Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 2 May 2005 From the Chairman “It’s the newspapers I can’t stand” Onora O’Neill The Newsletter again, and so soon. On behalf of all of us here thanks to those One of Tom Stoppard’s characters Appeals to rights to self-expression who sent us messages of encouragement explained to another: “I’m with you also won’t justify unconditional press after last year’s, and to those who have on the free press. It’s the newspapers I freedom. John Stuart Mill argued that contributed to the production of this one. can’t stand.” It is a thought many of individual freedom of expression We have for some years been aware us have had. Are grisly newspapers an should be limited only by requirements of gradually rising student numbers in inevitable cost of press freedom? If so, not to harm others, and then claimed the Cambridge Philosophy Tripos, why have British newspapers earned the same right for the press. The fuelled by a steady rise in the number of worse reputations than those in other analogy is unconvincing. Individuals applications. But recently the steady rise countries where the press is free? Are who are cavalier about accuracy may has become a flood, resulting in a arguments for press freedom beyond do little harm (even so, there are laws statistic that some will find startling: challenge? What exactly do the best against libel, slander and inciting there are more applications to of them show? Do any of them show hatred). Powerful organisations – Cambridge for Philosophy than for that press freedom is unconditional? governments, businesses – that are Computer Science. And when it comes Four arguments for press freedom cavalier about accuracy can do great to ratios of applications to admissions are in common use. One is harm. We don’t permit companies to in the University Philosophy is very jurisprudential: it simply appeals to invent their balance sheets, or public close to the top – only Architecture is constitutional or other authorities authorities their accounts and reports. significantly higher, Economics, Law that proclaim rights to a free press, If powerful media conglomerates have and the Vet School, with their obvious such as the First Amendment to the unconditional freedom of expression vocational emphasis, are slightly higher, US Constitution (“Congress shall they will be free to be cavalier about and no other Arts subject is near. This make no law abridging the freedom accuracy, to harm others and to of course brings problems, and they of the press”) and Article 10 of the undermine democracy. remain problems even though we can European Convention on Human Appeals to democracy also won’t take satisfaction in their very existence. Rights (clause 1; but note clause 2!). justify unconditional press freedom, It becomes particularly important to Unfortunately, arguments from since democracy needs a press that maintain staffing numbers in spite of the authority don’t provide deep informs citizens accurately. However, current tightening of the University’s justifications. if requirements for accurate reporting belt – for which our fundraising project Other arguments go deeper. Press are too tightly drawn, the press will has obvious relevance. freedom has been variously defended be intimidated. Nobody can be sure That project is now gaining as necessary for discovering truth, as of getting everything right – even with momentum. And there is one clear piece analogous to individual rights of self- zealous ‘fact checking’. So a press that of good news in the establishment by expression, and as required for serves rather than damages Trinity and Churchill Colleges of a joint democracy. None of these lines of democracy needs to aim for accuracy: College teaching post. So despite present thought justifies unconditional press we can require truthfulness, but not financial restrictions we have every freedom. truth. This standard can be met by reason to be cheerful. Appeals to truth seeking won’t providing evidence, by including Well before the next Newsletter justify unconditional press freedom caveats and qualifications, by prompt appears the Faculty will have a new because, as Bernard Williams points correction of error, by distinguishing chairman, Professor Jane Heal. So, out in Truth and Truthfulness, “in reporting from commentary, rumour wishing everyone all the best and hoping institutions dedicated to finding out and gossip. These and other forms of to see many of you at the Alumni the truth, such as universities, epistemic responsibility allow readers Weekend in September, I sign off. research institutes, and courts of law, to judge for themselves. speech is not at all unregulated.” Any Ostensibly the British Press is Edward Craig FBA search for truth needs structures and committed to accuracy. It is the first Knightbridge Professor of Philosophy disciplines, and is undermined by demand in the Press Complaints Chairman of the Philosophy Faculty casual disregard of accuracy or Commission’s Code. But good Board evidence. Unconditional freedom is reporting is a public good, not a not optimal for truth-seeking. continued on page 8 Philosophy at Cambridge page 1 May 2005 Cambridge Conferences The 2004 Annual Royal Institute of Philosophy Conference In July 2004, the Royal Institute of support of the Faculty of Philosophy and University Press, under the auspices of Philosophy annual conference was held in the Analysis Trust. the Royal Institute of Philosophy. Cambridge for the first time. I organised A volume based on the conference, the conference, together with Ross which will also include further Harrison, and the theme was ‘Preference- contributions, will be published as a Serena Olsaretti, University Lecturer in Formation and Well-Being’. The idea was special issue of Philosophy and as a self- Philosophy to bring together moral philosophers, standing volume by Cambridge political philosophers and philosophers of economics to address a number of questions concerning the formation of Postgraduate Conference preferences and its relevance for theories of well-being. This was both a timely and The 8th Annual National Postgraduate graduate work in analytic philosophy under-explored topic. In various debates Analytic Philosophy Conference was held today. Professor Onora O’Neill FBA, in moral and political philosophy, at Magdalene College, Cambridge, in July provided a keynote address to preferences are thought to have 2004. The Conference consisted of complete the three-day event. A large normative significance. For example, thirteen papers presented by graduates number of philosophy graduate their satisfaction is said to contribute to from across Britain and the US. Over students from all over the world met on individuals’ well-being; and the choices eighty submissions were received and this occasion making the event a great that people make in line with their thirteen were selected as the very best in success. preferences – such as the choice to pursue a costly goal or ambition – are said to legitimately justify inequalities. Mathematical Knowledge Conference In all these debates, it is assumed that the preferences individuals aim to satisfy, Goldbach’s conjecture (every even in part as a result of the high level of and make choices on the basis of, are number greater than two is the sum of interest in the philosophy of mathematics ‘authentic’ preferences, formed under two primes) has been confirmed for all amongst Cambridge mathematicians. some but not other conditions (for numbers less than 1016. Should that Since 2002, the Cambridge University example, that they are not preferences count as evidence that it is likely to be Society for the Philosophy of formed under hypnosis); or that they are true? What can the behaviour of Mathematics and Mathematical Sciences not ‘adaptive’, in the sense that they adolescent monkeys tell us about the (CUSPOMMS) has been holding should not be preferences formed in nature of mathematics? These were fortnightly seminars on the philosophy of stifling circumstances under which people amongst many questions addressed at mathematics in the Centre for come to prefer what is readily available the conference on ‘Mathematical Mathematical Sciences, organized by over what is not. In other words, these Knowledge’, held at Fitzwilliam College undergraduate mathematicians and various debates assume some account of in the summer 2004. This philosophers. These seminars have preference-formation. Nonetheless, interdisciplinary conference, organized regularly attracted large audiences of despite the central importance of by Dominic Gregory, Mary Leng, mathematicians and philosophers, and accounts of preference-formation, there is Alexander Paseau and Michael Potter, showed the potential for fruitful relatively little sustained and explicit aimed at bringing together interactions between both groups, based discussion of them. The conference was mathematicians, philosophers, and on a shared fascination with the nature of intended to initiate such a discussion. psychologists to present their mathematics. We were delighted to have, as our perspectives on questions concerning The conference was well attended by speakers, Richard Arneson (University of mathematical knowledge. 98 delegates from 16 countries, California, San Diego), Johan Brännmark Our invited speakers thus included representing disciplines including (University of Lund, Sweden), Daniel two mathematicians (set theorist philosophy, mathematics, psychology, Hausman (University of Wisconsin), Akihiro
Recommended publications
  • Truth and Simplicity F
    Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 58 (2007), 379–386 Truth and Simplicity F. P. Ramsey 1 Preamble ‘Truth and Simplicity’ is the title we have supplied for a very remarkable nine page typescript of a talk that Ramsey gave to the Cambridge Apostles on April 29, 1922.1 It is a relatively early work but it already touches even in such brief compass on several topics of fundamental philosophical interest: truth, ontological simplicity, the theory of types, facts, universals, and probability, that are recurrent themes found in most of Ramsey’s papers, published and posthumous. The present paper has not appeared in any of the classic collections, and it comes as a pleasant surprise—just when we thought we had seen it all.2 In the paper, Ramsey develops two ideas he thinks are related: that ‘true’ is an incomplete symbol, and ‘the only things in whose existence we have reason to believe are simple, not complex’. The first relies on Russell’s notion of an incomplete symbol and the second he says is a view now (1922) held by Russell, and, as he generously says, he got it from Russell in conversation and doubts whether he would ever have thought of it by himself. Ramsey is very clear as to what simplicity requires: I mean that there are no classes, no complex properties or relations, or facts; and that the phrases which appear to stand for these things are incomplete symbols. Ramsey says later in this paper, that the statements that ‘true’ is an incomplete symbol and that everything in the world is simple are part of the same view.
    [Show full text]
  • The Subterranean Influence of Pragmatism on the Vienna Circle: Peirce, Ramsey, Wittgenstein
    JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF PRAGMATISM ON THE VOLUME 4, NUMBER 5 VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN CHERYL MISAK EDITOR IN CHIEF KEVIN C. KLEMENt, UnIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS An underappreciated fact in the history of analytic philoso- EDITORIAL BOARD phy is that American pragmatism had an early and strong in- GaRY EBBS, INDIANA UnIVERSITY BLOOMINGTON fluence on the Vienna Circle. The path of that influence goes GrEG FROSt-ARNOLD, HOBART AND WILLIAM SMITH COLLEGES from Charles Peirce to Frank Ramsey to Ludwig Wittgenstein to HENRY JACKMAN, YORK UnIVERSITY Moritz Schlick. That path is traced in this paper, and along the SANDRA LaPOINte, MCMASTER UnIVERSITY way some standard understandings of Ramsey and Wittgen- LyDIA PATTON, VIRGINIA TECH stein, especially, are radically altered. MARCUS ROSSBERG, UnIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT MARK TEXTOR, KING’S COLLEGE LonDON AUDREY YAP, UnIVERSITY OF VICTORIA RICHARD ZACH, UnIVERSITY OF CALGARY REVIEW EDITORS JULIET FLOYD, BOSTON UnIVERSITY CHRIS PINCOCK, OHIO STATE UnIVERSITY ASSISTANT REVIEW EDITOR SEAN MORRIS, METROPOLITAN STATE UnIVERSITY OF DenVER DESIGN DaNIEL HARRIS, HUNTER COLLEGE JHAPONLINE.ORG C 2016 CHERYL MISAK THE SUBTERRANEAN INflUENCE OF saving labor, is . true instrumentally. Satisfactorily . means PRAGMATISM ON THE VIENNA CIRCLE: PEIRCE, more satisfactorily to ourselves, and individuals will emphasize their points of satisfaction differently. To a certain degree, there- RAMSEY, WITTGENSTEIN fore, everything here is plastic. (James 1975, 34–35)2 CHERYL MISAK It was Peirce’s more sophisticated pragmatism that influenced Ramsey. C. K. Ogden, inventor of Basic English, publisher of the Tractaus, and co-author of The Meaning of Meaning, was Ram- sey’s mentor from the time he was a schoolboy.
    [Show full text]
  • Carnap's Logic of Science and Reference to the Present Moment
    Carnap's Logic of Science and Reference to the Present Moment Florian Fischer Abstract The important switch from the so-called old B-theory to the new tenseless theory of time (NTT), which had significant implications for the field of tense and indexicals, occurred after Carnap's era. Against this new background, Carnap's original inter-translatability thesis can no longer be upheld. The most natural way out would be to modify Carnap's position according to the NTT; but this is not compatible with Carnap's metaphysi- cal neutrality thesis. Even worse, Carnap's work on measurement theory can be used to develop an argument in favour of the A-theory. I argue that there are tensed basic sentences which are needed in order to construct a tenseless system and thus cannot be translated without loss of meaning into tenseless ones (old B-theory) or made true by tenseless facts (NTT). Keywords: Rudolf Carnap, Philosophy of Time, Tense vs. Tenseless Theory, A-Theory, B-Theory, New Tenseless Theory of Time 1 Carnap and Tense This paper brings the work of Rudolf Carnap together with the modern debate about tense in the philosophy of time. It is an interesting fact that these fields have never been put together,1 despite the fact, or so I believe, that their content is deeply connected. The debate between so-called tensed and tenseless theories is a central issue in contemporary philosophy of time. `Tensers hold that grammatical tense is semantically irreducible, while detensers hold that tense is semantically reducible' [69, p. 2]. Under the buzz phrase `tensed versus tenseless theory', I subsume different philosophical positions about the reference to the present mo- ment.
    [Show full text]
  • FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, Spi
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi FRANK RAMSEY OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi CHERYL MISAK FRANK RAMSEY a sheer excess of powers 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 7/1/2020, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OXDP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Cheryl Misak The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in Impression: All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press Madison Avenue, New York, NY , United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: ISBN –––– Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A. Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in Time and Identity: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy
    Time and Identity: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy, Vol. 6, Michael O’Rourke, Joseph Campbell, and Harry Silverstein, eds. (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 2009). Temporal Reality Lynne Rudder Baker University of Massachusetts Amherst Nonphilosophers, if they think of philosophy at all, wonder why people work in metaphysics. After all, metaphysics, as Auden once said of poetry, makes nothing happen.1 Yet some very intelligent people are driven to spend their lives exploring metaphysical theses. Part of what motivates metaphysicians is the appeal of grizzly puzzles (like the paradox of the heap or the puzzle of the ship of Theseus). But the main reason to work in metaphysics, for me at least, is to understand the shared world that we all encounter and interact with. And the shared world that we all encounter includes us self-conscious beings and our experience. The world that we inhabit is unavoidably a temporal world: the signing of the Declaration of Independence is later than the Lisbon earthquake; the Cold War is in the past; your death is in the future. There is no getting away from time. The ontology of time is currently dominated by two theories: Presentism, according to which “only currently existing objects are real,”2 and Eternalism, according to which “past and future objects and times are just as real as currently existing ones.”3 In my opinion, neither Presentism nor Eternalism yields a satisfactory ontology of time. Presentism seems both implausible on its face and in conflict with the Special Theory of Relativity, and Eternalism gives us no handle on time as universally experienced in terms of an ongoing now.
    [Show full text]
  • Poststructuralism, in a Companion to Philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., Pp.455‐459
    This is the published version: Reynolds, Jack 2010, Poststructuralism, in A companion to philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., pp.455‐459. Available from Deakin Research Online: http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30061160 Reproduced with the kind permission of the copyright owner. Copyright : 2010, Monash University Publishing A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY IN AUSTRALIA & NEW ZEALAND I 455 Poststructuralism Poststructuralism Jack Reynolds While it is difficult to precisely define poststructuralism, we can begin ostensively by noting some of the philosophers who are most consistently and famously associated with the term. This includes Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Jacques Derrida, and Jean-Franc,:ois Lyotard. As such, poststructuralism refers primarily to those philosophers working in France who contested and problematised the reigning orthodoxy in the humanities and social sciences in the early 1960s, which at that time was structuralism. Before positively considering their work and the way in which their overlapping but not univocal interests came to form what we today refer to as poststructuralism, it is important to consider their immediate predecessor on the French scene, structuralism. Structuralism was both a methodological mode of analysis as well as a more thoroughgoing metaphysical and ontological position, and it was widespread in the 1950s and '60s, whether it be Roland Barthes employing structuralist techniques in literary theory, Claude Levi-Strauss in anthropology, Jacques Lacan in psychoanalysis, or Louis Althusser in relation to Marxism and class analysis. The linguistics of Ferdinand de Saussure was also garnering renewed attention. Structuralism sought to arrive at a stable and secure knowledge of a system or a structure, by charting differences within that structure, and it sought to do so without any references to subjectivity and consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1406.4740V1 [Physics.Hist-Ph] 18 Jun 2014 H Nelt Fteps;Tedna Ftime
    On Time chez Dummett Jeremy Butterfield Trinity College, Cambridge CB2 1TQ: [email protected] Published in The European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 8 (2012), 77-102; (a special issue about philosophy of physics, in honour of Michael Dummett) Keywords: The common now; seeing the present; the Everett interpretation; branching; the unreality of the past; the denial of time. Sat 12 May 2012 Abstract I discuss three connections between Dummett’s writings about time and philo- sophical aspects of physics. The first connection (Section 2) arises from remarks of Dummett’s about the different relations of observation to time and to space. The main point is uncon- troversial and applies equally to classical and quantum physics. It concerns the fact that perceptual processing is so rapid, compared with the typical time-scale on which macroscopic objects change their observable properties, that it engenders the idea of a ‘common now’, spread across space. The other two connections are specific to quantum theory, as interpreted along the lines of Everett. So for these two connections, the physics side is controversial, just as the philosophical side is. In Section 3, I connect the subjective uncertainty before an Everettian ‘splitting’ of the multiverse to Dummett’s suggestion, inspired by McTaggart, that a complete, i.e. indexical-free description of a temporal reality is impossible. And in Section 4, I connect Barbour’s denial that time is real—a denial along the lines of Everett, rather than McTaggart—to Dummett’s suggestion that statements about the past arXiv:1406.4740v1 [physics.hist-ph] 18 Jun 2014 are not determinately true or false, because they are not effectively decidable.
    [Show full text]
  • The Representational Inadequacy of Ramsey Sentences
    The Representational Inadequacy of Ramsey Sentences by ARNOLD KOSLOW Department of Philosophy, CUNY Abstract: We canvas a number of past uses of Ramsey sentences which have yielded disappointing results, and then consider three very interesting recent attempts to deploy them for a Ramseyan Dialetheist theory of truth, a modal account of laws and theories, and a criterion for the existence of factual properties. We think that once attention is given to the specific kinds of theories that Ramsey had in mind, it becomes evident that their Ramsey sentences are not the best ways of presenting those theories. Keywords: Ramsey sentence, Ramseyan theoretical truth, Dialetheism, modal theories, factual properties. 1. Ramsey Sentences Old Replacement Problems. Ever since Frank P. Ramsey’s views on the- ories became known through Richard B. Braithwaite’s publication of a collection of his papers, the use of Ramsey sentences has been a simple yet powerful source of solutions to philosophically hard problems. In the first section we review several important early uses of Ramsey sentences and the loss of interest in those problems and the consequent loss of inter- est in the sentences themselves. In the second section we review a kind of revival: some recent uses of Ramsey sentences to settle problems about truth (Dialetheism), laws (their modal character), and to help determine what (factual) properties exist. Despite the real interest that these new uses of Ramsey sentences generates, we want to argue that that interest is seriously diminished once it is realized that there are reasons not to take the Ramsey sentence as a good representation of a theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Ramsey Theory
    Introduction to Ramsey Theory Lecture notes for undergraduate course Introduction to Ramsey Theory Lecture notes for undergraduate course Veselin Jungic Simon Fraser University Production Editor: Veselin Jungic Edition: Second Edition ©2014-–2021 Veselin Jungic This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercialShareAlike 4.0 International License. Youcan view a copy of the license at http://creativecommons.org/ licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/. To my sons, my best teachers. - Veselin Jungic Acknowledgements Drawings of Alfred Hale, Robert Jewett, Richard Rado, Frank Ramsey, Issai Schur, and Bartel van der Waerden were created by Ms. Kyra Pukanich under my directions. The drawing of Frank Ramsey displayed at the end of Section 1.3 was created by Mr. Simon Roy under my directions. I am grateful to Professor Tom Brown, Mr. Rashid Barket, Ms. Jana Caine, Mr. Kevin Halasz, Ms. Arpit Kaur, Ms. Ha Thu Nguyen, Mr. Andrew Poelstra, Mr. Michael Stephen Paulgaard, and Ms. Ompreet Kaur Sarang for their comments and suggestions which have been very helpful in improving the manuscript. I would like to acknowledge the following colleagues for their help in creating the PreTeXt version of the text. • Jana Caine, Simon Fraser University • David Farmer, American Institute of Mathematics • Sean Fitzpatrick , University of Lethbridge • Damir Jungic, Burnaby, BC I am particularly thankful to Dr. Sean Fitzpatrick for inspiring and encouraging me to use PreTeXt. Veselin Jungic vii Preface The purpose of these lecture notes is to serve as a gentle introduction to Ramsey theory for those undergraduate students interested in becoming familiar with this dynamic segment of contemporary mathematics that combines, among others, ideas from number theory and combinatorics.
    [Show full text]
  • Prospects for Justificationism
    University of Birmingham Truth and meaning Rumfitt, Ian DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x License: Other (please specify with Rights Statement) Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (Harvard): Rumfitt, I 2014, 'Truth and meaning', Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, vol. 88, no. 1, pp. 21-55. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal Publisher Rights Statement: Checked for eligibility: 27/07/2015. This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Rumfitt, I. (2014), I—Truth and Meaning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 88: 21–55, which has been published in final form at doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8349.2014.00231.x . This article may be used for non- commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain.
    [Show full text]
  • Mellon Seminars on Ethics, Philosophy and Anthropology Hallvard Lillehammer
    Philosophy at Cambridge Newsletter of the Faculty of Philosophy Issue 9 May 2012 ISSN 2046-9632 From the Chair Tim Crane I took over as Chair of the Faculty from Simon Blackburn on his retirement last year. We said goodbye formally to Simon – shown on the right appreciating one of his retirement gifts – at a lovely party at Trinity in the summer. Fortunately, Simon will still be living in Cambridge for most of the year, so we haven’t lost him altogether. Since then it’s been a busy year. Huw Price has stepped into Simon’s chair (if that is what one does with a chair) and is already making his mark on the Faculty with workshops, conferences and new initiatives, like the new cross-Cambridge Philosophy of Science group (which Huw has named with the catchy acronym ‘CAMPOS’: see our interview on p. 4). But all members of the Faculty have been busy too this year, with what seems to be a record number of conferences on ethics, logic and the philosophy of mind. Details of these events can be found on our website; and of course, Simon Blackburn at his retirement garden party, Trinity College Cambridge Philosophy alumni are always very welcome to attend these. three new lecturers in February. We were philosophy; she comes to Cambridge Richard Holton and Rae Langton from looking to appoint a lecturer in the history from a lectureship at the University of East MIT have been our Faculty Visitors this year, of philosophy (an area where we have not Anglia. Tim is currently a research fellow at and have made a tremendous contribution been strong for a while) and to strengthen St John’s, Cambridge, and did his PhD in in giving talks, attending seminars and just our profile in ethics, especially important the Faculty.
    [Show full text]
  • Can Things Endure in Tenseless Time?1
    From Sats–Nordic Journal of Philosophy 10(1): 79-99 (Author’s Copy). CAN THINGS ENDURE IN TENSELESS TIME?1 Rögnvaldur Ingthorsson It has been argued that the tenseless view of time is incompatible with endurantism. This has been disputed, perhaps most famously by Hugh Mellor and Peter Simons. They argue that things can endure in tenseless time, and indeed must endure if tenseless time is to contain change. In this paper I will point out some difficulties with Mellor’s and Simons’ claims that in tenseless time a particular can be ‘wholly present’ at various times, and therefore endure, as well as have incompatible properties at those different times, and thereby change. In effect I argue that they do not resolve the charge that the tenseless view of time is incomatible with endurantism because the tenseless view does not allow anything to change temporal location and thereby come to be ‘wholly present’ at various times. 1. Introduction An important question in the philosophy of time is whether the tenseless view of time is compatible with an endurantist view of persistence, or if it is committed to the view that things perdure. The question is particularly important to those who believe that unless the tenseless view can accommodate for enduring particulars, it cannot give a convincing account of change in the standard sense; i.e. as a variation in the properties of one and the very same particular existing at different times. There are those who accept as coherent an account of change in terms of variation between temporal parts of a perduring entity.
    [Show full text]