Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill [HL]

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill [HL] HOUSE OF LORDS Select Committee on the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill [HL] Volume III: Evidence— Individual Submissions Ordered to be printed 3 March 2005 and published 28 April 2005 Published by the Authority of the House of Lords London : The Stationery Office Limited £14.50 HL Paper 86-III ASSISTED DYING FOR THE TERMINALLY ILL BILL [HL] SELECTED INDIVIDUAL SUBMISSIONS The select committee received over 14,000 personal letters or other submissions from individuals in regard to the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill. A brief analysis of these is given in Paragraphs 230-231 of HL Paper 86-I. This volume reproduces a small selection. CONTENTS Written Evidence Page Professor Margaret Battin 1 Dr Bert Broeckaert 6 Right Reverend Christopher Budd 8 Dr Jane Campbell 10 Dr Colleen Cartwright & Associate Professor Malcolm Parker 16 Nessa Coyle 21 Alison Davis 22 R George 30 Professor John Griffiths 37 Colin Harte 42 Raymond Hoffenberg 46 Professor Emily Jackson 48 Dr Bert Keizer 55 Dr Helga Kuhse 56 Henk-Maarten Laane 61 Ian Maddocks 67 Professor Roger Magnusson 70 Yvonne Yi Wood Mak & Glyn Elwyn 71 Baroness Masham of Ilton DL 80 Professor T S Maughan 81 Professor Charles F Mckann 82 NatCen 85 National Group of Nurse Consultants in Palliative Care 87 Professor Richard Glynn Owens 91 All-Party Parliamentary Pro-Life Group 93 St Christopher’s Hospice 96 Ms Karen Sanders 97 Professor John Saunders 101 Dr Richard Scheffer 103 A D Wade 107 Dr Ian R Williams 110 Dr Z Zylicz 113 Written Evidence Memorandum by Professor Margaret Battin of Utah University, USA My Background I am Distinguished Professor of the Department of Philosophy and Adjunct Professor of Internal Medicine at the University of Utah in the USA. I have authored, edited, or co-edited at least a dozen books, among them a study of philosophical issues in suicide, a collection on age-rationing of medical care, a study of ethical issues in organized religion entitled Ethics in the Sanctuary, and The Least Worst Death: Essays in Bioethics on the End of Life. I have been engaged in research on end-of-life medical decisions in the Netherlands and Oregon. In 2000, I was a co-recipient of the Rosenblatt Prize, the University of Utah’s most prestigious award. Summary of Submission 1. Palliative care and physician-assisted death — The question “What would you rather have, access to palliative care and hospice, or access to physician-assisted death?” presents a false dichotomy and does not fully address the needs, wishes, and realities of dying patients. — Opponents contend that legalization would undermine progress that has been made in improving palliative care and hospice. However there is dramatic evidence in both Oregon and the Netherlands that palliative care improves with the legalization of physician aid-in-dying. 2. The argument over physician-assisted death — In the past, debates about risks and benefits of legalization have been based on theory and conjecture. We now have empirical knowledge and data about the eVects of legalization in Oregon, and the Netherlands. — Opponents’ presentation of data from Oregon and from the Netherlands is incomplete and frequently filled with factual inaccuracies and distortions. — Many of the value-assumptions of those who oppose legislation are based in religious views. While religious commitments are to be respected, they should not be permitted to control social policy. 3. Addressing (and defeating) opposing arguments — Patient autonomy is actualized in physician-assisted dying. — Studies of physician practice show a measurable incidence of physician-assisted death whether legal or not. — In the vast majority of cases, assisted death is provided in the last week or last day before death would otherwise have occurred. — Already accepted methods of negotiating death oVer the patient few protections or safeguards. — The comfort provided by having the possibility of an easier death, even if one never actually uses it, can be enormous. — Society allows patients to make other end-of-life decisions—like refusing further treatment— without assuming that the patient is depressed. — No proposed statute for legalization would permit providing physician-assisted death without careful safeguards. — There is no evidence of sustained substantive abuse in either Oregon or the Netherlands. — There is a deep compatibility of excellent palliative care and physician-assisted death. 4. The philosophical debate over legalizing physician-assisted suicide — “Liberty” and “mercy” are fundamental principles of our society and are central to the case for legalization. — There is an ethical requirement for physicians to try to respond to autonomous requests from patients, and to not abandon patients. 2 assisted dying for terminally ill bill [hl]: evidence — The opposition claims killing is intrinsically wrong but accepts killing in self-defense, war and capital punishment. — The opposition cannot show that the principles or liberty and freedom, basic to an open, liberal, democratic society, should be overridden. 5. Conclusion — Physician-assisted death should be one of the last-resort options available to a patient who is facing a hard death. DiVerent people who are dying have very diVerent ideas and values about what would be, for them, the least worst death, and for some, an easier death with the assistance of their physician is vastly preferable to being allowed to die of their disease. — An open practice is better for patients, families and society. Below I outline more extensively, my arguments and reasoning 1. Palliative care and physician-assisted death 1.1 There is a growing consensus that palliative care is a core part of treatment to be oVered to all severely ill patients who are potentially facing death(1). However, challenging questions remain about how broad a range of choice patients may have in this process and about what limitations should be placed on the physician’s obligation to address patient suVering. Physician-assisted death has long been the focal point of ethical and political debate—a “hot-button”, divisive issue in a domain where there is otherwise considerable consensus. 1.2 If the question were, “What would you rather have, access to palliative care and hospice, or access to physician-assisted death?” most people would choose palliative care and hospice. Palliative care should be part of standard care for all severely ill patients, even those who are continuing active disease-directed treatment, and hospice should be the standard of care for all those who understand and accept that they are dying. I agree that access to physician-assisted death should not undermine processes and programs that promote comprehensive palliative care for patients and their families. 1.3 However, to frame this question in this way presents a false dichotomy: it serves the purpose of opposing access to physician-assisted death without fully addressing the needs, wishes, and realities of dying patients. I therefore prefer a more inclusive question: “What would you prefer, access to excellent palliative care and hospice by themselves, or access to excellent hospice and palliative care plus legal access to a physician-assisted death as a last resort if your suVering becomes intolerable?” 1.4 Both proponents and opponents of legalization of physician-assisted death can join together in support of improving access to and delivery of comprehensive palliative care for all severely ill patients. Both sides can also acknowledge and bemoan inadequacies in access to and delivery of health care services in general in the United States (and I therefore presume the UK), as well as end-of-life care in particular.(2) 1.5 However, as a proponent of legalization, I part company with opponents in my belief that it is not fair or justified to hold the question of legal access to physician-assisted death hostage to await the solution of these inadequacies. 1.6 Opponents of legalization contend that legalization of physician-assisted death-which they routinely demonize by using the term “physician-assisted suicide”—would undermine progress that has been made in improving palliative care and hospice. Not only is this not true, but there is dramatic evidence in both Oregon and the Netherlands that palliative care improves with the legalization of physician aid-in-dying. 2. The argument over physician-assisted death 2.1 In the past, debates about risks and benefits of legalization have been based on theory and conjecture. Even in the USA, the Supreme Court suggested when it addressed this issue in 1997 that “perhaps we should wait [on the question of legalization] until we know more.”(3; 4) Fortunately, we now have five years of empirical knowledge about the eVects of legalization in Oregon,(5-7) as well even more detailed empirical data from the Netherlands at various points over a 16 year period. Both of these data sets support the claim that a legal process can be contained; that little or no substantive abuse occurs. None is reported in Oregon, and much, much less than has been claimed in the Netherlands. Legislation is also associated with critical improvements in palliative care and hospice in both settings.(8) 2.2 Although “suicide” can be heroic and/or rational depending on setting philosophical and orientation(9; 10; 11), suicide in much writing is conflated with mental illness, and suggests the self-destruction of the person who is not thinking clearly or acting rationally. In most cases where a patient requests
Recommended publications
  • The Limits of Rationality: Suicidality, Affectivity, and the Rational
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2014 The Limits of Rationality: Suicidality, Affectivity, and the Rational Maria Jennifer Kulp Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kulp, Maria Jennifer, "The Limits of Rationality: Suicidality, Affectivity, and the Rational" (2014). Dissertations. 1277. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/1277 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2014 Maria Jennifer Kulp LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO THE LIMITS OF RATIONALITY: RATIONALITY, SUICIDALITY, AND AFFECTIVITY A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY MARIA J. KULP CHICAGO, IL DECEMBER 2014 Copyright by Maria J. Kulp, 2014 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS There is not enough space to thank all of the people who made this dissertation possible, but I will do my best. I would like to thank the professors of the Loyola Philosophy Department generally: many of you helped form me philosophically, professionally, and personally, and I am in your debt. I must thank my director, Dr. Jennifer Parks. Her constant encouragement, generous feedback, and willingness to share her expertise with me made this project possible. Her ability to be both coach and cheerleader, while still balancing her own projects, never ceases to amaze me.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Ethics and Humanities in Utah Fall 2020 "Emerging Ethical Issues in Psychedelic Research" with Benjamin R
    Published by the Program in Medical Ethics and Humanities in the Division of Internal Medicine at the University of Utah School of Medicine Medical Ethics and Humanities in Utah Fall 2020 "Emerging Ethical Issues in Psychedelic Research" with Benjamin R. Lewis, MD By Brent Kious, MD, PhD Psychedelic substances such as psilocybin, LSD, MDMA, ayahuasca, and others are increasingly the subject of clinical research for a number of psychiatric conditions, including major depressive disorder, post-traumatic stress disorder, obsessive-compulsive disorder, and various substance use disorders. In his June 11, 2020 Evening Ethics presentation, Dr. Benjamin Lewis (Department of Psychiatry, University of Utah) provided an introduction to the science of psychedelic research and the ethical issues arising from it. Dr. Lewis first reviewed some of the results of preliminary clinical research utilizing psychedelics, which provides the tantalizing suggestion that psychedelics may be helpful in the treatment of conditions that are not otherwise easily remedied. He then considered the hypothesized Ben Lewis, MD mechanisms of action of these drugs and their impact on depression and related disorders, which may involve disruptions in the activity of the default mode network, a collection of brain circuits that are hyperactive in some psychiatric conditions, where this activity is often associated with rumination and negative self-directed thought. Intriguingly, he noted, therapeutic response in many clinical trials, across a variety of psychiatric conditions and psychedelic substances, has been associated with the occurrence of transformative, quasi-spiritual experiences in which subjects report a sense of dissolution of the self or a sense of connection with others or the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Protecting Patients' Autonomy: Supporting the “Right to Die”
    Sound Decisions: An Undergraduate Bioethics Journal Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 2 2015-5 Protecting Patients’ Autonomy: Supporting the “Right to Die” Nick Lyon Follow this and additional works at: https://soundideas.pugetsound.edu/sounddecisions Part of the Bioethics and Medical Ethics Commons Recommended Citation Lyon, Nick (2015) "Protecting Patients’ Autonomy: Supporting the “Right to Die”," Sound Decisions: An Undergraduate Bioethics Journal: Vol. 1 : Iss. 1 , Article 2. Available at: https://soundideas.pugetsound.edu/sounddecisions/vol1/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Publications at Sound Ideas. It has been accepted for inclusion in Sound Decisions: An Undergraduate Bioethics Journal by an authorized editor of Sound Ideas. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Lyon: Protecting Patients’ Autonomy Protecting Patients’ Autonomy: Supporting the “Right to Die” By Nicholas Lyon As medical techniques have increased in complexity, death can be delayed more and more, and the debate over euthanasia has become increasingly important. Patients with chronic ailments such as AIDS or cancer can now receive treatments that allow them to survive for far longer than what was possible even only a few decades ago. Through the use of modern genetic analysis tools, companies like 23andMe have allowed people of all ages to know what diseases and infirmities they are prone to long before the onset of symptoms. Despite these advancements however, society’s definition of “survive” remains purely having the body’s mechanical processes continue, and fails to incorporate the patient’s suffering and quality of life into the discussion. Due to the intrinsically subjective nature of such complaints from a patient, the critical factor to be considered in the ethics of requests to die will be how the patient views their suffering and quality of life, not the observations of third parties.
    [Show full text]
  • Utah LWV Study on Aid in Dying
    Death with Dignity A Study by the League of Women Voters of Utah January 2016 The League of Women Voters is a nonpartisan political organization that encourages informed and active participation in government, works to increases understanding of major public policy issues, and influences public policy through education and advocacy. Study Committee Vickie Samuelson, Chair Tish Buroker Carol Jenson Jill Lesh Sandy Peck A.J. Schanfield Liana Teteberg Study Editors Kathryn Fitzgerald John O’Connell Interviews Margaret Pabst Battin Ph. D Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Adjunct Professor of Internal Medicine, Division of Medical Ethics, University of Utah Rebecca Chavez-Houck Utah House of Representative, Chief Sponsor of the 2015 HB391 Death with Dignity Act League of Women Voters of Utah Death with Dignity State Study Table of Contents Purpose of This Study …………………………………………………….4 Historical Summary ………………………………………………………..4 What Do the Death with Dignity Laws Allow? …………………………..5 Which States Have Death with Dignity Laws? ………………………….6 States With Pending Legislation ………………………………………….7 What Are the Arguments for and Against Death with Dignity Legislation? …………………………………………………………………7 What Are the Impacts of End-of-Life Legislation? ………………………9 Positions of Key Medical Organizations ………………………………..11 Positions of Other Organizations ………………………………………..13 Religious Positions ………………………………………………………..14 Conclusion …………………………………………………………………15 Appendix A: Historical Timeline ………………………………………….17 Appendix B: Glossary .…………………………………………………….28 Bibliography ………………………………………………………………..30 Purpose of this Study The purpose of this study is to educate the League of Women Voters of Utah (LWVUT) membership and come to consensus on Death with Dignity legislation. Currently there is no League of Women Voters of the United States (LWVUS) position on Death with Dignity. Death with Dignity legislation has become of increasing public interest and concern.
    [Show full text]
  • Reproductive Freedom, Self-Directed Dying
    OUR BODIES, OUR LIVES, OUR RIGHT TO DECIDE? REPRODUCTIVE FREEDOM, SELF-DIRECTED DYING, AND WOMEN’S AUTONOMY by Ninia Leilani Baehr A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in American Studies MONTANA STATE UNIVERSITY Bozeman, Montana November 2017 ©COPYRIGHT by Ninia Leilani Baehr 2017 All Rights Reserved ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS First, I thank the ten veteran reproductive freedom activists whose names, backgrounds, and insights are featured in the final chapter of this dissertation. They trusted me to keep specific confidences and to reflect their views with integrity. This study would not have been possible without their insights. Second, I thank the five members of my dissertation committee: Dr. Mary Murphy (History); Dr. Robert Rydell (History and American Studies); Dr. Kristen Intemann (Philosophy); Dr. Walter Fleming (Native American Studies); and Dr. Elizabeth Rink (Health and Human Development). Between them, they provided valuable guidance, excellent editing advice, and superb examples of accessible writing on a range of academic subjects. Third, I thank the abortion rights pioneers with whom I collected oral histories three decades ago, especially Laura Kaplan. I did not thank Laura publicly when I published my Master’s thesis under the name Abortion without Apology; my information about the Jane Abortion Service came from her, but many former Jane members were still not using their own names because their actions had been illegal. Since then, Laura has published the history of Jane. I now have the opportunity to thank her for introducing me to the radical history of the abortion rights movement years ago, and also for later introducing me to the National Women’s Health Network, where I learned about the reproductive justice model that informs this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Ethics and Humanities in Utah
    Published by the Program in Medical Ethics and Humanities in the Division of Internal Medicine at the University of Utah School of Medicine Medical Ethics and Humanities in Utah Summer 2020 Medical Ethics and Humanities Amidst a Pandemic As news of the novel coronavirus spread in the past few months, so did the awareness of the ethical dilemmas that would arise globally and the desire to look to the arts and humanities to help people in these difficult and uncertain times. The Program in Medical Ethics and Humanities has been honored to field an unprecedented number of questions recently about how to face COVID-19 and to be part of the changes required in educational practices. In the School of Medicine Curriculum In mid-March 2020, with safety in mind and following the guidance of national governing bodies, all medical students were pulled from clinical rotations and most of the School of Medicine curriculum moved online. This abrupt but necessary shift called for great creativity and patience, as faculty and staff looked for ways to deliver high-quality education and training from a distance. PMEH faculty have offered two additional elective courses for medical students in their clinical years, who find themselves in the position of not being able to participate in direct patient care. Leslie Francis, PhD, JD, has offered a second, asynchronous online section expressly for advanced medical students of the popular “Health Law for Non- Lawyers,” which she and Teneille Brown, JD, have taught annually as an Interprofessional, synchronous online course for health science students. Susan Inside This Issue Sample, PhD, MFA and Gretchen Case, PhD, MA, along with Neurology’s Awais Riaz, MD, have created and are teaching their new elective called “Narrative Lead Article: PMEH 1-3 Reflection for Clerkship and Beyond.” This course is taught with both synchronous and & Pandemic asynchronous elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Euthanasia: a Challenge to Medical Ethics Rui Nunes*And Guilhermina Rego Centre of Bioethics, Faculty of Medicine of the University of Porto, Alameda Prof
    l Rese ca arc ni h li & C f B o i o l e Journal of a t h n Nunes et al., J Clin Res Bioeth 2016, 7:4 r i c u s o J DOI: 10.4172/2155-9627.1000282 ISSN: 2155-9627 Clinical Research & Bioethics Commentary Open Access Euthanasia: A Challenge to Medical Ethics Rui Nunes*and Guilhermina Rego Centre of Bioethics, Faculty of Medicine of the University of Porto, Alameda Prof. Hernâni Monteiro, 4200-319, Porto, Portugal *Corresponding author: Rui Nunes, Centre of Bioethics, Faculty of Medicine of the University of Porto, Alameda Prof. Hernâni Monteiro, 4200-319, Porto, Portugal, Tel: + 351-225513625; Fax: +351 225513697; E-mail: [email protected] Received date: July 31, 2016; Accepted date: August 18, 2016; Published date: August 20, 2016 Copyright: © 2016 Nunes R, et al. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited Introduction Euthanasia and the Right to Choose For many decades the euthanasia debate is particularly controversial Although there is a strong debate in modern societies over the in modern societies. Indeed, in the northern European tradition, as legalisation of physician-assisted suicide, many ethicists of different well as in countries of Anglo-American influence, euthanasia, philosophical backgrounds are comfortable with voluntary euthanasia physician-assisted suicide and other end-of-life decisions are an and the right to die with dignity [4]. For instance, it is well known that important source of social debate.
    [Show full text]
  • Margaret Battin, the Ethics of Suicide
    Utah Authors: Margaret Battin, The Ethics of Suicide: Historical Sources OSHER 892-001 Dates: Monday, 4/11/2016 Times: 9:30AM- 11:30AM Location: Jewish Community Center, 2 North Medical Drive, Salt Lake City Instructor: Margaret Battin Course Overview Is suicide wrong, profoundly morally wrong? Almost always wrong, but excusable in a few cases? Sometimes morally permissible? Imprudent, but not wrong? Is it sick, a matter of mental illness? Is it a private matter or a largely social one? Could it sometimes be right, or a "noble duty," or even a fundamental human right? Whether it is called "suicide" or not, what role may a person play in the end of his or her own life? This collection of primary sources--the principal texts of ethical interest from major writers in western and nonwestern cultures, from the principal religious traditions, and from oral cultures where observer reports of traditional practices are available, spanning Europe, Asia, the Middle East, Africa, Oceania, the Arctic, and North and South America--facilitates exploration of many controversial practical issues: physician-assisted suicide or aid-in-dying; suicide in social or political protest; self-sacrifice and martyrdom; suicides of honor or loyalty; religious and ritual practices that lead to death, including sati or widow-burning, hara-kiri, and sallekhana, or fasting unto death; and suicide bombings, kamikaze missions, jihad, and other tactical and military suicides. This collection has no interest in taking sides in controversies about the ethics of suicide; rather, rather, it serves to expand the character of these debates, by showing them to be multi-dimensional, a complex and vital part of human ethical thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Suicide” Is Inaccurate, Biased Term to Describe Terminally-Ill Patients’ End-Of-Life Choices Public Opinion & Medical Experts Urge Media to Adopt Neutral Terms
    “Suicide” is Inaccurate, Biased Term to Describe Terminally-Ill Patients’ End-of-Life Choices Public Opinion & Medical Experts Urge Media to Adopt Neutral Terms PRESS KIT Why it’s Wrong To Refer to “Aid-In-Dying” as “Suicide” • Terminally ill people who want the choice of aid in dying do not want to die but, by definition, they are dying. They are facing an imminent, inevitable death and they simply want the option to avoid unbearable suffering. • “Suicide” is hurtful and derogatory term to both a dying patient and the patient’s loved ones. It conjures images of irrational, depressed teenagers, adults with mental illness, and terrorist bombers. It suggests guns and violence. It suggests the patient is choosing death over life. • Cancer patient Char Andrews told the National Press Club, it is “an insult” to her fight against her illness to call the choice she wants “suicide.” • Cancer patient Jack Newbold told reporters that he resented media reports announcing that he was going to kill himself. “I am not committing suicide, and I don’t want to die. I’m not killing myself; cancer is taking care of that.” • Recently the Oregon Department of Human Services removed all reference to “assisted suicide” from its reporting on the Oregon Death with Dignity Act. A spokesperson admitted the agency probably never should have used the term in the first place. • The Oregon Death With Dignity Act specifically states that a the ending of one’s own life under the controls and safeguards of the law is legally not a suicide. • The American Public Health
    [Show full text]
  • Medicine and the Marketplace: the Moral Dimensions of Managed
    J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme.26.4.293 on 1 August 2000. Downloaded from Journal of Medical Ethics 2000;26:291–295 Book reviews Physician-assisted end-of-life issues and she and her of the “slippery slope” and to the fellow editors have produced what is, relevance of the Dutch experience in Suicide: Expanding on the whole, an interesting, readable this context. the Debate and topical collection of essays. Finally, contributions on the Whether it succeeds in expanding and achievements and availability of pallia- deepening the debate is, however, tive care, the Oregon law, and on the Edited by Margaret P Battin, itself a matter for debate. alleged distinction between physician- Rosamund Rhodes and Anita Silvers, On the one hand, a number of con- assisted suicide and euthanasia, would New York and London, Routledge, tributions do help to develop the have been valuable. The book does, 1998, 463 pages, £45. debate, particularly Patricia King and however, have useful appendices con- Leslie Wolf’s essay on the perspective taining the text of the Supreme Court This substantial academic volume, of African-Americans, Patricia judgments; the “philosophers’ brief” which seeks to expand the debate on Mann’s on the meaning of death, and submitted to the court, and the physician-assisted suicide, is a signifi- the contribution by Margaret Battin Oregon Death With Dignity Act. cant addition to the growing number herself, which questions the common In short, in some significant re- of edited works on one of the most assumption that physician-assisted spects this volume serves to expand important issues in contemporary suicide should or would be rare.
    [Show full text]
  • Margaret Battin the Acadia Institute Project on Bioethics in American Society Page 1
    Margaret Battin The Acadia Institute Project on Bioethics in American Society page 1 1 June 23, 1998. Interview with Margaret Battin, PhD, Professor, Department of Philosophy, 2 University of Utah, and Adjunct Professor, Division of Medical Ethics, Department of Internal 3 Medicine, LDS Hospital and University of Utah School of Medicine. The interview is being 4 conducted by Judith Swazey at Professor Battin's office at the University of Utah. 5 6 Swazey: Tell me how you would characterize bioethics. 7 8 Battin: This a question which I think I would like to be answering during the entire course of 9 the interview. My first characterization would be that it's a hybrid discipline; it has 10 scholarly elements, it has practical elements, it has policy elements, and all those 11 coexist in a degree of what you might call amicable tension. They are in part in 12 conflict with each other but in part make each other possible. I think it's not easy to 13 give too straightforward an answer to this question. 14 15 Swazey: What makes it a discipline at this point? 16 17 Battin: It doesn't have to be called a discipline. It's certainly institutionally structured partly 18 that way. It's housed in many academic departments; there are professors of 19 philosophy, professors of theology, professors of literature. It's also housed in 20 medical schools and institutions, so there are many MD's and non-MD's who have 21 clinical appointments who do bioethics. It's also housed in law schools, so there are 22 law faculty, and then a great many other people.
    [Show full text]
  • MEDICALLY ASSISTED DYING I. INTRODUCTION There Has Been a Significant Debate in the United States and Elsewhere Over the Past Tw
    MEDICALLY ASSISTED DYING I. INTRODUCTION There has been a significant debate in the United States and elsewhere over the past two decades over the propriety of medically assisted death; that is, medical care designed to help a patient die how and when the patient wants to die. Every state allows a physician to aid a patient who wishes to discontinue life-sustaining medical care, at least under most circumstances. May a health care provider also provide affirmative intervention that will hasten the patient’s death? Under what circumstances? The language we use to discuss these questions has become especially divisive over the past few years, and we must be careful how we use words that have become laden with political and philosophical meaning. “Euthanasia,” for example, generally refers to an affirmative act that directly and immediately causes the death of a patient for the benefit of that patient. “Involuntary euthanasia” is sometimes used to describe euthanasia against the will of the patient, although sometimes it means euthanasia without the formal and expressed consent of the patient. “Voluntary euthanasia” is sometimes used to refer to euthanasia upon request of the patient, although most careful thinkers avoid using that term altogether. “Active euthanasia” sometimes refers to some affirmative act of euthanasia, while “passive euthanasia” generally refers, technically incorrectly, to withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatment. “Suicide” can refer to any act taken by a person to intentionally end his life (including the act of a patient taking a prescribed lethal dose of medication), but sometimes it refers only to an act taken by someone acting irrationally, or under the influence of extraordinary emotional distress or mental disease (and not, for example, to the act of a terminally ill, competent patient who knowingly takes a prescribed lethal dose to end his suffering).
    [Show full text]