ‘digitalbe called a Culture at the Department of Media and Culture Studies, Utrecht University, Cybergoth music to wireless dreams. Which new questions emerge new questions now new Which www.aup.nl press university amsterdam Together the contributions provide a provide contributions the Together The editors are all teaching and researching Three decadessocietalof cultural and

media matters 0 068 4 96 978-90-896-4068-0 908 8 ISBN 97