Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Jonathan Greig 29,998 words MSc by Research in Philosophy The University of Edinburgh August 20, 2014 (With minor corrections made November 19, 2014) This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ 1 Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Jonathan Greig Abstract The first principle, called the ‘One’, in Neoplatonism is typically asserted to be absolutely simpleand beyond being, such that all positive attributes implying multiplicity are denied of it. With this inmind, in his Commentary on Parmenides, Proclus critiques the view that the One constitutes its own being. In making this critique, Proclus has his predecessor, Plotinus, in mind, who, although agreeing that the One is beyond being and absolutely simple, also holds the view criticized. At the same time, Plotinus’ careful use of saying that the One is ‘as if’ (οἷον) self-constituted ensures that he is not contradicting himself when he also denies that the One is divided or made dual in its constituting its own being. With this in mind, one could go with John Dillon’s assessment that this disagreement is over semantics and that Proclus misunderstands Plotinus. However is Proclus misunderstanding Plotinus here, and are the differences between the two inconsequential on this count? In this dissertation, I wish to showthat Proclus is accounting for Plotinus’ ‘as if’ language through appropriating Plotinus’ understanding of the One’s causality, which is what makes possible Plotinus speaking of the One ‘as if’ causing itself. I focus on the two concepts of self-constitution in itself and the One’s causality for both figures. Plotinus understands self-constitution such that, in the realm of being with Intellect and Soul, it represents each entity imperfectly realizing the One’s perfect unity, which points to the One pre-containing perfect attributes that are imperfectly realized in Intellect. Likewise, the way Plotinus understands theOne producing Intellect implies that the One anticipates Intellect in pre-containing its effects as a direct cause, albeit in a way that transcends literal description. This is what makes possible the language of the One ‘as if’ being self-constituted for Plotinus. Proclus rather understands the process differently: self-constitution in the realm of being indicates the respective perfection of each such entity (such as Being, Life, and Intellect), while simultaneously necessitating higher causes, eventually leading to the One as the first, uncaused cause. Proclus’ One is rather an indirect cause through its production of beings by negation, starting with the two basic principles of the Limit and Unlimited as positive aspects of the One. Given these two factors of self-constitution in itself and the One’s causality for Plotinus and Proclus, there is reason to see an underlying disagreement. I finally conclude that Proclus addresses and critiques Plotinus’ causal model which supports the ‘as if’ language, which makes possible Plotinus’ quasi-self-constitution in the One, so that insofar as Proclus requires the One to be absolutely simple in negating all sense of multiplicity, Proclus’ critique is to this extent justified, where his own causal model is an attempt at improving on the inadequacy seen in Plotinus’ system. 2 Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Jonathan Greig Acknowledgements Special thanks to my supervisor, Dr. Inna Kupreeva, for all her support, insight, and advice in these past two years, and especially recently in the creation of this project. I also wish to thank Prof. Carlos Steel for his recommendation for me to look into the metaphysics of self-constitution (αὐθυπόστατον) in Proclus, which was the inspiration for this project. As well, I must thank Prof. Peter Adamson, Dr. Gary Gabor, Dr. David Butorac, Evan King, and Alan Brown for all of their insights and suggestions with textual references and help with understanding the various concepts involved in this project between Plotinus and Proclus. 3 Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Jonathan Greig Contents 1 Introduction 5 2 Self-Constitution and Its Conceptual Origin in Self-Motion 9 2.1 Self-Motion in Plato ........................................ 10 2.1.1 Assessing Plato on Self-Motion ............................. 13 2.2 Aristotle on Self-Motion and the Unmoved Mover ....................... 14 2.2.1 Self-Motion as Distinguished into Unmoved and Moved Movers ........... 15 2.2.2 Comparing Aristotle’s Approach with Plato’s on Self-Motion ............ 17 2.3 Plotinus on Self-Constitution ................................... 18 2.3.1 Intellect and Soul’s Self-Constitution .......................... 18 2.3.2 Answering the Aristotelian Objection to Self-Motion: Motion as an Aspect of Self- Constitution ........................................ 20 2.3.3 Conclusion: Self-Constitution in Plotinus’ System ................... 22 2.4 Proclus on Self-Constitution ................................... 22 2.4.1 Proclus’ Technical Concept of αὐθυπόστατον (Self-Constitution) ........... 23 2.4.2 Self-Constitution in the General Structure of Causality ................ 27 2.5 Conclusion: Comparing Plotinus and Proclus on the Concept of Self-Constitution ..... 28 3 Plotinus on the One and Its Causality 30 3.1 Plotinus’ Principle of Simplicity and the Necessity for the One as First Principle ...... 30 3.1.1 The One as Beyond Being and Absolutely Simple ................... 32 3.2 The One’s Causality of Being ................................... 33 3.2.1 The One as Causing By What It Does Not Possess ................... 34 3.2.2 The Two-Act Theory ................................... 36 3.3 The οἷον Principle: The One as Pre-Containing Multiplicity and Being ............ 39 3.4 Conclusion: Plotinus’ Conception of Simplicity and the Implications for Self-Constitution 40 4 Proclus on the One and Its Causality 42 4.1 Proclus’ Proof for the One .................................... 42 4.2 The One’s Causality of Being ................................... 45 4.2.1 The Principles of Limit and Unlimited ......................... 46 4.2.2 The One’s Causality via Negation ............................ 48 4.3 Conclusion: The One as Uncaused and Cause of Self-Constitution .............. 52 5 The One and Self-Constitution 54 5.1 Enn. VI.8.13–14: Plotinus’ Argument for the One as Cause of Its Own Being ........ 54 5.1.1 Contextualizing Plotinus’ Argument for the One’s Self-Constitution ........ 55 5.1.2 Plotinus’ Analogical Language as Corresponding with the One’s Being ....... 57 5.2 Reviewing Proclus’ Critique of Self-Constitution in the One ................. 59 5.3 Objection: Is Proclus’ Critique Justified? ............................ 61 5.4 Conclusion: Proclus’ Causal Model as a Response to Plotinus ................. 63 A The One and the Henads in Proclus 65 B Some Conceptual Background on the Limit and Unlimited in Proclus 68 4 Proclus and Plotinus on Self-Constitution in the One Jonathan Greig 1 Introduction The nature of the first principle’s causality is a major question for the Neoplatonists. From Plotinusonward, the Neoplatonic tradition has as its axiom that (1) all being is derived from a first principle that is an efficient cause, as well as final cause; and (2) that the first principle, the ‘One’, is absolutely simple and beyond being in itself.1 Where all being is characterized by some form of multiplicity, whether at the physical level or even the intelligible level, the One functions as the source of unity, and therefore existence, for all being. How the One is simple, and how the One functions as a cause of being, is at once a difficult, contested question for the Neoplatonists. Given this background, in the Commentary on Parmenides,2 Proclus critiques the view that the One is self-constituted, saying that what is self-constituted, ‘must necessarily be divisible into a superior and an inferior element; for it is superior in so far as it creates, and it is inferior in so far as it is created; the One, on the other hand, is entirely indivisible and non-multiple’ (In Parm. 1150.6–9; trans. Morrow/Dillon). For Proclus, self-constitution implies a distinction of cause and effect, between a ‘superior’ and ‘inferior’ aspect of the same being, which implies a duality that the One, by definition, precludes. In giving this critique, Proclus appears to have Plotinus in mind, the latter of whom holds that the One in some sense constitutes its own being: …for [the One] is the father of reason and cause and causative substance, which are certainly all far from chance, he would be the principle and in a way the exemplar (παράδειγμα) of all things which have no part in chance, truly and primarily, uncontaminated by chances and coincidence and happening, cause of himself and himself from himself and through himself. (Ennead VI.8.14.37–42; trans. Armstrong) Plotinus asserts self-constitution in the One insofar as it is the source of being and Intellect, so that because of this, the One is most free and in control of itself such that it constitutes its being from itself and not from chance or any prior cause.3 In the background to this disagreement, Plotinus and Proclus equally hold that the One is absolutely simple and beyond all multiplicity, even to the point that all literal knowledge of the One is impossible. As a result, both Plotinus and Proclus negate all positive attributes applying to the One, insofar as any such attribute implies multiplicity. At one level, both philosophers agree that theOneis beyond being a cause in any sense, even of having any activity or causation in relation to itself. Given this picture, one could go along with John Dillon’s assessment of Proclus’ critique: Proclus next turns to an attack on those Platonists who wish to make the One ‘self-constitutive’αὐθυπόστατον ( ). In Plotinus’ case, this is bound up with his doctrine, in Enn.
Recommended publications
  • Plato As "Architectof Science"
    Plato as "Architectof Science" LEONID ZHMUD ABSTRACT The figureof the cordialhost of the Academy,who invitedthe mostgifted math- ematiciansand cultivatedpure research, whose keen intellectwas able if not to solve the particularproblem then at least to show the methodfor its solution: this figureis quite familiarto studentsof Greekscience. But was the Academy as such a centerof scientificresearch, and did Plato really set for mathemati- cians and astronomersthe problemsthey shouldstudy and methodsthey should use? Oursources tell aboutPlato's friendship or at leastacquaintance with many brilliantmathematicians of his day (Theodorus,Archytas, Theaetetus), but they were neverhis pupils,rather vice versa- he learnedmuch from them and actively used this knowledgein developinghis philosophy.There is no reliableevidence that Eudoxus,Menaechmus, Dinostratus, Theudius, and others, whom many scholarsunite into the groupof so-called"Academic mathematicians," ever were his pupilsor close associates.Our analysis of therelevant passages (Eratosthenes' Platonicus, Sosigenes ap. Simplicius, Proclus' Catalogue of geometers, and Philodemus'History of the Academy,etc.) shows thatthe very tendencyof por- trayingPlato as the architectof sciencegoes back to the earlyAcademy and is bornout of interpretationsof his dialogues. I Plato's relationship to the exact sciences used to be one of the traditional problems in the history of ancient Greek science and philosophy.' From the nineteenth century on it was examined in various aspects, the most significant of which were the historical, philosophical and methodological. In the last century and at the beginning of this century attention was paid peredominantly, although not exclusively, to the first of these aspects, especially to the questions how great Plato's contribution to specific math- ematical research really was, and how reliable our sources are in ascrib- ing to him particular scientific discoveries.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources of the Central Christian Doctrine
    ! Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources ! of the Central Christian Doctrine Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX 77004 Paper published in A Journal from the Radical Reformation. A testimony to Biblical Unitarianism. Vol. 14, No.! 1, Spring 2007, pp. 3-31. Quis obsecro, nisi penitus amens logomachias has sine risu toleraret? Nec in Thalmud, nec in Alchoran, sunt tam horrendae blasfemiae. Haec nos hactenus audire ita sumus alsuefacti, ut nihil miremur. Futurae vero generationes stupenda haec iudicabunt. Stupenda sunt vere, plusquam ea daemonum inventa, quae Valentinianis tribuit Irenaeus. I implore you, who in his sane mind could tolerate such logomachias without bursting into laughter? Not in the Talmud, nor in the Qu’ran can one find such horrendous blasphemies. But we are accustomed to hear them to the point that nothing astonishes us. Future generations will judge them obscure. Indeed, they are obscure, much more than the diabolic inventions which Irenaeus attributed to the Valentinians. ! Michael Servetus Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. I. p. 46. Si locum mihi aliquem ostendas, quo verbum illud filius olim vocetur, fatebor me victum. Christianismi Restitutio, If you show me a single passage in which the Son was called the Word, I will give up. Michael Servetus, Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. III p. 108. ! Abstract This paper attempts to explain the sources of the central Christian doctrine about the nature of deity. We can trace a continuous line of thought from the Greek philosophy to the development of the doctrine of the Trinity. The first Christian doctrine was developed by Justin Martyr (114-165 C.E.).
    [Show full text]
  • Proclus and Artemis: on the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion
    Kernos Revue internationale et pluridisciplinaire de religion grecque antique 13 | 2000 Varia Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion Spyridon Rangos Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 DOI: 10.4000/kernos.1293 ISSN: 2034-7871 Publisher Centre international d'étude de la religion grecque antique Printed version Date of publication: 1 January 2000 ISSN: 0776-3824 Electronic reference Spyridon Rangos, « Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Ancient Religion », Kernos [Online], 13 | 2000, Online since 21 April 2011, connection on 01 May 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kernos/1293 ; DOI : 10.4000/kernos.1293 Kernos Kernos, 13 (2000), p. 47-84. Proclus and Artemis: On the Relevance of Neoplatonism to the Modern Study of Andent Religion* Imagine the situation in which contemporary philosophers would find themselves if Wittgenstein introduced, in his Philosophical Investigations, the religious figure of Jesus as Logos and Son of God in order to illuminate the puzzlement ofthe private-language paradox, or if in the second division of Being and Time Heidegger mentioned the archangel Michael to support the argument of 'being toward death'. Similar is the perplexity that a modern reader is bound to encounter when, after a highly sophisticated analysis of demanding metaphysical questions about the relationship of the one and the many, finitude and infinity, mind and body, Proclus, l in ail seriousness and without the slightest touch of irony, assigns to some traditional gods of Greek polytheism a definitive place in the structure of being.
    [Show full text]
  • PROCLUS on HESIOD's WORKS and DAYS Patrizia Marzillo
    PERFORMING AN ACADEMIC TALK: PROCLUS ON HESIOD’S WORKS AND DAYS Patrizia Marzillo Abstract From Socrates onwards orality was the favoured means of expression for those wholaterlovedtocallthemselves‘Platonic’.Theyusedtodiscussphilosophical issues in debates that turned into academic lectures and seminars. According to Plato’s original teaching, these talks should have not been “fixed” in written compositions, yet Plato himself put most of his doctrine into fictive “written dia- logues”.His followers intensified their connection with writing, above all for the purposes of teaching. On the one hand, they made notes on the lessons of their teachers; on the other, they enlarged their own talks in written compositions. Neoplatonists’ commentaries are often an amplification of their academic talks. The lessons held in the school of Athens or in Platonic circles coalesced into texts that mostly constitute Neoplatonic propaganda intended for the outside world. When Proclus directed the school in Athens, Plato and Aristotle were taught, but also theologian poets such as Homer, Orpheus, Hesiod. As the Suda reports, Proclus wrote commentaries on all of these poets, but the only onepreservedisthecommentaryonHesiod’sWorks and Days.Througha comparison of some passages from this commentary, I show how Proclus’ commentary on Hesiod is not only a good example of an oral lesson that has become a written commentary, but also, importantly, of a text that aimed at the diffusion of Neoplatonic ideas among an audience of non-adherents. As his biographer and disciple Marinus of Neapolis relates, the neo- Platonist Proclus was accustomed to write about lines a day.1 Besides being a very prolific author, he was also an indefatigable teacher since in addition to his writing he held several classes during the day and also gave evening talks.2 What I propose to show in this paper is the profound interaction between the oral communication in his school and the written performance of his commentaries.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and Religion at the Crossroads of Aristotelian Biology, Hippocratic Medicine and Platonic Theurgy
    Studia Antiqua et Archaeologica 23(2): 333–349 Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and religion at the crossroads of Aristotelian biology, Hippocratic medicine and Platonic theurgy Eugene AFONASIN1 Abstract. In the first part of the paper, I will briefly discuss certain peculiarities of the medical profession in antiquity. In his Philosophical History (fr. 80–84 Athanassiadi) Damascius narrates about a philosopher, named Asclepiodotus, whose interests ranged from Platonic philosophy to Aristotelian natural sciences. Asclepiodotus’ instructor in medical matters, a son of a doctor from the island of Rhodos, Iacobus, is pictured by Damascius as an exemplary figure (fr. 84), who, unlike many of his contemporaries, always tested the opinions of others and gained a reputation of an extremely successful physician, although the methods of treatment, ascribed to him by Damascius, are highly reminiscent of those presented as the Pythagorean by Iamblichus (On the Pythagorean way of life 244). In this respect both Iacobus and Asclepiodotus are conformed to the best standards of medical ethics, and pass the test set by Galen in his “On examination by which the best physicians are recognized”, except perhaps by the fact that they preferred to base their activities on such authorities as Aristotle and the Methodist Soranus rather than on a list of the “dogmatists” proposed by Galen. In the second part of the paper, dedicated to the cult of Asclepius in Late Antiquity, I will look at various kinds of evidence taken from the Neoplatonic philosophers. Having discussed first the principal philosophical interpretations of Asclepius found in Apuleius, Aelianus, Macrobius, Julian, Porphyry, Iamblichus, Proclus, Damascius, etc., we turn to Proclus’ attitude to Athena and Asclepius as reflected in Marinus’ Vita Procli and finally discuss the cult of Eshmun as found in Damascius.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016
    Revista Classica, v. 30, n. 2, p. 137-142, 2017 137 BONAZZI, Mauro; SCHORN, Stefan. Bios Philosophos: Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016. 313p. ISBN 978-2-503-56546-0 Gustavo Laet Gomes* * Mestre em Filosofia Bernardo C. D. A. Vasconcelos** pela Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais. guslaet@ gmail.com Bios Philosophos. Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography (Brepols, 2016), organized by Mauro Bonazzi and Stefan Schorn, delivers a ** Mestre em Filosofia pela both deep and wide tour through the philosophical aspects of Greek Universidade Federal biographical production. On one hand, it does not concentrate only in de Minas Gerais. the later periods of Greek philosophy, when biographical production bernardovasconcelos abounded, but goes all the way back to the fourth century BCE, when @gmail.com biographical texts were fragmentary and mingled with other styles. On the other, it tries to unveil the philosophical motives in the works of authors who tend to be disregarded as historians, biographers, hagiographers or even as mere fans of the most prominent figures of their own schools. In our review, we will attempt to give a brief account of the ten articles that make up this volume, which, in turn, will hopefully provide an overview of the different connections between the biographies and biographers and their philosophical motives. Thomas Bénatouïl’s Pythagore chez Dicéarque: anectodes biographiques et critique de la philosophie contemplative (p. 11-36) proposes an inversion of the traditional interpretation regarding the testimony of Dicaearchus of Messana about the life of Pythagoras. Since antiquity, Dicaearchus’ reports tend to be seen as positive, because they present a Pythagoras devoid of mysticism and apparently more interested in practical matters.
    [Show full text]
  • Face to Face and One Face Reflected in Many Mirrors
    Irina Kolbutova Moscow [email protected] FACE TO FACE AND ONE FACE REFLECTED IN MANY MIRRORS In this article I would like to demonstrate how a very ancient theo- logical concept emerged unexpectedly through the mediation of the Platonic tradition almost simultaneously in the twelfth-century Latin West and in a remote oriental context, and how these two later devel- opments of the same set of ideas can clarify each other and their com- mon roots. At the outset it is worth making some observations concerning the use of the early Christian writings in this study, which scholars of the previous generations almost indiscriminately called “gnostic” thus us- ing the term by which, as was noted by A. DeConick, they att empted to reconstruct “an umbrella religion called ‘Gnosticism,’ a religion which in fact did not exist.”1 Furthermore, as R. G. Hall indicated, “the terms ‘Jewish,’ ‘Christian,’ and ‘gnostic’ are notoriously slippery when ap- plied to texts from early in the second century. The Odes of Solomon, with their close relationship to the Hodayot from Qumran, on the one hand, and to later gnostic literature, on the other, would belong equal- ly in studies of ancient Jewish hymnody, early Christian prophecy, and the origin of gnosticism. The Gospel of John belongs as clearly in a study of Gnostic origins as in a study of Christian origins and is Jew- ish to such an extent that one of the biggest issues it faces is being put out of the synagogue.”2 Finally, A. Golitz in highlighted the problem noting the “re-evaluation of apocalyptic literature, Christian origins, and the analysis of Gnosticism” for which scholars “had begun to look to more proximate (as opposed to distant Iranian), Jewish sources.” As this scholar observed, “we can fi nd a striking instance of this shift in the respective — and stunningly diff erent — analyses of the Acts of (1) A.
    [Show full text]
  • Assessing Porphyry's Reaction to Plotinus's Doctrine of The
    HeyJ LII (2011), pp. 1–10 DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-2265.2011.00686.x PORPHYRY THE APOSTATE: ASSESSING PORPHYRY’S REACTION TO PLOTINUS’S DOCTRINE OF THE ONE SEAMUS O’NEILL Memorial University of Newfoundland St. John’s, Canada In an article in the first volume of Harris’s Studies in Neoplatonism, Patrick Atherton described what he saw as a radical difference between the trinitarian and Neoplatonic first principles. The distinction he draws is seminal: because the first principle, or , produces all things, all that follows from it is determined by its nature. Whereas the unity of what Atherton describes as the ‘Neoplatonic One’ transcends all relation and difference, The trinitarian , by contrast, appears as an attempt to reconcile the requirement of unity with that of difference within the principle itself: is now recognised as a moment within the unity, as belonging to the principle as unity. Such a position requires a very different interpretation of the relation between the principle and its derivatives than that found in Neoplatonism.1 Recent scholarship on Porphyry, however, suggests that the important distinction Atherton adverts to is not resolvable into distinctly Neoplatonic and trinitarian camps. What Atherton describes as ‘Neoplatonism’ is more diverse, as scholars debate the subtle differences between the doctrines of Plotinus, Porphyry, Iamblichus, Augustine, and Proclus, among others. For example, John Dillon and Steven Strange have recently argued that Porphyry’s doctrine of the first principle is in fact – as Atherton describes the two positions – ‘trinitarian’ rather than ‘Neoplatonic’. Atherton’s characterization of the Neoplatonic describes more narrowly the Plotinian One, for Plotinus is the only Neoplatonist who maintains the absolute transcendence of the first principle beyond all relation and difference.
    [Show full text]
  • Naming the Principles in Democritus: an Epistemological Problem
    apeiron 2017; 50(4): 435–448 Enrico Piergiacomi* Naming the Principles in Democritus: An Epistemological Problem DOI 10.1515/apeiron-2016-0058 Abstract: It is well known that Democritus posited two principles of reality, i. e. atoms and void, and that he gave them many names. Synonyms of atom include the terms “body”, “form” and “thing” or δέν, while void was also called “space”, “infinite” and “no-thing” or μηδέν. What usually escapes the attention of scholars is the problematic outcome that this apparently plain mode of expression raises at the epistemological level. Indeed, according to Proclus (In Plat. Crat. 16 = fr. 68 B 26 DK), Democritus believed that names are not established by nature, but by convention, which may imply that they do not express the true nature of the object named. Proclus gives four proofs on his behalf, among which we find the ἰσορροπία argument. Names do not have a natural link with the objects they refer to and, therefore, do not express their inner essence, since thesamethingwillreceivedifferent designations and meanings, none of which fully expresses its real φύσις. Now, I will argue that, if we apply this idea to the principles, it follows that Democritus may have acknowledged that they are not fully comprehensible to human beings. The fact that both the atom and the void are assigned different names/meanings shows that their nature escapes human under- standing.Atthesametime,Iwillalso briefly suggest that the “ἰσορροπία argument” does not lead to skepticism. Instead, it leads to a rational dog- matism, which recognizes that atoms and void exist, are known and can be expressed through language, although no mind can fully comprehend their essence.
    [Show full text]
  • Mithras Demiourgos Diego Romagnoli
    MITHRAS DEMIOURGOS DIEGO ROMAGNOLI Summary: Roman Mithraism has been subject to philosophical interpretations and influences over the years. In this paper, I will present the important case of Mithras as a Demiurge by following the Platonic doctrine of the three Gods and its evolution, and after Plato, in three further phases. A. Plato in the Timaeus and in the dialogue The Sophist (both written in 360 BC) debated three fundamental divine figures: the Being, who accounts for the early Idea and the source of all the other ideas, as well as the early cause of the world; the Demiurge, who was born from the Being and accounts for the acting Power creating the perceivable world; the Anima Mundi (the Soul of the World or the World Soul), who was born from the other two Gods and is the “mother” shaping all of beings. B. Later, Middle Platonism (lasted from I century BC to II century AD and on which the Chaldean Oracles were based) identified the Being as the First God and the source of every indistinct idea; the Demiurge as the Second God featuring the early Idea in order to create the world; and the Anima Mundi as the unifying principle from which all of organisms are shaped. C. Finally, in Neoplatonism (lasted from III century to VI century AD and on which the Porphyry‟s De Antro Nympharum is based) this doctrine was fitted together with Mithraism: Mithras was the Demiurge and the Goddess Hecate was identified with the Anima Mundi. This paper contributes to the current state of knowledge on this topic with a full detailed analysis of the connected different phases of Platonism in order to reach the identification of Mithras as the Demiurge.
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 520 Fall 2007 Historical Background
    MATH 520 – Foundations of Geometry Historical Background The word geometry is derived from the Greek words meaning “earth measure” implying that geometry involves measuring earthly things. Ancient geometry in part has its beginnings in the practical need necessary for the agriculture of the Babylonians (modern region is southern Iraq from around Baghdad to the Persian Gulf) and Egyptians, civilizations “known for their engineering prowess in marsh drainage, irrigation, flood control, and the erection of great edifices and structures” (Eves, 1969). There is evidence from clay tablets that the Babylonians (~ 1900 BC) were familiar with Pythagorean Triples long before Pythagoras lived. 1 The Egyptians used the formula ++= dbcaA ))(( to calculate the area of an arbitrary quadrilateral with 4 successive sides a, b, c, and d. This formula proves correct for rectangles but not for quadrilaterals in general. Not until the 6th century B.C. did mathematicians begin to question whether such empirical results were always true. The contemporary study of geometry bears little resemblance to its historical beginnings in that it does not necessarily require that we measure anything or even restrict ourselves to the earth. People/Characters Thales of Miletus (ca. 640 – 546 B.C.) Greek Most often credited with initiating the formal study of demonstrative geometry as a discipline – The Father of Demonstrative Geometry; A Wise Man of Antiquity Well traveled throughout Babylonia, Egypt, and the Middle East. Thales knew the work and culture of the regions. He began to generalize and demonstrate geometric propositions by using logical reasoning to argue in favor of propositions rather than simply going with the “it works so use it” method.
    [Show full text]