Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction Notes Introduction 1 . See, for example, Sahlin (1990), Marion (1998), Holton and Price (2003). 2 . See McGuinness (1985) for discussion. 3 . But see Sahlin (1997) for an excellent elaboration of the kinds of influence that Ramsey’s thought may have had on the later work of Wittgenstein. 4 . Interpretive questions regarding the way in which TLP ought to be read have dominated the literature on the matter for decades now. For guides from all sides regarding the nature of the distinction, see Goldfarb (1997), Williams (2004), Sullivan (2004), Conant and Diamond (2004) amongst many others. It should be noted that the distinction between resolute and traditional (or irresolute) readings of the Tractatus should be held apart from the distinc- tion between realist and non-realist interpretations of the work. A resolute reading certainly implies an abandonment of a realist interpretation of the work (indeed, of any interpretation of the work), but that same abandonment certainly need not imply resolution. These are orthogonal issues: as long as non-realist interpreters consider the seemingly metaphysical propositions of the Tractatus to have a content at all, they cannot be subsumed to the resolute programme. 5. See Diamond (1986) for one characterization of the realistic. 6. For persuasive arguments in favour of the positive answer, see Misak (forthcoming). 7. I mean by ‘linguistic representation’ not only utterances but thought as well, which Wittgenstein took also to occur in a language: ‘I don’t know whatt the constituents of a thought are but I know thatt it must have such constituents which correspond to the words of Language. Again, the kind of relation of the constituents of the thought and the pictured fact is irrelevant. It would be a matter of psychology to find out’ (McGuinness 2012, p. 98). 8. Peter Sullivan (2005) attributes the former view to Kenny and the latter view to Anscombe. I have been careful to remark that the objection to the latter view holds only on one conception of what a sign is. Sullivan’s view, which draws on TLPP 3.32 and diffuses the objection that I (and Kenny) make, is that a sign is the visible part of a symbol. If that is right, then there may be ‘a secondary notion’ of meaning that attaches to signs since a sign can no longer be conceived of as a mere e string but rather as something distinguishable only as a part of a meaning-bearing entity. I confess that I am suspicious of this idea: if one regards the relation of signs to symbols as something established by convention, then it seems that there must be a sense in which a sign has an existence which is independent of the symbol with which it is ultimately associated. That is, in establishing some conventional relationship between this sign and this symbol, the sign must be already distinguishable prior to its conventional correlation with the symbol. Sullivan’s article takes on renewed importance in Chapter 6; see also Kenny (1973) and Anscombe (1959). 238 Notes 239 9. Readers who are interested in more biographical detail regarding Ramsey than I have been able to incorporate into this book should see Mellor (1995), Taylor (2006), Paul (2012). I also very much recommend Mellor’s wonderful ‘Better than the Stars: a radio portrait of F.P. Ramsey’, located at http://sms.csx.cam. ac.uk/media/20145. 1 The Realistic Spirit 1 . There is a large literature on the nature, extent and commitments of realism. See Brock and Mares 2006, for an overview. Fine 2001 offers an alternative characterisation. Dummett proposed a controversial account of realism, according to which the defining mark of realism is a commitment to biva- lence for the sentences of X, anti-realism about X thus entailing the rejection of that semantic claim. See Dummett 1978 Ch. 10, 1993. See also Devitt 1983 and 1991, and Wright 1993. This meaning theoretic view of the distinction between realism and anti-realism defers questions of metaphysics, preferring an initial determination of whether or not a realist construal of the sentences in question, upon which grasp of their meaning is to be characterised by grasp of their truth conditions, makes unreasonable demands on speakers. 2 . Ramsey raises the issue of non-synonymy in F&P, p. 154. Clearly, someone might believe that ‘Lorna voted and Rob voted ... ’ was true without assenting to ‘Everyone in Cambridge voted’, simply because they do not know that the names in the conjunction exhaust the domain. That is, only if they assented to ‘Lorna voted and Rob voted and ... and Lorna, Rob, ... , are everyone in Cambridge’ would they assent also to the generalization. But all that Ramsey needs in order to support his claim is that, for any such generalization over a finite domain, there is a materially (though not logically) equivalent conjunc- tion available. It is, in general, extremely important to remember that nobody would suggest that a sentence S that expresses the truth-conditions of some sentence T is synonymous with T. 3 . TLPP 4.4221, 5.535. 4 . Note that Ramsey does not construe this as merely a subjective matter, for rules can be better or worse as they conform to ‘known psychological laws’, that is, the psychological laws governing our expectations about how people will infer on the basis of their singular experience. Further, particular matters of fact might be brought into such a disagreement, insofar as they may be used to explain why one rule for judging is better supported than another. 5 . I am aware that this is not the best way in which to express the Tractarian view of universal generalisations, and I give that view more careful exposition in Chapter 9. Nonetheless, it is how Ramsey expresses the view, and as it makes no material difference to the elucidation of Ramsey’s view at this early stage, I shall continue to express thus also. 6 . In the passage, Ramsey does use the term ‘realistic’, but it is obvious from the context that he intends one of a range of views for which I am using the label ‘realist’, that is, a view which may be described as a form of realism. 7 . To be more precise, it would be a conjunction of conjunctions, each of the latter consisting of a conjunction of propositions asserting the non-toxicity of each strawberry for some particular human. The main conjunction would 240 Notes then have as its conjuncts infinitely many conjunctions, each of which concerned an object in the infinite domain of humans. These domains are infinite because the content of a statement of law is not exhausted by the actual instances of the objects in question. ‘Arsenic is poisonous’ is not taken to mean only that the sum total of arsenic in the actual world is poisonous; we would assert it even if, for instance, there were no arsenic in nature, but the properties given by its position in the periodic table assured us that, were it to exist, it would be poisonous to us. 8 . Leaving aside, that is, cases of deception, confusion, misunderstanding and such. 9 . ‘What causes hesitation is the fact that, after all, Mr. Wittgenstein manages to say a good deal about what cannot be said’. TLPP p. xxiii. 10 . TLPP 5.4731, 5.5563. In a 1929 note, Ramsey wrote ‘“All our everyday prop[osition]s are in order” is absolutely false, and shows the absurdity of interpreting logic as a part of natural science’. Ramsey 1991a, p. 277; HL 002–30–01. 11 . It is not known who Mr C is – the name is illegible in the original document. 12 . This claim is hard to generalise; obviously, one is, at some point, playing bridge, even if muddling along and making some mistakes. Where one goes from learning to really playing may be, on such a view, a matter of one’s own expectations and those of the other players, as well as what oneself and others take one to be committed to in undertaking the activity. 13 . Robert Trueman has pointed out the limits of the analogy in respect of certain games, such as video games played on a console. In order to play such games, one inputs instructions via a controller, and no combination of inputs is illegitimate in any way that might be considered a contravention (though they may be stupid, counterproductive, etc.). Rather, an illegitimate input would simply be one on which nothing happened. Of course, there are ways of cheating in such games – hacking the code, for instance – and it seems at least plausible that such cheats would count as a contraven- tion in my sense, as opposed to an illegitimate activity which was not a contravention. For imagine that the aim of the game is to complete a course in a certain amount of time. Then, whether the hack that slows the clock counts as a contravention or not will depend on whether one credits oneself (or whether one would allow someone else to credit one) with having won thatt game (as opposed to a new game in with a slower clock) in completing the course against the hacked clock. If the goal is to complete the course in 30 seconds, but one has deceived an observer, actual or potential, into thinking that 45 seconds is 30 seconds, and makes no effort to relieve him of that misapprehension, then I should say that that would be to commit a contravention in the relevant sense. For what remains are the commit- ments that one has undertaken and the expectations of the other players (or observers).
Recommended publications
  • Truth and Simplicity F
    Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 58 (2007), 379–386 Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey 1 Preamble ‘Truth and Simplicity’ is the title we have supplied for a very remarkable nine page typescript of a talk that Ramsey gave to the Cambridge Apostles on April 29, 1922.1 It is a relatively early work but it already touches even in such brief compass on several topics of fundamental philosophical interest: truth, ontological simplicity, the theory of types, facts, universals, and probability, that are recurrent themes found in most of Ramsey’s papers, published and posthumous. The present paper has not appeared in any of the classic collections, and it comes as a pleasant surprise—just when we thought we had seen it all.2 In the paper, Ramsey develops two ideas he thinks are related: that ‘true’ is an incomplete symbol, and ‘the only things in whose existence we have reason to believe are simple, not complex’. The first relies on Russell’s notion of an incomplete symbol and the second he says is a view now (1922) held by Russell, and, as he generously says, he got it from Russell in conversation and doubts whether he would ever have thought of it by himself. Ramsey is very clear as to what simplicity requires: I mean that there are no classes, no complex properties or relations, or facts; and that the phrases which appear to stand for these things are incomplete symbols. Ramsey says later in this paper, that the statements that ‘true’ is an incomplete symbol and that everything in the world is simple are part of the same view.
    [Show full text]
  • The Subterranean Influence of Pragmatism on the Vienna Circle: Peirce, Ramsey, Wittgenstein
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF PRAGMATISM ON THE VOLUME 4, NUMBER 5 VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN CHERYL MISAK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS An underappreciated fact in the history of analytic philoso- EDITORIAL BOARD phy is that American pragmatism had an early and strong in- GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON fluence on the Vienna Circle. The path of that influence goes GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES from Charles Peirce to Frank Ramsey to Ludwig Wittgenstein to HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY Moritz Schlick. That path is traced in this paper, and along the SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY way some standard understandings of Ramsey and Wittgen- LyDIA PATTON, VIRGINIA TECH stein, especially, are radically altered. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY REVIEW EDITORS JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER DESIGN DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE JHAPONLINE.ORG C 2016 CHERYL MISAK THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF saving labor, is . true instrumentally. Satisfactorily . means PRAGMATISM ON THE VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, more satisfactorily to ourselves, and individuals will emphasize their points of satisfaction differently. To a certain degree, there- RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN fore, everything here is plastic. (James 1975, 34–35)2 CHERYL MISAK It was Peirce’s more sophisticated pragmatism that influenced Ramsey. C. K. Ogden, inventor of Basic English, publisher of the Tractaus, and co-author of The Meaning of Meaning, was Ram- sey’s mentor from the time he was a schoolboy.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap's Logic of Science and Reference to the Present Moment
    Carnap's Logic of Science and Reference to the Present Moment Florian Fischer Abstract The important switch from the so-called old B-theory to the new tenseless theory of time (NTT), which had significant implications for the field of tense and indexicals, occurred after Carnap's era. Against this new background, Carnap's original inter-translatability thesis can no longer be upheld. The most natural way out would be to modify Carnap's position according to the NTT; but this is not compatible with Carnap's metaphysi- cal neutrality thesis. Even worse, Carnap's work on measurement theory can be used to develop an argument in favour of the A-theory. I argue that there are tensed basic sentences which are needed in order to construct a tenseless system and thus cannot be translated without loss of meaning into tenseless ones (old B-theory) or made true by tenseless facts (NTT). Keywords: Rudolf Carnap, Philosophy of Time, Tense vs. Tenseless Theory, A-Theory, B-Theory, New Tenseless Theory of Time 1 Carnap and Tense This paper brings the work of Rudolf Carnap together with the modern debate about tense in the philosophy of time. It is an interesting fact that these fields have never been put together,1 despite the fact, or so I believe, that their content is deeply connected. The debate between so-called tensed and tenseless theories is a central issue in contemporary philosophy of time. `Tensers hold that grammatical tense is semantically irreducible, while detensers hold that tense is semantically reducible' [69, p. 2]. Under the buzz phrase `tensed versus tenseless theory', I subsume different philosophical positions about the reference to the present mo- ment.
    [Show full text]
  • FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi CHERYL MISAK FRANK RAMSEY a sheer excess of powers 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OXDP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Cheryl Misak The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in Impression: All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press Madison Avenue, New York, NY , United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: ISBN –––– Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A. Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in Time and Identity: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy
    Time and Identity: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy, Vol. 6, Michael O’Rourke, Joseph Campbell, and Harry Silverstein, eds. (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2009). Temporal Reality Lynne Rudder Baker University of Massachusetts Amherst Nonphilosophers, if they think of philosophy at all, wonder why people work in metaphysics. After all, metaphysics, as Auden once said of poetry, makes nothing happen.1 Yet some very intelligent people are driven to spend their lives exploring metaphysical theses. Part of what motivates metaphysicians is the appeal of grizzly puzzles (like the paradox of the heap or the puzzle of the ship of Theseus). But the main reason to work in metaphysics, for me at least, is to understand the shared world that we all encounter and interact with. And the shared world that we all encounter includes us self-conscious beings and our experience. The world that we inhabit is unavoidably a temporal world: the signing of the Declaration of Independence is later than the Lisbon earthquake; the Cold War is in the past; your death is in the future. There is no getting away from time. The ontology of time is currently dominated by two theories: Presentism, according to which “only currently existing objects are real,”2 and Eternalism, according to which “past and future objects and times are just as real as currently existing ones.”3 In my opinion, neither Presentism nor Eternalism yields a satisfactory ontology of time. Presentism seems both implausible on its face and in conflict with the Special Theory of Relativity, and Eternalism gives us no handle on time as universally experienced in terms of an ongoing now.
    [Show full text]
  • Poststructuralism, in a Companion to Philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., Pp.455‐459
    This is the published version: Reynolds, Jack 2010, Poststructuralism, in A companion to philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., pp.455‐459. Available from Deakin Research Online: http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30061160 Reproduced with the kind permission of the copyright owner. Copyright : 2010, Monash University Publishing A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY IN AUSTRALIA & NEW ZEALAND I 455 Poststructuralism Poststructuralism Jack Reynolds While it is difficult to precisely define poststructuralism, we can begin ostensively by noting some of the philosophers who are most consistently and famously associated with the term. This includes Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Jacques Derrida, and Jean-Franc,:ois Lyotard. As such, poststructuralism refers primarily to those philosophers working in France who contested and problematised the reigning orthodoxy in the humanities and social sciences in the early 1960s, which at that time was structuralism. Before positively considering their work and the way in which their overlapping but not univocal interests came to form what we today refer to as poststructuralism, it is important to consider their immediate predecessor on the French scene, structuralism. Structuralism was both a methodological mode of analysis as well as a more thoroughgoing metaphysical and ontological position, and it was widespread in the 1950s and '60s, whether it be Roland Barthes employing structuralist techniques in literary theory, Claude Levi-Strauss in anthropology, Jacques Lacan in psychoanalysis, or Louis Althusser in relation to Marxism and class analysis. The linguistics of Ferdinand de Saussure was also garnering renewed attention. Structuralism sought to arrive at a stable and secure knowledge of a system or a structure, by charting differences within that structure, and it sought to do so without any references to subjectivity and consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1406.4740V1 [Physics.Hist-Ph] 18 Jun 2014 H Nelt Fteps;Tedna Ftime
    On Time chez Dummett Jeremy Butterfield Trinity College, Cambridge CB2 1TQ: [email protected] Published in The European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 8 (2012), 77-102; (a special issue about philosophy of physics, in honour of Michael Dummett) Keywords: The common now; seeing the present; the Everett interpretation; branching; the unreality of the past; the denial of time. Sat 12 May 2012 Abstract I discuss three connections between Dummett’s writings about time and philo- sophical aspects of physics. The first connection (Section 2) arises from remarks of Dummett’s about the different relations of observation to time and to space. The main point is uncon- troversial and applies equally to classical and quantum physics. It concerns the fact that perceptual processing is so rapid, compared with the typical time-scale on which macroscopic objects change their observable properties, that it engenders the idea of a ‘common now’, spread across space. The other two connections are specific to quantum theory, as interpreted along the lines of Everett. So for these two connections, the physics side is controversial, just as the philosophical side is. In Section 3, I connect the subjective uncertainty before an Everettian ‘splitting’ of the multiverse to Dummett’s suggestion, inspired by McTaggart, that a complete, i.e. indexical-free description of a temporal reality is impossible. And in Section 4, I connect Barbour’s denial that time is real—a denial along the lines of Everett, rather than McTaggart—to Dummett’s suggestion that statements about the past arXiv:1406.4740v1 [physics.hist-ph] 18 Jun 2014 are not determinately true or false, because they are not effectively decidable.
    [Show full text]
  • The Representational Inadequacy of Ramsey Sentences
    The Representational Inadequacy of Ramsey Sentences by ARNOLD KOSLOW Department of Philosophy, CUNY Abstract: We canvas a number of past uses of Ramsey sentences which have yielded disappointing results, and then consider three very interesting recent attempts to deploy them for a Ramseyan Dialetheist theory of truth, a modal account of laws and theories, and a criterion for the existence of factual properties. We think that once attention is given to the specific kinds of theories that Ramsey had in mind, it becomes evident that their Ramsey sentences are not the best ways of presenting those theories. Keywords: Ramsey sentence, Ramseyan theoretical truth, Dialetheism, modal theories, factual properties. 1. Ramsey Sentences Old Replacement Problems. Ever since Frank P. Ramsey’s views on the- ories became known through Richard B. Braithwaite’s publication of a collection of his papers, the use of Ramsey sentences has been a simple yet powerful source of solutions to philosophically hard problems. In the first section we review several important early uses of Ramsey sentences and the loss of interest in those problems and the consequent loss of inter- est in the sentences themselves. In the second section we review a kind of revival: some recent uses of Ramsey sentences to settle problems about truth (Dialetheism), laws (their modal character), and to help determine what (factual) properties exist. Despite the real interest that these new uses of Ramsey sentences generates, we want to argue that that interest is seriously diminished once it is realized that there are reasons not to take the Ramsey sentence as a good representation of a theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Ramsey Theory
    Introduction to Ramsey Theory Lecture notes for undergraduate course Introduction to Ramsey Theory Lecture notes for undergraduate course Veselin Jungic Simon Fraser University Production Editor: Veselin Jungic Edition: Second Edition ©2014-–2021 Veselin Jungic This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercialShareAlike 4.0 International License. Youcan view a copy of the license at http://creativecommons.org/ licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/. To my sons, my best teachers. - Veselin Jungic Acknowledgements Drawings of Alfred Hale, Robert Jewett, Richard Rado, Frank Ramsey, Issai Schur, and Bartel van der Waerden were created by Ms. Kyra Pukanich under my directions. The drawing of Frank Ramsey displayed at the end of Section 1.3 was created by Mr. Simon Roy under my directions. I am grateful to Professor Tom Brown, Mr. Rashid Barket, Ms. Jana Caine, Mr. Kevin Halasz, Ms. Arpit Kaur, Ms. Ha Thu Nguyen, Mr. Andrew Poelstra, Mr. Michael Stephen Paulgaard, and Ms. Ompreet Kaur Sarang for their comments and suggestions which have been very helpful in improving the manuscript. I would like to acknowledge the following colleagues for their help in creating the PreTeXt version of the text. • Jana Caine, Simon Fraser University • David Farmer, American Institute of Mathematics • Sean Fitzpatrick , University of Lethbridge • Damir Jungic, Burnaby, BC I am particularly thankful to Dr. Sean Fitzpatrick for inspiring and encouraging me to use PreTeXt. Veselin Jungic vii Preface The purpose of these lecture notes is to serve as a gentle introduction to Ramsey theory for those undergraduate students interested in becoming familiar with this dynamic segment of contemporary mathematics that combines, among others, ideas from number theory and combinatorics.
    [Show full text]
  • Prospects for Justificationism
    University of Birmingham Truth and meaning Rumfitt, Ian DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x License: Other (please specify with Rights Statement) Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (Harvard): Rumfitt, I 2014, 'Truth and meaning', Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, vol. 88, no. 1, pp. 21-55. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal Publisher Rights Statement: Checked for eligibility: 27/07/2015. This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Rumfitt, I. (2014), I—Truth and Meaning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 88: 21–55, which has been published in final form at doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x . This article may be used for non- commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain.
    [Show full text]
  • Mellon Seminars on Ethics, Philosophy and Anthropology Hallvard Lillehammer
    Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 9 May 2012 ISSN 2046-9632 From the Chair Tim Crane I took over as Chair of the Faculty from Simon Blackburn on his retirement last year. We said goodbye formally to Simon – shown on the right appreciating one of his retirement gifts – at a lovely party at Trinity in the summer. Fortunately, Simon will still be living in Cambridge for most of the year, so we haven’t lost him altogether. Since then it’s been a busy year. Huw Price has stepped into Simon’s chair (if that is what one does with a chair) and is already making his mark on the Faculty with workshops, conferences and new initiatives, like the new cross-Cambridge Philosophy of Science group (which Huw has named with the catchy acronym ‘CAMPOS’: see our interview on p. 4). But all members of the Faculty have been busy too this year, with what seems to be a record number of conferences on ethics, logic and the philosophy of mind. Details of these events can be found on our website; and of course, Simon Blackburn at his retirement garden party, Trinity College Cambridge Philosophy alumni are always very welcome to attend these. three new lecturers in February. We were philosophy; she comes to Cambridge Richard Holton and Rae Langton from looking to appoint a lecturer in the history from a lectureship at the University of East MIT have been our Faculty Visitors this year, of philosophy (an area where we have not Anglia. Tim is currently a research fellow at and have made a tremendous contribution been strong for a while) and to strengthen St John’s, Cambridge, and did his PhD in in giving talks, attending seminars and just our profile in ethics, especially important the Faculty.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy
    Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 2 May 2005 From the Chairman “It’s the newspapers I can’t stand” Onora O’Neill The Newsletter again, and so soon. On behalf of all of us here thanks to those One of Tom Stoppard’s characters Appeals to rights to self-expression who sent us messages of encouragement explained to another: “I’m with you also won’t justify unconditional press after last year’s, and to those who have on the free press. It’s the newspapers I freedom. John Stuart Mill argued that contributed to the production of this one. can’t stand.” It is a thought many of individual freedom of expression We have for some years been aware us have had. Are grisly newspapers an should be limited only by requirements of gradually rising student numbers in inevitable cost of press freedom? If so, not to harm others, and then claimed the Cambridge Philosophy Tripos, why have British newspapers earned the same right for the press. The fuelled by a steady rise in the number of worse reputations than those in other analogy is unconvincing. Individuals applications. But recently the steady rise countries where the press is free? Are who are cavalier about accuracy may has become a flood, resulting in a arguments for press freedom beyond do little harm (even so, there are laws statistic that some will find startling: challenge? What exactly do the best against libel, slander and inciting there are more applications to of them show? Do any of them show hatred).
    [Show full text]