Large Cardinals from Determinacy Peter Koellner and W

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Large Cardinals from Determinacy Peter Koellner and W Large Cardinals from Determinacy Peter Koellner and W. Hugh Woodin Contents 1Introduction ....................... 2 1.1 Determinacy and Large Cardinals . 2 1.2 Notation ......................... 16 2 BasicResults....................... 18 2.1 Preliminaries. .. .. .. .. .. .. 18 2.2 BoundednessandBasicCoding . 22 2.3 Measurability ...................... 26 2.4 TheLeastStable .................... 32 2.5 Measurability of the Least Stable . 40 3Coding........................... 44 3.1 CodingLemma ..................... 44 3.2 UniformCodingLemma . 49 3.3 Applications ....................... 55 R 4 A Woodin Cardinal in HODL( ) ............ 58 4.1 Reflection ........................ 59 4.2 StrongNormality . 72 4.3 AWoodinCardinal . 91 5 Woodin Cardinals in General Settings . 95 5.1 FirstAbstraction . 97 5.2 Strategic Determinacy . 100 1 1. Introduction 2 5.3 Generation Theorem . 109 5.4 SpecialCases ......................137 6 Definable Determinacy . 145 6.1 Lightface Definable Determinacy . 146 6.2 Boldface Definable Determinacy . 169 7 Second-Order Arithmetic . 177 7.1 First Localization . 179 7.2 Second Localization . 186 8 FurtherResults ..................... 187 8.1 Large Cardinals and Determinacy . 188 8.2 HOD-Analysis . .192 Bibliography......................... 199 1. Introduction In this chapter we give an account of Woodin’s technique for deriving large cardinal strength from determinacy hypotheses. These results appear here for the first time and for this reason we have gone into somewhat more detail than is customary in a handbook. All unattributed results that follow are either folklore or due to Woodin. 1.1. Determinacy and Large Cardinals In the era of set theory following the discovery of independence a major concern has been the discovery of new axioms that settle the statements left undecided by the standard axioms (ZFC). One interesting feature that has emerged is that there are often deep connections between axioms that spring from entirely different sources. In this chapter we will be concerned with one instance of this phenomenon, namely, the connection between axioms of definable determinacy and large cardinal axioms. In this introduction we will give a brief overview of axioms of definable determinacy and large cardinal axioms (in sections A and B), discuss their 1. Introduction 3 interconnections (in sections C and D), and give an overview of the chapter (in section E). At some points we will draw on notation and basic notions that are explained in fuller detail in sections 1.2 and 2.1. A. Determinacy For a set of reals A ⊆ ωω consider the game where two players take turns playing natural numbers: I x(0) x(2) x(4) . II x(1) x(3) . At the end of a round of this game the two players will have produced a real x, obtained through “interleaving” their plays. We say that Player I wins the round if x ∈ A; otherwise Player II wins the round. The set A is said to be determined if one of the players has a “winning strategy” in the associated game, that is, a strategy which ensures that the player wins a round regardless of how the other player plays. The Axiom of Determinacy (AD) is the statement that every set of reals is determined. It is straightforward to see that very simple sets are determined. For example, if A is the set of all reals then clearly I has a winning strategy; if A is empty then clearly II has a winning strategy; and if A is countable then II has a winning strategy (by “diagonalizing”). A more substantive result is that if A is closed then one player must have a winning strategy. This might lead one to expect that all sets of reals are determined. However, it is straightforward to use the Axiom of Choice (AC) to construct a non- determined set (by listing all winning strategies and “diagonalizing” across them). For this reason AD was never really considered as a serious candidate for a new axiom. However, there is an interesting class of related axioms that are consistent with AC, namely, the axioms of definable determinacy. These axioms extend the above pattern by asserting that all sets of reals at a given 1 level of complexity are determined, notable examples being, ∆∼ 1-determinacy (all Borel sets of reals are determined), PD (all projective sets of reals are R determined) and ADL( ) (all sets of reals in L(R) are determined). One issue is whether these are really new axioms or whether they follow from ZFC. In the early development of the subject the result on the deter- minacy of closed sets was extended to higher levels of definability. These 1 developments culminated in Martin’s proof of ∆∼ 1-determinacy in ZFC. It turns out that this result is close to optimal—as one climbs the hierarchy 1. Introduction 4 1 of definability, shortly after ∆1 one arrives at axioms that fall outside the ∼ R provenance of ZFC. For example, this is true of PD and ADL( ). Thus, R we have here a hierarchy of axioms (including PD and ADL( )) which are genuine candidates for new axioms. There are actually two hierarchies of axioms of definable determinacy, one involving lightface notions of definability (by which we mean notions 1 (such as ∆2) that do not involve real numbers as parameters) and the other involving boldface notions of definability (by which we mean notions (such 1 as ∆∼ 2) that do involve real numbers as parameters). (See Jackson’s chapter in this Handbook for details concerning the various grades of definability and the relevant notation.) Each hierarchy is, of course, ordered in terms of increasing complexity. Moreover, each hierarchy has a natural limit: the natural limit of the lightface hierarchy is OD-determinacy (all OD sets of reals are determined) and the natural limit of the boldface hierarchy is OD(R)- determinacy (all OD(R) sets of reals are determined). The reason these are natural limits is that the notions of lightface and boldface ordinal definability are candidates for the richest lightface and boldface notions of definability. To see this (for the lightface case) notice first that any notion of definability which does not render all of the ordinals definable can be transcended (as can be seen by considering the least ordinal which is not definable according to the notion) and second that the notion of ordinal definability cannot be so transcended (since by reflection OD is ordinal definable). It is for this reason that G¨odel proposed the notion of ordinal definability as a candidate for an “absolute” notion of definability. Our limiting cases may thus be regarded as two forms of absolute definable determinacy. So we have two hierarchies of increasingly strong candidates for new ax- ioms and each has a natural limit. There are two fundamental questions concerning such new axioms. First, are they consistent? Second, are they true? In the most straightforward sense these questions are asked in an ab- solute sense and not relative to a particular theory such as ZFC. But since we are dealing with new axioms, the traditional means of answering such questions—namely, by establishing their consistency or provability relative to the standard axioms (ZFC)—is not available. Nevertheless, one can hope to establish results—such as relative consistency and logical connections with respect to other plausible axioms—that collectively shed light on the origi- nal, absolute question. Indeed, there are a number of results that one can R bring to bear in favour of PD and ADL( ). For example, these axioms lift the structure theory that can be established in ZFC to their respective domains, 1. Introduction 5 namely, second-order arithmetic and L(R). Moreover, they do so in a fash- ion which settles a remarkable number of statements that are independent of ZFC. In fact, there is no “natural” statement concerning their respective domains that is known to be independent of these axioms. (For more on the structure theory provided by determinacy and the traditional considerations in their favour see [10] and for more recent work see Jackson’s chapter in this Handbook.) The results of this chapter figure in the case for PD and R ADL( ). However, our concern will be with the question of relative consis- tency; more precisely, we wish to calibrate the consistency strength of axioms of definable determinacy—in particular, the ultimate axioms of lightface and boldface determinacy—in terms of the large cardinal hierarchy. There are some reductions that we can state at the outset. In terms of consistency strength the two hierarchies collapse at a certain stage: Kechris and Solovay showed that ZF + DC implies that in the context of L[x] for x ∈ ω 1 ω , OD-determinacy and ∆2-determinacy are equivalent (see Theorem 6.6). R And it is a folklore result that ZFC+OD(R)-determinacy and ZFC+ADL( ) are equiconsistent. Thus, in terms of consistency strength, the lightface 1 hierarchy collapses at ∆2-determinacy and the boldface hierarchy collapses R at ADL( ). So if one wishes to gauge the consistency strength of lightface 1 and boldface determinacy it suffices to concentrate on ∆2-determinacy and R ADL( ). 1 Now, it is straightforward to see that if ∆2-determinacy holds then it R holds in L[x] for some real x and likewise if ADL( ) (or AD) holds then it holds in L(R). Thus, the natural place to study the consistency strength of lightface definable determinacy is L[x] for some real x and the natural place to study the consistency strength of boldface definable determinacy (or full determinacy) is L(R). For this reason these two models will be central in what follows. To summarize: We shall be investigating the consistency strength of light- 1 L(R) face and boldface determinacy. This reduces to ∆2-determinacy and AD . The settings L[x] and L(R) will play a central role.
Recommended publications
  • Set Theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, Xii + 621 Pp., '$53.00
    BOOK REVIEWS 775 BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 3, Number 1, July 1980 © 1980 American Mathematical Society 0002-9904/80/0000-0 319/$01.75 Set theory, by Thomas Jech, Academic Press, New York, 1978, xii + 621 pp., '$53.00. "General set theory is pretty trivial stuff really" (Halmos; see [H, p. vi]). At least, with the hindsight afforded by Cantor, Zermelo, and others, it is pretty trivial to do the following. First, write down a list of axioms about sets and membership, enunciating some "obviously true" set-theoretic principles; the most popular Hst today is called ZFC (the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms with the axiom of Choice). Next, explain how, from ZFC, one may derive all of conventional mathematics, including the general theory of transfinite cardi­ nals and ordinals. This "trivial" part of set theory is well covered in standard texts, such as [E] or [H]. Jech's book is an introduction to the "nontrivial" part. Now, nontrivial set theory may be roughly divided into two general areas. The first area, classical set theory, is a direct outgrowth of Cantor's work. Cantor set down the basic properties of cardinal numbers. In particular, he showed that if K is a cardinal number, then 2", or exp(/c), is a cardinal strictly larger than K (if A is a set of size K, 2* is the cardinality of the family of all subsets of A). Now starting with a cardinal K, we may form larger cardinals exp(ic), exp2(ic) = exp(exp(fc)), exp3(ic) = exp(exp2(ic)), and in fact this may be continued through the transfinite to form expa(»c) for every ordinal number a.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics 144 Set Theory Fall 2012 Version
    MATHEMATICS 144 SET THEORY FALL 2012 VERSION Table of Contents I. General considerations.……………………………………………………………………………………………………….1 1. Overview of the course…………………………………………………………………………………………………1 2. Historical background and motivation………………………………………………………….………………4 3. Selected problems………………………………………………………………………………………………………13 I I. Basic concepts. ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….15 1. Topics from logic…………………………………………………………………………………………………………16 2. Notation and first steps………………………………………………………………………………………………26 3. Simple examples…………………………………………………………………………………………………………30 I I I. Constructions in set theory.………………………………………………………………………………..……….34 1. Boolean algebra operations.……………………………………………………………………………………….34 2. Ordered pairs and Cartesian products……………………………………………………………………… ….40 3. Larger constructions………………………………………………………………………………………………..….42 4. A convenient assumption………………………………………………………………………………………… ….45 I V. Relations and functions ……………………………………………………………………………………………….49 1.Binary relations………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….49 2. Partial and linear orderings……………………………..………………………………………………… ………… 56 3. Functions…………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….…….. 61 4. Composite and inverse function.…………………………………………………………………………… …….. 70 5. Constructions involving functions ………………………………………………………………………… ……… 77 6. Order types……………………………………………………………………………………………………… …………… 80 i V. Number systems and set theory …………………………………………………………………………………. 84 1. The Natural Numbers and Integers…………………………………………………………………………….83 2. Finite induction
    [Show full text]
  • Biography Paper – Georg Cantor
    Mike Garkie Math 4010 – History of Math UCD Denver 4/1/08 Biography Paper – Georg Cantor Few mathematicians are house-hold names; perhaps only Newton and Euclid would qualify. But there is a second tier of mathematicians, those whose names might not be familiar, but whose discoveries are part of everyday math. Examples here are Napier with logarithms, Cauchy with limits and Georg Cantor (1845 – 1918) with sets. In fact, those who superficially familier with Georg Cantor probably have two impressions of the man: First, as a consequence of thinking about sets, Cantor developed a theory of the actual infinite. And second, that Cantor was a troubled genius, crippled by Freudian conflict and mental illness. The first impression is fundamentally true. Cantor almost single-handedly overturned the Aristotle’s concept of the potential infinite by developing the concept of transfinite numbers. And, even though Bolzano and Frege made significant contributions, “Set theory … is the creation of one person, Georg Cantor.” [4] The second impression is mostly false. Cantor certainly did suffer from mental illness later in his life, but the other emotional baggage assigned to him is mostly due his early biographers, particularly the infamous E.T. Bell in Men Of Mathematics [7]. In the racially charged atmosphere of 1930’s Europe, the sensational story mathematician who turned the idea of infinity on its head and went crazy in the process, probably make for good reading. The drama of the controversy over Cantor’s ideas only added spice. 1 Fortunately, modern scholars have corrected the errors and biases in older biographies.
    [Show full text]
  • Tall, Strong, and Strongly Compact Cardinals ∗†
    Tall, Strong, and Strongly Compact Cardinals ∗y Arthur W. Apter z Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth Avenue New York, New York 10016 USA http://faculty.baruch.cuny.edu/aapter [email protected] August 12, 2017 Abstract We construct three models in which there are different relationships among the classes of strongly compact, strong, and non-strong tall cardinals. In the first two of these models, the strongly compact and strong cardinals coincide precisely, and every strongly compact/strong cardinal is a limit of non-strong tall cardinals. In the remaining model, the strongly compact cardinals are precisely characterized as the measurable limits of strong cardinals, and every strongly compact cardinal is a limit of non-strong tall cardinals. These results extend and generalize those of of [3] and [1]. 1 Introduction and Preliminaries We begin with some definitions. Suppose κ is a cardinal and λ ≥ κ is an arbitrary ordinal. κ is λ tall if there is an elementary embedding j : V ! M with critical point κ such that j(κ) > λ and M κ ⊆ M. κ is tall if κ is λ tall for every ordinal λ. Hamkins made a systematic study of tall cardinals in [10]. In particular, among many other results, he showed that every cardinal which is ∗2010 Mathematics Subject Classifications: 03E35, 03E55. yKeywords: Supercompact cardinal, strongly compact cardinal, strong cardinal, tall cardinal, non-reflecting stationary set of ordinals, indestructibility. zThe author wishes to thank Stamatis Dimopoulos for helpful email correspondence on the subject matter of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Set-Theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms
    Set-theoretic Geology, the Ultimate Inner Model, and New Axioms Justin William Henry Cavitt (860) 949-5686 [email protected] Advisor: W. Hugh Woodin Harvard University March 20, 2017 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Mathematics and Philosophy Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Author’s Note . .4 1.2 Acknowledgements . .4 2 The Independence Problem 5 2.1 Gödelian Independence and Consistency Strength . .5 2.2 Forcing and Natural Independence . .7 2.2.1 Basics of Forcing . .8 2.2.2 Forcing Facts . 11 2.2.3 The Space of All Forcing Extensions: The Generic Multiverse 15 2.3 Recap . 16 3 Approaches to New Axioms 17 3.1 Large Cardinals . 17 3.2 Inner Model Theory . 25 3.2.1 Basic Facts . 26 3.2.2 The Constructible Universe . 30 3.2.3 Other Inner Models . 35 3.2.4 Relative Constructibility . 38 3.3 Recap . 39 4 Ultimate L 40 4.1 The Axiom V = Ultimate L ..................... 41 4.2 Central Features of Ultimate L .................... 42 4.3 Further Philosophical Considerations . 47 4.4 Recap . 51 1 5 Set-theoretic Geology 52 5.1 Preliminaries . 52 5.2 The Downward Directed Grounds Hypothesis . 54 5.2.1 Bukovský’s Theorem . 54 5.2.2 The Main Argument . 61 5.3 Main Results . 65 5.4 Recap . 74 6 Conclusion 74 7 Appendix 75 7.1 Notation . 75 7.2 The ZFC Axioms . 76 7.3 The Ordinals . 77 7.4 The Universe of Sets . 77 7.5 Transitive Models and Absoluteness .
    [Show full text]
  • Mice with Finitely Many Woodin Cardinals from Optimal Determinacy Hypotheses
    MICE WITH FINITELY MANY WOODIN CARDINALS FROM OPTIMAL DETERMINACY HYPOTHESES SANDRA MULLER,¨ RALF SCHINDLER, AND W. HUGH WOODIN Abstract We prove the following result which is due to the third author. 1 1 Let n ≥ 1. If Πn determinacy and Πn+1 determinacy both hold true and 1 # there is no Σn+2-definable !1-sequence of pairwise distinct reals, then Mn 1 exists and is !1-iterable. The proof yields that Πn+1 determinacy implies # that Mn (x) exists and is !1-iterable for all reals x. A consequence is the Determinacy Transfer Theorem for arbitrary n ≥ 1, 1 (n) 2 1 namely the statement that Πn+1 determinacy implies a (< ! − Π1) de- terminacy. Contents Abstract 1 Preface 2 Overview 4 1. Introduction 6 1.1. Games and Determinacy 6 1.2. Inner Model Theory 7 1.3. Mice with Finitely Many Woodin Cardinals 9 1.4. Mice and Determinacy 14 2. A Model with Woodin Cardinals from Determinacy Hypotheses 15 2.1. Introduction 15 2.2. Preliminaries 16 2.3. OD-Determinacy for an Initial Segment of Mn−1 32 2.4. Applications 40 2.5. A Proper Class Inner Model with n Woodin Cardinals 44 3. Proving Iterability 49 First author formerly known as Sandra Uhlenbrock. The first author gratefully ac- knowledges her non-material and financial support from the \Deutsche Telekom Stiftung". The material in this paper is part of the first author's Ph.D. thesis written under the su- pervision of the second author. 1 2 SANDRA MULLER,¨ RALF SCHINDLER, AND W. HUGH WOODIN 3.1.
    [Show full text]
  • SRB MEASURES for ALMOST AXIOM a DIFFEOMORPHISMS José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur
    SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur To cite this version: José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur. SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS. 2013. hal-00778407 HAL Id: hal-00778407 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00778407 Preprint submitted on 20 Jan 2013 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS JOSE´ F. ALVES AND RENAUD LEPLAIDEUR Abstract. We consider a diffeomorphism f of a compact manifold M which is Almost Axiom A, i.e. f is hyperbolic in a neighborhood of some compact f-invariant set, except in some singular set of neutral points. We prove that if there exists some f-invariant set of hyperbolic points with positive unstable-Lebesgue measure such that for every point in this set the stable and unstable leaves are \long enough", then f admits a probability SRB measure. Contents 1. Introduction 2 1.1. Background 2 1.2. Statement of results 2 1.3. Overview 4 2. Markov rectangles 5 2.1. Neighborhood of critical zone 5 2.2. First generation of rectangles 6 2.3. Second generation rectangles 7 2.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1901.02074V1 [Math.LO] 4 Jan 2019 a Xoskona Lrecrias Ih Eal Ogv Entv a Definitive a Give T to of Able Basis Be the Might Cardinals” [17]
    GENERIC LARGE CARDINALS AS AXIOMS MONROE ESKEW Abstract. We argue against Foreman’s proposal to settle the continuum hy- pothesis and other classical independent questions via the adoption of generic large cardinal axioms. Shortly after proving that the set of all real numbers has a strictly larger car- dinality than the set of integers, Cantor conjectured his Continuum Hypothesis (CH): that there is no set of a size strictly in between that of the integers and the real numbers [1]. A resolution of CH was the first problem on Hilbert’s famous list presented in 1900 [19]. G¨odel made a major advance by constructing a model of the Zermelo-Frankel (ZF) axioms for set theory in which the Axiom of Choice and CH both hold, starting from a model of ZF. This showed that the axiom system ZF, if consistent on its own, could not disprove Choice, and that ZF with Choice (ZFC), a system which suffices to formalize the methods of ordinary mathematics, could not disprove CH [16]. It remained unknown at the time whether models of ZFC could be found in which CH was false, but G¨odel began to suspect that this was possible, and hence that CH could not be settled on the basis of the normal methods of mathematics. G¨odel remained hopeful, however, that new mathemati- cal axioms known as “large cardinals” might be able to give a definitive answer on CH [17]. The independence of CH from ZFC was finally solved by Cohen’s invention of the method of forcing [2]. Cohen’s method showed that ZFC could not prove CH either, and in fact could not put any kind of bound on the possible number of cardinals between the sizes of the integers and the reals.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounding, Splitting and Almost Disjointness
    Bounding, splitting and almost disjointness Jonathan Schilhan Advisor: Vera Fischer Kurt G¨odelResearch Center Fakult¨atf¨urMathematik, Universit¨atWien Abstract This bachelor thesis provides an introduction to set theory, cardinal character- istics of the continuum and the generalized cardinal characteristics on arbitrary regular cardinals. It covers the well known ZFC relations of the bounding, the dominating, the almost disjointness and the splitting number as well as some more recent results about their generalizations to regular uncountable cardinals. We also present an overview on the currently known consistency results and formulate open questions. 1 CONTENTS Contents Introduction 3 1 Prerequisites 5 1.1 Model Theory/Predicate Logic . .5 1.2 Ordinals/Cardinals . .6 1.2.1 Ordinals . .7 1.2.2 Cardinals . .9 1.2.3 Regular Cardinals . 10 2 Cardinal Characteristics of the continuum 11 2.1 The bounding and the dominating number . 11 2.2 Splitting and mad families . 13 3 Cardinal Characteristics on regular uncountable cardinals 16 3.1 Generalized bounding, splitting and almost disjointness . 16 3.2 An unexpected inequality between the bounding and splitting numbers . 18 3.2.1 Elementary Submodels . 18 3.2.2 Filters and Ideals . 19 3.2.3 Proof of Theorem 3.2.1 (s(κ) ≤ b(κ)) . 20 3.3 A relation between generalized dominating and mad families . 23 References 28 2 Introduction @0 Since it was proven that the continuum hypothesis (2 = @1) is independent of the axioms of ZFC, the natural question arises what value 2@0 could take and it was shown @0 that 2 could be consistently nearly anything.
    [Show full text]
  • O&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE and MEASURABLE CARDINALS 0
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 30 (1986) 293-320 293 North-Holland o&ONSTRUCTIBLE UNIVERSE AND MEASURABLE CARDINALS Claude SURESON Dkpartement de Mathkmatiques, Universitk de Caen, 1403.2 Caen, France Communicated by A. Nerode Received 23 September 1984 In analogy with K. Godel’s model L, C. Chang [l] formulated the wr- constructible universe C”‘, using the infinitary language L,,,, instead of the language of Set Theory L,,. The cumulative hierarchy of sets obtained in this way has many similarities with the hierarchy of the constructible universe (except for a major point: the axiom of choice [l], [9]). C”’ can also be characterized as the least inner model closed under arbitrary countable sequences. This paper is inspired by results of R. Jensen and J. Silver concerning the existence of O# and the covering property for L. We consider here a stronger notion of indiscernibles for the model C”’ and we say that C”’ satisfies the ‘covering property’ if any set of ordinals X in the universe can be covered by a set in C”’ of cardinality ]X]‘O. The existence of ‘indiscernibles’ for C”’ is also linked to large cardinal assumptions, and our main result (in ZFC) can be summarized as shown in Diagram 1: Diagram 1. The first part is devoted to the study of indiscernibles for PI. We prove the implications (1) and (2). In the second section, we deal with the covering property and show (3).
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Stably Measurable Cardinals
    Stably measurable cardinals P.D. Welch School of Mathematics, University of Bristol, Bristol, BS ÕTW, England Dec. óß’th óþÕ Abstract We dene a weak iterability notion that is sucient for a number of arguments concerning Σ-denability at uncountable regular cardinals. In particular we give its exact consistency strength rstly in terms of the second uniform indiscernible for bounded subsets of : u( ), and secondly to give the consistency strength of a property of Lucke’s.¨ eorem: e following are equiconsistent: (i) ere exists which is stably measurable ; (ii) for some cardinal , u( ) = ( ); (iii) e Σ-club property holds at a cardinal . M H + H Here ( ) is the height of the smallest ăΣ ( ) containing + and all of ( ). Let R R Φ( ) be the assertion: @X Ď @r P [X is Σ( , r)-denable ←→ X P Σ(r)]. eorem: Assume is stably measurable. en Φ(). And a form of converse: eorem: Suppose there is no sharp for an inner model with a strong cardinal. en in the core model K we have: “DΦ()” is (set)-generically absolute ←→ ere are arbitrarily large stably measurable cardinals. When u( ) < ( ) we give some results on inner model reection. Õ Õ Introduction ere are a number of properties in the literature that fall in the region of being weaker than measur- ability, but stronger than j, and thus inconsistent with the universe being that of the constructible sets. Actual cardinals of this nature have been well known and are usually of ancient pedigree: Ramsey cardinals, Rowbottom cardinals, Erdos˝ cardinals, and the like (cf. for example, [ß]).
    [Show full text]