Moral Obligations to Non-Humans

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Load more

Moral Obligations to Non-Humans Alasdair David Charles Cochrane PhD Government London School of Economics and Political Science UMI Number: U615648 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U615648 Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 I confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own: Alasdair Cochrane n Jbrary imtisfr Library o* Potttrcdf :nd. Fconomic Sciftncft. Abstract: Moral Obligations to Non-Humans My PhD thesis provides an account of the moral obligations we have to non-humans. The project is divided into two sections: the theoretical and the applied. In the first section I examine the foundations of our moral obligations, answering two key questions: what types of thing have moral status, and how can we delineate our obligations to them? I maintain that those entities with the capacity for ‘well-being’ have moral status. I refute the claim made by some that all living organisms have well-being, and argue that only beings with ‘phenomenal consciousness’ (sentience) have lives that can go well or badly for themselves. At this point then, the thesis turns its focus towards sentient animals. Next I consider just how we should structure our moral obligations. I argue that a utilitarian or aggregative framework fails to individuate entities with moral status, treating them as mere ‘receptacles’ of value. I thus propose that an interest-based rights theory provides the appropriate means for delineating our obligations to non-human animals. The second part of the thesis involves teasing out the implications of this interest-based rights theory for the ways in which we treat animals. To this end, I evaluate four different contexts in which we use non-human animals: in experiments, in agriculture, in entertainment, and by cultural groups. During these considerations, I argue that animals’ interests in avoiding pain and continued life ground prima facie animal rights not to be made to suffer and not to be killed. This renders many of the ways we currently use animals impermissible, particularly with regards to factory farming and experimentation. However, unlike other proponents of animal rights, I do not see the use of animals as impermissible in itself. This is because I claim that animals have no intrinsic interest in liberty, whether liberty is construed as the absence of interference or as the ability to govern one’s own life. Since animals h a ^ n o interest in liberty for its own sake, this means that they ordinarily have no right not\> be used or interfered with by humans. Thus, the ultimate conclusion of my thesis is that the moral obligations we have to animals do not involve liberating them from zoos, farms and our homes. Rather, they necessitate putting an end to the suffering and death that animals endure at our hands. 3 Acknowledgements I became fascinated by the question of what we owe to non-human entities when studying as an undergraduate in the Department of Politics at the University of Sheffield. Indeed, it was there that I decided I would like to write a thesis on the topic. For giving me the opportunity to go there, I would like to thank my Mum and Dad: it was undoubtedly the best present I have ever received. For sparking my interest in animal rights, environmental philosophy and political philosophy more generally, I would like to thank James Meadowcroft, whose courses at Sheffield were hugely enjoyable. If it were not for a scholarship from the AHRC, I would not have been able to afford to come to the LSE for my Masters, so I would like to thank them for that. Moreover, I am extremely grateful for the various research scholarships and teaching studentships that I have been awarded by the LSE throughout studying for my PhD. My greatest intellectual debt is owed to my PhD supervisor, Cecile Fabre. From when she first taught me in my Masters, to when she read the penultimate draft of this thesis, she has always made my attempts to do political philosophy richly rewarding. Furthermore, her professionalism, insightfulness and depth of feedback have simply been amazing. I would like to thank her for these efforts, and for helping to make the whole process of writing the thesis so enjoyable. While Cecile Fabre has read the whole thesis, others have read parts of it, and I would like to thank them for their feedback. In particular, my PhD advisor Paul Kelly read early parts of what are now Chapter 2, and an early draft of Chapter 5. Fintan McCullagh also read an early draft of Chapter 8. The Political Theory Workshop at the LSE has heard versions of Chapters 3 and 4 and I would like to thank all who attended for their comments. Of particular help were comments from: Garrett Brown, Katrin Flikschuh, Andrej Keba, Alex Leveringhaus, Christian List, Panos Papoulias, Kai Spiekermann, Laura Valentini and Jeremy Williams. A reworked version of Chapter 5 is to be published in Res Publica, and I would like to thank the editors and an anonymous referee for their helpful comments. No doubt part of the reason that I have enjoyed writing this thesis so much is down to the fact that I have left it alone at evenings and weekends. For not discussing animal rights with me at these times, I would like to thank my family, friends, and especially Susie. 4 Table of Contents Abstract 3 Acknowledgements 4 Table of Contents 5 1 Introduction 8 1.1 The Contribution of the Thesis 9 1.2 The Method and Assumptions of the Thesis 11 1.2.1 Analytical Philosophy 11 1.2.2 Reflective Equilibrium 12 1.2.3 Foundations, Rationalism, Impartiality and Universalism 13 1.3 The Outline of the Thesis 17 2 Well-Being and Moral Status 20 2.1 The Meaning of Well-Being 21 2.1.1 The Prudential Value of Well-Being 21 2.1.2 Interests 22 2.1.3 Harm 23 2.2 Well-Being and Our Moral Obligations 24 2.2.1 Is Well-Being Necessary to Have Moral Status? 24 2.2.2 Is Well-Being Sufficient to Have Moral Status? 27 2.3 Life, Consciousness and Well-Being 30 2.3.1 Is Life Necessary for Well-Being? 30 2.3.2 Is Life Sufficient for Well-Being? 32 2.3.3 Is Consciousness Necessary for Well-Being? 33 2.3.4 Is Consciousness Sufficient for Well-Being? 36 2.4 Locating Phenomenal Consciousness and Moral Status 40 2.4.1 Evidence in Favour of Animal Experience 41 2.4.2 Objectively Proving the Subjective 42 2.4.3 Drawing the Line 43 2.5 Conclusion 47 3 The Well-Being of Non-Human Animals 48 3.1 The Well-Being of Persons 50 3.1.1 Pleasure 50 3.1.2 Desires 52 3.1.3 Goals 53 3.1.4 Needs, Functionings and Capabilities 54 3.2 The Well-Being of Non-Persons 57 3.2.1 Capabilities and Non-Persons 58 3.2.2 Achieved Functionings, Needs and Non-Persons 59 3.2.3 Desires and Non-Persons 60 3.2.4 Pleasure and Non-Persons 61 3.2.5 Potentiality and Drawing the Line for Personhood 64 3.3 A Hierarchy of Moral Status? 65 3.4 Conclusion 66 5 4 Non-Human Animals and Moral Rights 68 4.1 What Kinds of Thing Are Rights? 69 4.1.1 Legal Rights, Moral Rights and Hohfeldian Incidents 69 4.1.2 The Will Theory of Rights 70 4.1.3 The Interest Theory of Rights 72 4.1.4 The Entitlement and Several Function Theories of Rights 73 4.2 Assigning Moral Rights 76 4.2.1 Joseph Raz’s Interest Theory 77 4.2.2 The Peremptory Force of Rights 78 4.3 Can Non-Human Animals Have Moral Rights? 80 4.3.1 Choice and Autonomy 80 4.3.2 Reciprocity and Moral Agency 83 4.3.3 Well-Being 87 4.4 Conclusion 88 5 Non-Human Animals and Experimentation 89 5.1 Establishing the Strength of an Interest 90 5.1.1 Value to the Individual and Psychological Continuity 90 5.2 A Right Not to Be Subject to Painful Experimentation? 92 5.2.1 The Benefits of Experimentation Justify its Continuation 94 5.2.2 Species Membership is Ethically Significant 95 5.2.3 Human Life is Worth More than Animal Life 99 5.3 A Right Not to Be Killed by Experimentation? 102 5.3.1 Do Animals Have an Interest in Continued Life? 103 5.3.2 The Strength of the Interest in Continued Life 105 5.3.3 A Moral Right Not to Be Killed by Experimentation? 106 5.4 A Right Not to Be Used in Experimentation? 109 5.4.1 Do Animals Have an Interest in Negative Freedom? 110 5.4.2 Do Animals Have an Interest in Positive Freedom? 112 5.4.3 Human Non-Persons, Freedom and Experimentation 114 5.5 Conclusion 116 6 Non-Human Animals and Agriculture 117 6.1 Applying the Rights Theory to Animals in Agriculture 118 6.1.1 Factory Farming 119 6.1.2 Killing Animals for their Flesh 120 6.1.3 Raising Animals for their Milk and Eggs 122 6.2 Animals Killed in the Field 124 6.2.1 Crop Cultivation and Numbers of Animals Killed 125 6.2.2 Crop Cultivation and Rights Violations 126 6.3 The Predation Argument 127 6.3.1 Animals Are Not Moral Agents 127 6.3.2 Killing for Survival and Overall Harm 128 6.4 The Non-Identity Problem and Farm Animals 130 6.4.1 The Non-Identity Problem 130 6.4.2 Is Modifying Animals Inherently Wrong? 135 6.4.3 Is Modifying Animals Ever Wrong? 137 6.5 Conclusion 142 7 Non-Human Animals and Entertainment 143 6 7.1 Implications of the Rights Theory for Animals in Entertainment 144 7.1.1 Pet-Keeping 144 7.1.2 Circuses
Recommended publications
  • Why Fish Do Not Feel Pain

    Why Fish Do Not Feel Pain

    Key, Brian (2016) Why fish do not eelf pain. Animal Sentience 3(1) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1011 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. Instructions: http://animalstudiesrepository.org/animsent/guidelines.html Why fish do not feel pain Brian Key Biomedical Sciences University of Queensland Australia Abstract: Only humans can report feeling pain. In contrast, pain in animals is typically inferred on the basis of nonverbal behaviour. Unfortunately, these behavioural data can be problematic when the reliability and validity of the behavioural tests are questionable. The thesis proposed here is based on the bioengineering principle that structure determines function. Basic functional homologies can be mapped to structural homologies across a broad spectrum of vertebrate species. For example, olfaction depends on olfactory glomeruli in the olfactory bulbs of the forebrain, visual orientation responses depend on the laminated optic tectum in the midbrain, and locomotion depends on pattern generators in the spinal cord throughout vertebrate phylogeny, from fish to humans. Here I delineate the region of the human brain that is directly responsible for feeling painful stimuli.
  • Comparative Evolutionary Approach to Pain Perception in Fishes

    Comparative Evolutionary Approach to Pain Perception in Fishes

    Brown, Culum (2016) Comparative evolutionary approach to pain perception in fishes. Animal Sentience 3(5) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1029 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Sentience 2016.011: Brown Commentary on Key on Fish Pain Comparative evolutionary approach to pain perception in fishes Commentary on Key on Fish Pain Culum Brown Biological Sciences Macquarie University Abstract: Arguments against the fact that fish feel pain repeatedly appear even in the face of growing evidence that they do. The standards used to judge pain perception keep moving as the hurdles are repeatedly cleared by novel research findings. There is undoubtedly a vested commercial interest in proving that fish do not feel pain, so the topic has a half-life well past its due date. Key (2016) reiterates previous perspectives on this topic characterised by a black-or-white view that is based on the proposed role of the human cortex in pain perception. I argue that this is incongruent with our understanding of evolutionary processes. Keywords: pain, fishes, behaviour, physiology, nociception Culum Brown [email protected] studies the behavioural ecology of fishes with a special interest in learning and memory. He is Associate Professor of vertebrate evolution at Macquarie University, Co-Editor of the volume Fish Cognition and Behavior, and Editor for Animal Behaviour of the Journal of Fish Biology.
  • Bioethical Questions of Animals in Sport1

    Bioethical Questions of Animals in Sport1

    Preliminary communication UDK: 17:798/799 636.046:17 Bruno Ćurko (Croatia) Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, University of Split [email protected] BIOETHICAL QUESTIONS OF ANIMALS IN SPORT1 Abstract Animals are a part of sport industries, from the so-called traditions such as fox hunting and bullfighting, horse and dog racing, to the cruel examples of hare coursing, rodeo, and orangutan boxing (Thailand), to cock and dog fights. These are prominent examples of animal exploitation serving our human entertainment. In my presentation, I will try to identify some of the essential questions considering animal use in sports. Some of these questions are: Can we justify animal exploitation in the name of tradition? Can we take into consideration the well-being of sport animals before, during, and after their competitive career? How much could and should the imminent risk of animal stress, injuries, and fatalities prevent us from their exploitation in sports? If animals are ready to obey demands we set upon them, should we abuse them for our entertainment and sport? Keywords: animals, sports industry, cultural tradition, bioethics, entertainment 1 This paper is an elaborated adaptation of a lecture titled “Bioethical Questions of Animals in Sport”, presented at the conference “3rd Osijek days of bioethics” - Faculty of Education, J. J. Strossmayer University of Osijek, 11–12 November 2019. Pannoniana, vol. IV, no. I (2020): 143-153 Introduction When we think about animals in sport, we usually think about activities where people use animals in some competitions such as horse races, dog races, and other similar ones. But first, we need to research the definition of sport as it is.
  • An Assessment of Recent Trade Law Developments from an Animal Law Perspective: Trade Law As the Sheep in Wolf's Clothing?

    An Assessment of Recent Trade Law Developments from an Animal Law Perspective: Trade Law As the Sheep in Wolf's Clothing?

    AN ASSESSMENT OF RECENT TRADE LAW DEVELOPMENTS FROM AN ANIMAL LAW PERSPECTIVE: TRADE LAW AS THE SHEEP IN WOLF’S CLOTHING? By Charlotte Blattner* Further development within the field of animal law seems to be at an impasse, lost among the potential paths presented by its traditional influ- ences: international treaty law, domestic animal welfare regulations, and trade law. First, classical elements of global animal treaty law are limited to preservationist aspirations, insusceptible to the questions of how animals are treated or how they cope with their environment. Second, animal welfare regulation is understood as a matter confined to national territories. In cross-border dialogue, animal matters have been reduced to allegations of imperialism, which is not conducive to furthering animal interests. Third, animals are regarded as commodities in international trade law, rendering their regulation an undesirable barrier to trade. These present deficiencies deprive global animal law of its significance as a dynamic instrument re- sponsive to global challenges, be they ethical, environmental, economic, technological, or social in nature. The objective of this paper is to demonstrate future ways out of this impasse. Recent developments in trade law, as demonstrated by four exam- ples found within the World Trade Organization’s (WTO) ‘case law,’ mark an important development for animal law. State objectives expressed through trade law are slowly moving away from anthropocentric considera- tions (i.e., geared to preserve a fraction of animals for human interests) to- wards sentiocentric animal welfare (i.e., aimed at minimizing animal suffering and focusing on animal interests). Thereby, the quality of animal law that developed on the international scene through trade law exceeded the status quo of global animal treaty law.
  • The Use of Animals in Sports

    The Use of Animals in Sports

    Existence, Breeding, a,nd Rights: The Use of Animals in Sports Donald Scherer Bowling Green State University Against these lines of argument one frequently encounters a certain objection. It is argued that since the animals for fighting, hunting and racing exist only because they have been bred for such human uses, human beings are justified in so treating them. The purpose of this paper is to evaluate this line ofobjection, or to speak more precisely, to evaluate the two distinct objections implicit in this line. For the objection may be either that (l) the present uses of the animals are justified because they are better for the animals than the Standardly, philosophical arguments about the alternative, namely non-existence, or that quality of treatment human beings owe nonhuman animals! rest on two bases. Peter Singer is famous (2) breeding an animal for a purpose gives the for arguing from the capacity of animals to feel pain breeders (transferable) rights over what they to the conclusion that since almost none of the pain have bred. human beings cause animals is necessary, almost none of it is morally justifiable (Singer, 1989, pp. 78-79). I shall pursue these alternatives sequentially. Singer rests his case on the premise that who suffers pain does not affect the badness of the suffering, so The Value of Existence that, without strong justification, the infliction of pain is universally wrong (Ibid., pp. 77-78). Tom Regan is The strength ofthe first form ofthe objection rests on equally famous for his argument that the beliefs and a common intuition comparing the values of existence desires which normal one year-old mammals clearly and non-existence.
  • Humane Intervention’: the International Protection of Animal Rights

    Humane Intervention’: the International Protection of Animal Rights

    This is a repository copy of ‘Humane intervention’: the international protection of animal rights. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/95205/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Cochrane, A. and Cooke, S. (2016) ‘Humane intervention’: the international protection of animal rights. Journal of Global Ethics, 12 (1). pp. 106-121. ISSN 1744-9626 https://doi.org/10.1080/17449626.2016.1149090 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Alasdair Cochrane & Steve Cooke ‘Humane Intervention’: The International Protection of Animal Rightsi Abstract: This paper explores the international implications of liberal theories which extend justice to sentient animals. In particular, it asks whether they imply that coercive military intervention in a state by external agents to prevent, halt or minimise violations of basic animal rights (‘humane intervention’) can be justified.
  • “But It's Just a Fish”: Understanding the Challenges of Applying the 3Rs

    “But It's Just a Fish”: Understanding the Challenges of Applying the 3Rs

    animals Article “But It’s Just a Fish”: Understanding the Challenges of Applying the 3Rs in Laboratory Aquariums in the UK Reuben Message * and Beth Greenhough School of Geography and the Environment, University of Oxford, Oxford OX1 2JD, UK; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 29 October 2019; Accepted: 28 November 2019; Published: 3 December 2019 Simple Summary: Fish are widely used in research and some species have become important model organisms in the biosciences. Despite their importance, their welfare has usually been less of a focus of public interest or regulatory attention than the welfare of more familiar terrestrial and mammalian laboratory animals; indeed, the use of fish in experiments has often been viewed as ethically preferable or even neutral. Adopting a social science perspective and qualitative methodology to address stakeholder understandings of the problem of laboratory fish welfare, this paper examines the underlying social factors and drivers that influence thinking, priorities and implementation of fish welfare initiatives and the 3Rs (Replacement, Reduction and Refinement) for fish. Illustrating the case with original stakeholder interviews and experience of participant observation in zebrafish facilities, this paper explores some key social factors influencing the take up of the 3Rs in this context. Our findings suggest the relevance of factors including ambient cultural perceptions of fish, disagreements about the evidence on fish pain and suffering, the language of regulators, and the experiences of scientists and technologists who develop and put the 3Rs into practice. The discussion is focused on the UK context, although the main themes will be pertinent around the world.
  • The Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Series

    The Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Series

    The Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Series Series editors: Andrew Linzey and Priscilla Cohn Associate editor: Clair Linzey In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the ethics of our treatment of animals. Philosophers have led the way, and now a range of other scholars have followed, from historians to social scientists. From being a marginal issue, animals have become an emerging issue in ethics and in multidisciplinary inquiry. This series explores the challenges that Animal Ethics poses, both conceptually and practically, to traditional understandings of human-animal relations. Specifically, the series will ● provide a range of key introductory and advanced texts that map out ethical positions on animals, ● publish pioneering work written by new, as well as accomplished, scholars, and ● produce texts from a variety of disciplines that are multidisciplinary in char- acter or have multidisciplinary relevance. Titles include Elisa Aaltola ANIMAL SUFFERING: PHILOSOPHY AND CULTURE Aysha Akhtar ANIMALS AND PUBLIC HEALTH Why Treating Animals Better Is Critical to Human Welfare Alasdair Cochrane AN INTRODUCTION TO ANIMALS AND POLITICAL THEORY Eleonora Gullone ANIMAL CRUELTY, ANTISOCIAL BEHAVIOUR, AND HUMAN AGGRESSION More than a Link Alastair Harden ANIMALS IN THE CLASSICAL WORLD Ethical Perspectives from Greek and Roman Texts Lisa Johnson POWER, KNOWLEDGE, ANIMALS Andrew Knight THE COSTS AND BENEFITS OF ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS Randy Malamud AN INTRODUCTION TO ANIMALS IN VISUAL CULTURE Ryan Patrick McLaughlin CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY AND
  • GOVERNMENT GAZETTE Focus on Hungary's Presidency

    GOVERNMENT GAZETTE Focus on Hungary's Presidency

    WHITEHALL • WESTMINSTER • BELFAST • EDINBURGH • CARDIFF • EUROPE • INTERNATIONAL EUROPEAN EDITIONGOVERNMENT GAZETTE Focus on Hungary's Presidency November 2010 £10.00, €11.00 ISSN 2042-4167 GOVERNMENT GAZETTE November 2010 GOVERNMENT The Hungarian Foreign Minister sets out the aims and objectives of Hungary's EU Presidency Democracy Foreign Policy Redevelopment Environment Jerzy Buzek on Knut Fleckenstein Danuta Huebner Gunther its promotion discusses Brussels' outlines plans to Oettinger around the world relationship with redevelop central lays out his Russia and eastern Europe priorities Gov Gazette Nov Europe cover proof.indd 1 29/10/2010 12:57:35 Shrinking budgets but increasing service demands? Do you face the difficult challenge of maintaining or improving services while reducing costs? Atos Origin can help you ease the pressure on your staff, enabling them to focus on delivery. We do this by optimizing your existing infrastructure and processes to deliver greater efficiency, superior service and lower costs. Atos Origin. Helping you achieve more. For more information: www.atosorigin.com/achievemore [email protected] www.atosorigin.com ATE_Public&Health_Advert_10-10703.indd 1 10/28/2010 4:18:11 PM WHITEHALL • WESTMINSTER • BELFAST • EDINBURGH • CARDIFF • EUROPE • INTERNATIONAL EUROPEAN EDITIONG G Focus on Hungary's Presidency OVERNMENT AZETTE November 2010 £10.00, €11.00 ISSN 2042-4167 GOVERNMENT GAZETTE Focus: Hungary's EU Presidency The Hungarian Foreign Minister sets out the aims and objectives of Hungary's EU Presidency
  • Animal Law & Policy Program

    Animal Law & Policy Program

    HARVARD ANIMAL LAW & POLICY PROGRAM HARVARD LAW SCHOOL Annual Report Fiscal Year 2017 July 1, 2016 – June 30, 2017 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Part One: Report of Activities 2 A. Summary of the Academic Year 2016–2017 2 1. Executive Summary 2 2. Research, Scholarship, and Activities 3 a. Program Mission and Areas of Inquiry 3 b. Research, Scholarship, and Project Activities 3 i. Professor Kristen Stilt 3 ii. Academic Fellow, Delcianna Winders 4 iii. Policy Fellow, Alice DiConcetto 5 iv. Farmed Animal Law & Policy Fellow, Peter Brandt 5 v. Graduate Scholar, Jessica Eisen 6 c. Conferences 7 i. The Animal Welfare Act at Fifty Conference 7 ii. The Ivy League Vegan Conference at Harvard University 8 d. Academic Workshops 9 i. The Animal Welfare Act at Fifty Workshop 9 ii. Animal Agriculture from the Middle East to Asia Workshop 9 e. Other Events 11 3. Contributions to HLS Teaching Program 12 4. Participation of HLS Students in Program Activities 14 a. ALPP Student Travel Grants 14 b. Mentoring and Guidance 14 c. ALPP Student Writing Prize 16 5. Faculty Participation 17 6. Other Contributions to the HLS Community 17 a. Faculty Director, Kristen Stilt 18 b. Executive Director, Chris Green 18 7. Law Reform and Advocacy 19 a. Faculty Director, Kristen Stilt 19 b. Executive Director, Chris Green 21 c. Academic Fellow, Delcianna Winders 23 8. Connections to the Profession & Public Outreach 25 a. Faculty Director, Kristen Stilt 26 b. Executive Director, Chris Green 27 9. Collaboration with Other Schools and Departments at HLS & Harvard University 30 a.
  • The Ad Bellum Challenge of Drones: Recalibrating Permissible Use of Force

    The Ad Bellum Challenge of Drones: Recalibrating Permissible Use of Force

    The European Journal of International Law Vol. 28 no. 1 © The Author, 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of EJIL Ltd. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] The ad bellum Challenge of Drones: Recalibrating Permissible Use of Force Alejandro Chehtman* Abstract Drones constitute an incremental advance in weapons systems. They are able to significantly reduce overall, as well as collateral, damage. These features seem to have important implications for the ad bellum permissibility of resorting to military force. In short, drones would seem to expand the right to resort to military force compared to alternative weapons systems by making resorting to force proportionate in a wider set of circumstances. This line of reasoning has signifi- cant relevance in many contemporary conflicts. This article challenges this conclusion. It argues that resorting to military force through drones in contemporary asymmetrical conflicts would usually be disproportionate. The reason for this is twofold. First, under conditions of radical asymmetry, drones may not be discriminatory enough, and, thereby, collateral damage would still be disproportionate. Second, their perceived advantages in terms of greater discrimination are counteracted by the lesser chance of success in achieving the just cause for war. As a result, resorting to military force through drones in contemporary asymmetrical conflicts would gener- ally be disproportionate not because of the harm they would expectedly cause but, rather, because of the limited harm they are ultimately able to prevent. On the basis of normative argument and empirical data, this article ultimately shows that we need to revise our understanding of ad bel- lum proportionality not only at the level of moral argument but also in international law.
  • 1 ANIMALS, SPORT, and the ENVIRONMENT Kass Gibson

    1 ANIMALS, SPORT, and the ENVIRONMENT Kass Gibson

    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Plymouth Marjon University Repository ANIMALS, SPORT, AND THE ENVIRONMENT Kass Gibson 1 Purpose – To outline the multiple ways in which animals are inserted into sporting practices, outline historical and contemporary approaches to studying human-animal sporting practices, and advocate for the centring of sociological problems in human- animal research in sporting contexts and cultures and for considering such problems in relation to environmental issues. Design/methodology/approach -- In the first part of the chapter, conceptual differentiation of animals in the animal-sport complex is presented. Subsequently, studies of interspecies sport are reviewed with reference to the ‘animal turn’ in the literature. In the second part, a critique is presented relating to: i) the privileging of companion animals, especially dogs and horses, which overlooks the multiple ways animals are integrated into (multispecies) sport; ii) micro-sociological and insider ethnographies of companionship displacing of sociological problems in favour of relationship perspectives; and iii) the environment as absent from analysis. The conclusion offers implications for understanding multispecies sport and the environment. Findings -- I chart a general shift in emphasis and focus from animals as an ‘absent- presence’ in pursuit of sociological knowledge towards a clearly defined focus on interspecies sport as a field of research characterised by investigations of relationships with companion animals through the ‘animal turn.’ Research limitations/implications – The focus on companion species means other animals (i.e., non-companions) are understudied, big picture sociological questions are often side-lined, environmental concerns marginalised, and sociological understanding of the environment more generally is either ignored or reduced to a conduit of human-animal interactions.